281 32 7MB
English Pages 337 [352] Year 2011
Computational Music Science
Series Editors Guerino Mazzola Moreno Andreatta
For further volumes: www.springer.com/series/8349
Guerino Mazzola r Joomi Park r Florian Thalmann
Musical Creativity Strategies and Tools in Composition and Improvisation
Prof. Dr. Guerino Mazzola School of Music University of Minnesota Minneapolis, MN, USA [email protected] Department of Informatics University of Zurich Zurich, Switzerland
Dr. Joomi Park McNally Smith College of Music Saint Paul, MN, USA [email protected] Florian Thalmann School of Music University of Minnesota Minneapolis, MN, USA [email protected]
ISSN 1868-0305 e-ISSN 1868-0313 Computational Music Science ISBN 978-3-642-24516-9 e-ISBN 978-3-642-24517-6 DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 Springer Heidelberg Dordrecht London New York Library of Congress Control Number: 2011942218 ACM Classification (1998): H.5.5, J.5 © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilm or in any other way, and storage in data banks. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is permitted only under the provisions of the German Copyright Law of September 9, 1965, in its current version, and permission for use must always be obtained from Springer. Violations are liable to prosecution under the German Copyright Law. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. Printed on acid-free paper Springer is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www.springer.com)
Every act of creation is first of all an act of destruction. (Pablo Picasso)
Yes, but always with a constructive intention. (Guerino Mazzola, Joomi Park, Florian Thalmann)
Preface
Writing this book was a special challenge because we knew that creativity is a core but quite mysterious topic in music. We had many ideas about creativity in theory, and we had also been working creatively as composers, improvisers, and music software programmers. But there was one very special and demanding part of the book that we wanted to write, namely the practical tutorial. We planned to complement theoretical and other high-end perspectives with a really concrete, practical, and teachable contribution. The result of this effort is the hundred-page tutorial, Part II. It significantly precedes the theoretical Part III because we wanted to offer a presentation that works for undergraduate students or for any reader who wants to see how the theory works when you apply it, without having to go through long and annoying theoretical discourses, also called “general nonsense”1 . Writing the tutorial was in no way a replication of known material. In each unit of the tutorial, we had to break through the standards of that theme and develop creative extensions of the status quo. We are by no means claiming that our solutions are unique or even optimal ones, but we hope that they demonstrate the validity of our general method for working creatively in music theory, technology, and performance. All tutorial chapters have been written as an exchange of ideas between Joomi Park (as a composer and pianist) and Guerino Mazzola (as a scientist). Joomi’s practical and musical contributions have strongly enhanced the value of the tutorial chapters as a model for a future course syllabus, as well as the case studies and the theoretical chapters of this book. 1
“General nonsense” is a well-known qualification of utterly abstract and general mathematical theories, in particular category theory. It was a style developed in the 1970s following Alexander Grothendieck’s success in algebraic geometry, which was achieved in this style, but then used by not-so-creative mathematicians. Around 1980, this style was strongly criticized, also relating to teaching abstract set theory in elementary school.
vii
viii
Preface
This book’s approach to creativity is a bit different from others since it follows less a psychological method than a semiotically shaped procedure. Of course, psychology is extremely important in individual and collective creative dynamics. But we wanted to present a method that can be taken as a backbone for any given challenge in musical creativity and that is operational, i.e. one can start working without first having to go through psychotherapeutic warmups. And although this approach is applied to musical creativity in this book, we believe that its generic character enables you to apply it in many creative environments and problem fields. Because our approach is so specific, we felt obliged to include a short review of what has been done in creativity research in the past and present times. Florian Thalmann has been charged with this delicate subject, and we are very grateful for his diligent presentation. We hope that our present contribution may help demystify the mysterious perspective in the popular creativity discourse, moving to a relaxed understanding of the term and following Albert Einstein’s statement, “Creativity is knowing how to hide your sources.” As in the previous book of this Springer series on performance theory, Emily King has been an invaluable help in transforming our text to a valid English prose; thank you so much for your patience with non-native English. We are pleased to acknowledge the strong support for writing such a demanding treatise by Springer’s science editor Ronan Nugent. Minneapolis, August 2011
Guerino Mazzola, Joomi Park, Florian Thalmann
Contents
Part I Introduction 1
What the Book Is About . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
3
2
Oniontology: Realities, Communication, Semiotics, and Embodiment of Music . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.1 Realities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.2 Communication . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.3 Semiotics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.4 Embodiment . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.5 The Baboushka Principle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
5 6 7 7 8 9
Part II Practice 3
The Tutorial . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15
4
The General Method of Creativity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17
5
Getting Off the Ground . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
6
Motivational Aspects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
23 23 24 24 25 25 26 27 ix
x
Contents
7
Rhythmical Aspects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
29 29 30 31 33 34 34 35
8
The Pitch Aspect . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
37 37 38 38 39 42 43 45
9
The Harmonic Aspect . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
47 48 48 49 49 51 53 55
10 Melodic Aspects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
57 58 59 60 61 63 66 67
11 The Contrapuntal Aspect . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
73 74 76 77 77 77 79 82
Contents
12 Instrumental Aspects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
xi
85 85 86 87 88 88 89 90
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism 93 13.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96 13.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 97 13.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98 13.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98 13.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 100 13.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 101 13.6.1 Another Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 104 13.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 105 14 Large Form Aspects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 107 14.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109 14.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 110 14.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 110 14.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 111 14.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 112 14.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113 14.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 115 15 Community Aspects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117 15.1 What is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 118 15.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 118 15.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119 15.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120 15.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120 15.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 15.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 16 Commercial Aspects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123 16.1 What Is Your Open Question? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123 16.2 Let Us Describe the Context! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 124 16.3 Find the Critical Concept! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 124 16.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125 16.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125 16.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126 16.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126
xii
Contents
Part III Theory 17 Historical Approaches . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 131 17.1 The Concept of Creativity through (Western) History . . . . . . . . . 132 17.2 Creativity in Early Psychology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 135 17.3 Creativity Research in Recent Years . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137 18 Present Approaches . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141 18.1 The Creative Process Today . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141 18.1.1 The Four P’s of Creativity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141 18.1.2 The Creative Process . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 142 18.2 Musical Creativity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 145 19 Our Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 149 19.1 Approach to Creativity: A Semiotic Presentation . . . . . . . . . . . . . 149 19.1.1 The Open Question’s Context in Creativity . . . . . . . . . . . . 149 19.1.2 Motivation for a Semiotic Extension . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 150 19.1.3 The Critical Sign . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 151 19.1.4 Identifying a Concept’s Walls . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 152 19.1.5 Opening a Wall and Displaying Its New Perspectives . . . . 154 19.1.6 Visual Representation of the Wall Paradigm . . . . . . . . . . . 155 19.1.7 Evaluating the Extended Walls . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 157 19.2 Approach to Creativity: A Mathematical Model . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 157 19.3 The List of the Creativity Process . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 159 20 Principles of Creative Pedagogy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 161 20.1 Origins of Creative Pedagogy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 161 20.2 Applying Our Concept of Creativity to Creative Pedagogy . . . . . 163 20.3 Creative Pedagogy for Musical Creativity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 164 20.3.1 Conceiving Our Tutorial in Creative Pedagogy for Musical Creativity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 166 21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity . . . . 169 21.1 Acoustic Reality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 169 21.1.1 First Sound Anatomy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 171 21.1.2 Making Sound . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 172 21.1.3 Fourier . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 176 21.1.4 FM, Wavelets, Physical Modeling . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 180 21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW . . . . . . 185 21.2.1 General Picture of Analog/Digital Sound Encoding . . . . . 185 21.2.2 LP and Tape Technologies, Some History . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 190 21.2.3 The Digital Approach, Sampling . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191 21.2.4 Finite Fourier Analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 193 21.2.5 Fast Fourier Analysis (FFT) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 196
Contents
xiii
21.2.6 Compression . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 201 21.2.7 MP3, MP4, AIFF . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 202 21.2.8 Filters and EQ . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 209 21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 214 21.3.1 Western Notation and Performance . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 214 21.3.2 MIDI: What It Is About, Short History . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 217 21.3.3 MIDI Networks: MIDI Devices, Ports, and Cables . . . . . . 219 21.3.4 MIDI Messages: Hierarchy and Anatomy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 220 21.3.5 Time in MIDI, Standard MIDI Files . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 222 21.3.6 Short Introduction to Denotators . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 224 21.4 Creativity in Electronic Music: Languages and Theories . . . . . . . 231 22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 233 22.1 Defining Composition and Improvisation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 233 22.2 Creativity in Composition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 236 22.2.1 Composition by Objectivation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 236 22.2.2 Creativity in Composition with Symbolic Objects . . . . . . 237 22.3 Creativity in Improvisation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 239 22.3.1 Improvisational Creativity in the Imaginary Time-Space . 241 22.3.2 Improvisational Creativity with Gestural Embodiment . . 243 22.4 Instant Composition and Slow-Motion Improvisation . . . . . . . . . . 245 Part IV Case Studies 23 The CD Passionate Message . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 251 23.1 The General Background of This Production . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 251 23.1.1 The Overall Strategy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 251 23.1.2 Joomi’s Compositional Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 252 23.1.3 Guerino’s Improvisational Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 256 23.2 Softening One’s Boundaries in Creativity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258 23.2.1 Embodied Creation and the Crisis of Contemporary Composition . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 259 23.3 The Problem of Creativity in a Dense Cultural Heritage of Compositions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 262 23.3.1 First Wall: Composition, an Object? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 262 23.3.2 Second Wall: Originality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 263 24 The Escher Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 267 24.1 A Short Review of the Escher Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 267 24.1.1 Gestures and Hypergestures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 267 24.1.2 The Escher Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 270 24.2 The Escher Theorem and Creativity in Free Jazz . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273 24.3 Applying the Escher Theorem to Open Walls of Critical Concepts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 276
xiv
Contents
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 279 25.1 Boulez’s Idea of a Creative Analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 279 25.2 Ligeti’s Analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 282 25.3 A First Creative Analysis of Structure Ia from Ligeti’s Perspective . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 283 25.3.1 Address Change Instead of Parameter Transformations . . 284 25.3.2 The System of Address Changes for the Primary Parameters . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 285 25.3.3 The System of Address Changes for the Secondary Parameters . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 286 25.3.4 The First Creative Analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 288 25.4 Implementing Creative Analysis on RUBATO . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 288 25.4.1 The System of Boulettes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 290 25.5 A Second More Creative Analysis and Reconstruction . . . . . . . . . 292 25.5.1 The Conceptual Extensions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 294 25.5.2 The BigBang Rubette for Computational Composition . . 297 25.5.3 A Composition Using the BigBang Rubette and the Boulettes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 299 25.5.4 Was This “Creative Analysis” a Creative Success? . . . . . . 302 26 Ludwig van Beethoven’s Sonata opus 109: Six Variations . . . 305 26.1 Uhde’s Perspective Metaphor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 306 26.2 Why a Sixth Variation? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 307 Part V References, Index References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 313 Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 319
Part I
Introduction
1 What the Book Is About
This book is about creativity. After a short introduction (Part I), it presents its practical aspects in a tutorial (Part II), the theoretical background (Part III), and four extensive case studies (Part IV). The practical tutorial is conceived as a skeleton for a university undergraduate course syllabus. It can be taught either in a one-semester course with a straightforward strategy going through the entire tutorial, or in a two-semester course with the suggested practical exercises in each of the tutorial’s chapters. It starts with an informal presentation of the subject of creativity (the formal theory is presented in Part III). We then discuss eleven topics in tutorial units. These units all deal with fundamental themes from music theory, performance, and social as well as commercial issues. These themes are all deployed to challenge the future composer in creative extensions of known material and methods. Our treatment of these topics is by no means thought to replace the traditional standard teaching in theory or performance. The idea is to lead these students to new frontiers that transcend standard points of view. The philosophy of this plan is that music is an ever-evolving field of artistic and scientific expression, and that such extensions can be achieved by following a general process scheme of creative exploration. Our approach should make clear that creativity is not that mysterious uncontrollable phenomenon of human originality which still dominates the overall discourse on this subject. Creativity is neither divine inspiration nor random spontaneity. We hope the reader will agree on this point after having run through the tutorials’ storyboard. The theoretical part is devoted to two main threads: an overview of the history and presence of creativity theories, together with our own theoretical approach, including a presentation of creative pedagogy; and a thorough discussion of the creative potential of music technology in hardware and software as well as a comparison of creativity in composition and improvisation. Music technology is included because we believe that any serious endeavor in new music must take care of the hard facts of embodiment. Music is not only a G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 1, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
3
4
1 What the Book Is About
matter of thoughts and emotions; it relies on the physical environment where sounds are produced and where instrumental interfaces are designed. Part IV, case studies, is a spectrum of four topics where creativity plays a crucial role. Our selection includes (1) a discussion of creativity in a recent CD production, involving authors Joomi Park and Guerino Mazzola; (2) the analysis of a systematic procedure, the Escher Theorem, for realizing creative extensions; (3) a technology-oriented discourse of a software that enables a recomposition of Pierre Boulez’s Structures pour deux pianos; (4) an interpretation of Ludwig van Beethoven’s six variations in the third movement of piano sonata op. 109 as a creative achievement in sonata theory. We hope that our threefold perspective (Parts II, III, IV) on creativity will inspire students, instructors, and researchers to think in new ways about what creativity is about.
2 Oniontology: Realities, Communication, Semiotics, and Embodiment of Music
Before we embark on the detailed investigation of musical creativity, we should ask about the localization of such creation: Where are those works which composers and improvisers are generating? And also: Where are the generative processes and gestures located, and is there an option to view all these objects and activities in a big existential topography? To answer this complex questionnaire, we want to prepend the technically detailed discussion with a complete picture of musical existentiality: where music exists and how it comes into being. Musical ontology is precisely the philosophy and field of knowledge that deals with these questions. This approach will give us the necessary conceptual architecture to unfold a presentation of the subject that comprises all relevant perspectives and that enables us to interconnect them in the framework of a unified understanding of music. We shall now describe the general setup of musical ontology. Although general musical ontology has been described in a concise way in [85], in [82], and in [89], we want to recapitulate it here for the sake of a self-contained text, and also to stress certain aspects to be more adapted to the topic of creativity. Let us start with what we have coined musical oniontology. It is the classical musical ontology that was introduced in [72], comprising the dimensions of realities, communication, and semiotics, but now enriched by a fourth dimension, embodiment. Since this fourth dimension splits into three layers, the classical ontology is given a triple-layered structure, hence the somewhat fancy name of an “oniontology” (see Figure 2.5). This oniontology presents a topographic landscape of musical ontology: It is a geographic display of localities determined by coordinates as specified from the four dimensions of ontology. In other words, musical oniontology is a conceptual space on which phenomena of musical existence are distributed. This spatial display enables us to understand creativity as a dynamic process that retrieves its contextual data from the oniontological landscape. So let us present all the dimensions of musical oniontology.
G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 2, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
5
6
Oniontology: Realities, Communication, Semiotics, Embodiment of Music
2.1 Realities
Fig. 2.1. The three fundamental realities of music.
This dimension describes the three fundamental values of reality involved in music: physical reality, psychological reality, and mental or symbolic reality (see Figure 2.1). So, acoustical phenomena relate to physics, emotional effects to psychology, and symbolic structures, e.g. mathematical descriptions in music theory, to the mental reality. Observe that the mental reality is not conceived as being a part of the psychological one, since mathematical reality (for example) is independent of our human psyche. Differentiation of realities is crucial for avoiding widespread misunderstandings about the nature of musical facts. For example, the retrograde of a melody is a clear mathematical fact in the mental reality, but its reality in the psychological understanding of a listener is mostly inexistent: You probably cannot recognize the retrograde of a melody when hearing it.1 Methodologically, there is no reason nor is it ontologically possible to reduce one reality to others. For example, it is a logically vicious circle to try to reduce mental reality to physical reality, as happens in fashionable neuroscience. In fact, explaining mathematical thoughts by neuroscience would mean describing them by chemical and physical processes. But their description would enforce quantum mechanics of chemistry and other basic theories of physical processes. Such descriptions, however, would be based on the complex mathematics of quantum mechanics and therefore generate a vicious circle: explaining maths by maths. 1
A more complex example of this problem is Fourier’s theorem, roughly stating that every periodic function is a unique sum of sinusoidal components, but see section 21.1.3 for a precise discussion. Its a priori status is a mental one, a theorem of pure mathematics. In musical acoustics, it is often claimed that—according to Fourier’s theorem—a sound “is” composed of “pure” sinusoidal partials. However, there is no physical law to support this claim. Without a specific link to physics, Fourier’s statement is just one of an infinity of mathematically equivalent orthonormal decompositions based on “pure” functions of completely general character. To give the claim a physical status, it would be necessary to refer to a concrete dynamical system, such as the cochlea of the inner ear, which is physically sensitive to the first seven partials in Fourier’s sense.
2.3 Semiotics
7
The problem is rather to describe the transformation rules from the manifestation of a phenomenon in one reality to its correspondences within the others. To be clear, a neurophysiological transformation (“explanation”) of a psychological phenomenon does not, however, conserve the psychological ontology of the phenomenon. The specific phenomenon within the psychological realm corresponds to another phenomenon within the physiological realm. But ontologically, the phenomena do not collapse.
2.2 Communication
Fig. 2.2. The three stages of communication in music.
Following the famous scheme of Jean Molino and Paul Val´ery [72], music deals with communication from the first value, the poietic position of the composer or creator, to the creator’s work, which is the material essence and output of the second value, called neutral level by Molino (see Figure 2.2). Communication, as encoded in the work, targets the third value: the aesthesic position of the listener, the addressee of the composer’s message. Val´ery coined the word “aesthesic” to differentiate it from the aesthetic understanding. Aesthesis means perception and can be acoustical, psychological, or analytical, and it needs not relate to aesthetical evaluation. The aesthesic instance could even be computer software that takes a MIDI file as input and processes an analytical task thereof.
2.3 Semiotics This axis (Figure 2.3) comprises all sign-theoretic aspects of music. It is articulated in the three classical constituents of a sign: expression, content, and signification. Expression, the first value on this axis, relates to the surface of a sign, something that stands for the sign’s meaning or content. The latter, content, is the second value—the “aliquo” in the classical definition “aliquid stat pro aliquo” (“something stands for something else”) of a sign. The third value is the signification part of a sign. It refers to the middle word “stat pro” of the
8
Oniontology: Realities, Communication, Semiotics, Embodiment of Music
Fig. 2.3. The three positions in musical semiotics.
classical definition and explains the way or process engaged for the transfer of the surface value of expression to the “hidden” value of content. For example, when reading the musical expression for a fermata, the reader must invoke a complex machinery to understand the expression, i.e. produce the symbol’s content. In a semiotic system, there are three main structural aspects: The pointer from expression to content is called semantics; the connection between different signs, such as is built in sentences of a language, is called syntagm; and the mechanisms of signification applied by the user of the semiotics is called pragmatics. The classical three-dimensional cube of musical topography is shown in Figure 2.4.
2.4 Embodiment The very making of art is a level that is not articulated in that threedimensional cube of musical ontology. Not one of its twenty-seven (3 × 3 × 3) positions grasps the gestural aspect of making art (and science). The cube, strictly speaking, only deals with the ontology of facts, of “what is the case” in Ludwig Wittgenstein’s sense [127]. It does not include the processual level of ontology. Formally speaking, processes are the diagrams of spaces and transformations that describe the interaction of components of a complex system. We have to differentiate between processes and their products, the output of pro-
2.5 The Baboushka Principle
9
Fig. 2.4. The classical three-dimensional cube of musical ontology.
cessual dynamics. Processes are a kind of factory for facts, but not the facts themselves. The processual level is fundamentally different from its output products. Processes and facts are instances of different ontologies. Going still farther in the initiated direction, processes are also an abstraction from a more basic layer—namely, the gestural layer—where all processes and their facts are initiated. Processes are disembodied gestures, reduced to their referential system of transformations. This means that a new dimension must be added to the cube of musical ontology. This fourth dimension is called dimension of embodiment. Its three values are: facts, processes, and gestures. They deal with, respectively, these activities: “what is the case,” “to refer to,” and “to make.” In this scheme, the transition from gesture to process is dominated by disembodiment and schematization, whereas the transition from process to facts is dominated by evaluation and dissection (from the relating transformations). Together with the previous three-dimensional cube of ontology, this fourth dimension creates a four-dimensional cube, which we call the hypercube of musical oniontology. It takes the form of a three-layered onion of gestural, processual, and factual levels of ontology, as shown in Figure 2.5.
2.5 The Baboushka Principle The above dimensions do not mean that musical ontology is indecomposably inscripted in such coordinates. It mostly happens that the 3 × 3 × 3 × 3 coordinates are themselves encapsulated subsystems of the same nature. This
10
Oniontology: Realities, Communication, Semiotics, Embodiment of Music
Fig. 2.5. The hypercube of musical oniontology defined by the fourth dimension of embodiment. The graphics illustrate facts (the M¨ obius strip as a configuration of tonal degrees), processes (a diagram from Lewin’s transformational theory), and gestures (a model of the pianist’s hand).
reiteration of the hypercube’s structure is called the Baboushka principle. It does not mean that new dimensions are generated, but that each position in the hypercube can recursively be the compact representation of still a finer hypercube of the same type. Let us make this clear on the two examples of semiotics and communication. In the semiotic dimension, it is a classical result from Louis Hjelmslev’s investigations [52] that the expressive surface of a semiotic system may be a semiotic system in its own. This is the case, for example, in so-called double articulation in language. Here, the words—expressions of the language sign system—are also signs with a graphical expression—the written level of alphabetization—that signifies its acoustical content. This level or semiotic ramification within the expressive level of the top system is called connotation. If, on the other end, the content level is itself a semiotic system, the comprising system is called a metasystem. And if the middle layer of signification is a semiotic system, the comprising system is called a motivated semiotics. It can be shown that music is built from a repeated imbrication of connotative subsystems [76, 77].
2.5 The Baboushka Principle
11
In the dimension of musical communication, the overall poietic position may be seen (and this was our example above) as articulated in composer, work (score), and interpreter, whereas this entire communicative unit is the poiesis that generates the neutral level of a performed work (on the acoustical level, say, when the performance is taking place in a concert), which in turn reaches the aesthesic level of the audience. We leave it to the reader to imagine such Baboushka configurations for the dimensions of realities or embodiment. Hint: Think of the physical reality of a symbol, the symbolic representation of a physical sound, the facticity of a gesture, or the processual scheme underlying a gestural utterance, etc.
Part II
Practice
3 The Tutorial
This book has two parts, a first practical one, and a second theoretical one. We have decided to prepend the practical part because we believe it is possible and also our obligation to the students and instructors to access creativity without having to go through heavy theories. Those who want to learn about more theoretical topics will find a lot of theory and case studies in the theoretical part. The practical part is essentially a tutorial in creative pedagogy of music. In chapter 20 we give an in-depth definition and discussion of what is creative pedagogy in general, and what we add to the general approach in this book. For the present practical aspect, let us just say that creative pedagogy is a pedagogical method to teach whatever field of knowledge or art by letting the student experience learning as a creative activity. So we do not teach creativity, but via creativity. However, in our special field of music, we will teach not only via creativity, but also the specific creativity in musical composition. We believe that this double presence of creativity will give the student an excellent education, which should free him/her from that mysticism that usually radiates from the word “creativity,” a mysticism that immediately refers us to those great geniuses of music Bach, Mozart, Beethoven, Schumann, Liszt, Schoenberg, Berg, Webern, Scriabin, Bartok, and so on, and that paralyzes our own power of invention instead of boosting it. We do not claim that creativity is a mechanical competence you can learn like you can learn to solve linear equations, but we claim that this tutorial and the backing theory can eliminate a good number of wrong obstructions of psychological and methodological natures. This tutorial is conceived to be used as a skeleton of a syllabus for a university course in musical creativity at a school of music. It is structured in eleven units—each of which could be covered in a week over three hours— which deal with specific aspects of musical creativity. Our choice is by no means unique, but it is a prototypical setup that could, of course, be shaped differently according to the weights chosen by the instructors. Here are our eleven aspects: G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 3, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
15
16
1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11.
3 The Tutorial
Motivational Aspects, chapter 6 Rhythmical Aspects, chapter 7 The Pitch Aspect, chapter 8 The Harmonic Aspect, chapter 9 Melodic Aspects, chapter 10 The Contrapuntal Aspect, chapter 11 Instrumental Aspects, chapter 12 System Aspects, chapter 13 Large Form Aspects, chapter 14 Community Aspects, chapter 15 Commercial Aspects, chapter 16
These units are not independent of one another. For example, the harmonic aspect unit presupposes the pitch aspect. The overall image of dependence is known as “leitfaden” and is depicted in Figure 3.1 below. The leitfaden enables different flow paths through the total material if preferences vary.
Fig. 3.1. The tutorial’s leitfaden.
4 The General Method of Creativity
While we give a theoretically founded presentation of creativity, its history, present trends, and our own approach in chapters 17, 18, and 19, we want to describe here the essentials of our approach to creativity in practical terms to be used in the tutorial. Our approach to creativity is not a psychological trick nor does it incite a state of ecstasy, possibly boosted by drugs and similar devices. It is a process of discovery and invention that begins with an open question and continues with a run through a sequence of well-defined operational steps. It might not be successful in finding a solution to the question, but we can start over and repeat the processual run until we find a solution. Creativity cannot be guaranteed, but there are good reasons for approaching it based upon a clear strategy. Again, we discuss many examples of successful creativity in the theory part and hope that the reader will accept our approach here as a basis for our practical work. The process of creativity is composed of the following steps: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6.
Exhibiting the open question Identifying the semiotic context Finding the question’s critical sign or concept in the semiotic context Identifying the concept’s walls Opening the walls and displaying its new perspectives Evaluating the extended walls
Let us briefly describe them, together with a simple example: the invention of 3M’s Post-It (see Figure 4.1). Step 1, exhibiting an open question. Creativity should start with the will to find something new that will answer an open question. It has a target. Example: In 1968, Dr. Spencer Silver, a chemist at Minnesota’s 3M company, developed an adhesive that did not really glue. He did not know what to do with it. What would be the usage of such a substance? Step 2 consists of identifying the context of this question. This is a natural requirement: We want to know what is the overall position of the question, since G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 4, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
17
18
4 The General Method of Creativity
for one individual the question might be open but trivial, while for another it might be a big challenge. Also, we stress that the context is a semiotic one. What does this mean? It means that the context should be one of things, thoughts, and signs that mean something. The open question then would be one that creates new contents when answered. It would extend the given meaningful context. So creation in our understanding is about creating new contents, not just forms. Example: The context is the chemical industry. Including a variety of more than 50,000 3M products. Step 3 is the moment of focusing on a specific location in the context, a critical concept or thing where we guess that the open question could be made more precise. Example: The critical concept here was “adFig. 4.1. The Post-It notes. hesive.” Dr. Silver had invented an adhesive that was critical—it did not glue as required, but only “half of it.” Step 4 is very important. It asks us to identify the concept’s walls. Walls are a metaphor for properties, characteristics, and specificities of the concept that circumscribe the concept in a more or less explicit form. It is a delicate task here, since some properties might be so subtle that one is barely capable of recognizing them. Example: The walls of the concept “adhesive” was that one would expect that an adhesive has to glue, meaning 100 percent not just somewhat. It was a wall because it was so evident that an adhesive had to glue, by its very definition! Step 5 asks us to consider these walls and to try to ‘soften’ and to ‘open’ them. This means that we ask to what extent these walls are necessary for the critical concept, and whether we could possibly find ways to open them and to recognize new perspectives on the other side of the given walls. Example: The softening of the “glue” wall meant that one had to put into question this strong requirement of 100 percent gluing. It was Arthur Fry, who attended one of Silver’s seminars, who successfully opened that wall. He sang in a church choir and was frustrated with the paper bookmarks he used to mark the songs in his hymnal because they would not stay put. Fry realized that Silver’s adhesive met exactly his needs. Step 6 is the terminal step. It consists of the evaluation of wall extensions we may have found in step 5, and then the judgment of this evaluation’s result. Is it a successful extension of the original critical concept or didn’t we find an answer to the open question? If we are successful, everything is OK; otherwise, we have to go back to step 4 and find new walls and new extensions, or even to step 3 and look for new critical concepts. Example: In 1980 Post-It Notes were introduced nationwide in the U.S. and soon became a big success.
4 The General Method of Creativity
19
Remark 1 It is, of course, easy to give an example of a creative strategy that very probably would not be successful. Suppose that an open question in number theory is given. The critical concept could be “number.” And the wall one could discover could be “the number’s color” when you write it down on paper, on a blackboard, or on a computer screen. You could have the ‘ingenious’ idea that the number’s color could be extended from the usual black, blue, or red to any fancy color. But it is quite clear that such an extension would not solve the original number-theoretical question. Remark 2 We should not conclude this informal introduction to our creativity process scheme without pointing out the deep impact of representing ideas and methods in a sensual way (touch, smell, taste, hearing, sight). We have already established the sight- and touch-oriented metaphor of a wall described in steps 4, 5, and 6. When unfolding creative processes, we should always embed our activity in an object-oriented environment, where we feel at home and comfortable. Humans cannot think in abstract categories without using sensual metaphors. Even the most abstract mathematical thoughts are always embodied in objects that can be manipulated by human gestures. This is one of the secrets of successful mathematicians. Einstein, for example, admitted that his thoughts were always performed with an intense chewing activity. He was literally chewing ideas! Last but not least, we should be aware that probably the most creative force is love for life. After all, this is the strongest motor of human propagation. For a successful creation, the atmosphere should be a warm and loving one1 ; creation out of hate or indifference is never for life. A creation is a mental baby; it needs a ‘mother’ and her carrying body.
1
Sidney Lanier says, “Music is love in search of a word.”
5 Getting Off the Ground
The following tutorial is not a full-fledged syllabus, but it should give you, as a student or as an instructor, enough information to complete such a syllabus and to run through a course in creative musical composition applying creative pedagogy. For convenience, in the tutorial, we use the term “composition” to represent both, composition and improvisation. If we review the tutorial’s topics, one might have the impression that this course replaces music theory courses, counterpoint, etc., but this is not the aim of the tutorial. It is more a fresh look at the fundamental target of creativity in music, using this special type of pedagogy. We could imagine giving such a course to freshmen or sophomores. But as a course in composition, it would also be an ideal educational contribution. Why? Because composition, and musical creativity in general, is not viewed as comprising theoretical fields, too. Theory is given, and might or might not be used in composition, but to include theory in one’s compositional creativity is not standard, although making music should not halt in front of theory. We have strong evidence that musical laws are not yet in their final state; musical evolution is still in its Planck time (that very short initial time after the Big Bang when the natural laws were not defined yet). This tutorial, therefore, is a trajectory through music as a creation that the composer realizes with full responsibility—not just taking gadgets from the shelf, not doing just anything, but creating in a thoroughly constructive way. It might also seem that the trajectory through this tutorial starts with a huge spectrum of freedom and chaos, and then successively restricts one’s freedom by the variety of structural castings. This is only appearance. Creativity is not the limitless extension and chaos and destruction of limits; it is an evolutionary process that builds up spiritual cathedrals, much as biology has its most sophisticated creations in a very limited environment on a very special planet and for a very short time, presumably. In our tutorial, we shall always suppose that a ‘model student’ is taking the course and therefore also suppose that his/her achievements in the previous G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 5, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
21
22
5 Getting Off the Ground
lessons could be used in later lessons. This creates a natural coherence in the pedagogical development. We also might suppose that our model student has some preliminary knowledge in musical notation or even might know how to play an instrument.
6 Motivational Aspects
This is the very beginning of our tutorial. In this initial unit, we want to approach creatively the very motivation you, the student1 , may discover and set up for the entire study lying ahead: more precisely, for the will to compose music. This is a very general situation, as motivations to compose music may stem from very different areas of human engagement. And the student might also envisage very different musical styles he/she wants to compose: classical, contemporary Western music, jazz, pop, rap, world musics, etc. Or the student just has a certain sound in his/her ears without any stylistic specification. Further, it is very important to also discuss the psychological motivations backing the student’s decision. This is a wide and complex field, but the instructor should also give it a chance in this first tutorial unit. The student we shall present here makes a specific choice for his/her motivation. But we encourage the instructor of a real course to group motivational directions of the students and to develop all of these threads in the creative process.
6.1 What Is Your Open Question? You have chosen to want to compose music. To be a creator of musical works. That’s why you are a student in this course. Beautiful! Let us first listen to different genres of music you might want to compose and then discuss your ideas on the styles you want to compose: classical Western music (Mozart, Beethoven), contemporary Western art music (Schoenberg, Nono, Stockhausen), classical jazz (Ellington, Parker), modern jazz (Davis, Coltrane, Taylor), rock ’n Roll (Preseley), pop (Michael Jackson), rock (Alanis 1
We shall henceforth always use this classical pedagogical form of a fictitious dialog with a student.
G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 6, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
23
24
6 Motivational Aspects
Morissette), hip-hop (Meshell Ndegeocello), rap (Public Enemy), world music (Don Cherry), etc. Let us now also discuss what and why you want to compose. Exercise 1 Tell us (in your own words) the music style in which you would like to compose. It does not have to be precise, but it is important that you actively choose or even create this style. Exercise 2 Tell us your emotional, social, artistic, or economic reasons for wanting to compose. Let us know about your open questions! We now want to follow your open question and show how the creativity process may help solve it. Your question when becoming a composer is about the chance to compose new music. This is what you want to achieve. So let us first envisage your unanswered question: Why should you be motivated to create new, unheard musical works?
6.2 Let Us Describe the Context! There is nothing more important than the context where this initial question must be positioned. After all, you are not alone on Earth, and it is a big burden to want to compose in a culture where so many great (and not so great) works have already been written and performed. It is also important to think about for whom you want to compose, and for which communication, media, style, etc. Let us know your understanding of the context. We will suppose here that for you the context is the entire society, with its history, cultural diversity, music media, and technology.
6.3 Find the Critical Concept! What is the critical concept on which the question of your motivation would focus in the broad context you have just defined? You seem to be concerned with the problem of wanting to compose new works in a context that first of all gives you the impression that everything has already been said, or at least said in a way that nobody could outperform. Who can write more beautifully than Mozart, who can swing better than Count Basie, who can play the piano more energetically than Cecil Taylor, who can write more divine structures than Bach, who can invent more substantially than Beethoven? And so on. Also let us listen to some of the music you have in mind, music that impresses you a lot or music that you would never want to compose.
6.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls!
25
So, what is the critical concept here? Let us guess that you choose create new music, and let us specify for the experts that you write “new” and “music” with lowercase letters, not uppercase letters, which would be the name of a very special movement in composition that took place in the first half of the twentieth century. So this is what you are concerned with: writing new music in a context where everything seems to be there already, or at least essentially.
6.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! We now want to discuss the critical concept’s walls! What is the concept’s limitation in your chosen context? The strongest wall is that ominous attribute new. You have to make something new in the context of a world of already created works. Is new music still possible? This is how you judge your situation: You are a young student of composition and you stand in front of a big wall asking to create really new music. At first, you feel like this is an impossible attribute; how can new music be created at all? Your critical concept looks like an impossible task. A second wall is connected to this first one: creation. How can you make such new music? Do you have to invent it or can you possibly find it in an eternal repertory as it is described for the great composers, who are inspired by a divine message and who do not essentially make new music by their own action? So let us investigate the meaning of “new” and the role of the associated “creative” action.
6.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! Let us first attack the question of novelty. Is new music still possible? Look at all the scores that have been written in Western notation. Think about how many signs for notes, pauses, bar lines, etc., you have in such a score. Without going into combinatorial details, you will find out that almost all potential scores that can be written have not been composed yet, when you are using a given huge number of such signs and limiting the signs to be contained in reasonable value containers. So it is not true that no new music is possible, at least when speaking about the score form. In other words, all potential scores are already given in an abstract mathematical sky—you only have to find the good ones. This opens two problematic threads: First, if this were the point of novelty, Beethoven would not have created new music but just found it in an eternal repertory. Second, the first wall would throw you back to the second wall: Creation is not possible, so it is only about inspiration, finding music in a huge combinatorial repertory. But then, what is your chance to share this inspiration?
26
6 Motivational Aspects
Do you have any chance to be connected to those divine resources of ingenious inspiration? These are the walls in their seemingly impenetrable rigidity. Creating new music appears as the perfect illusion that offers no vital motivation for becoming a composer. In the Middle Ages, it was in fact believed that no creation by humans was possible, and all music came from God. The solution against this apparent impenetrability is to become aware of what it means to create a composition. It is certainly not about creating new combinations of score signs, but about the meaning, which is added to the given understanding of music. It is similar to the writing of a poetic text. The combinatorial question is also clear: Every possible reasonable text is already contained in a mathematical sky of combinations of letters and spaces. But what we add is not this formal level of letter conglomerates; you add your own meaning to given semiotic contexts. Don’t try only to compose unheard sounds. Einstein’s energy formula E = mc2 is a simple combination of letters, but its meaning is revolutionary, and this one cannot be reduced to letter combinations. In music, even the empty score can be an example of new music. John Cage’s famous composition 4′ 33′′ , composed in 1952, is an empty score and its only specification is the duration of 4 minutes and 33 seconds. But its meaning is a novelty: It puts into question the score form as such. Is the score form already music? Is it the sounds that happen during the performance of 4′ 33′′ that define its music? Is the score music, as much as an empty canvas is painting? To put it into simple words, the softening of these walls consists of questioning the meaning of music that you may create. You do not create scores, but the meaning of scores. So let us follow this thread and see what could be added to extend these opened walls.
6.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? But what is the direction of our opening gesture? Is it about the score signs only? We have learned that it is about extending the meaning of a combination of signs. The score is such a combination, but if we think about the general situation, it means that you may think of adding meaning to any formal sign combination in the music you encounter, and, more generally speaking, to any explicitly determined formal system of musical entities. Does this make sense? Exercise 3 Think of all the constraints you have when composing music: It is not only about the score signs, but also about the rules that are applied when setting the score signs. It is about counterpoint, harmony, any kind of music theory, and it is about the use of instruments, which are also rigid machines for sound production according to well-defined rules of usage. Also think about
6.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
27
your personal psychological or social constraints when composing. Perhaps you would never compose without getting less than $ 1 million. . . What we learn here is that the extension of our walls could lead you to question any fixed system of formal objects and rules, to think about extension of meanings, of signification, the making of music as a meaningful human activity.
6.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension So, suppose now that you have discovered what kind of musical composition you are aiming at, given your personal situation. You have just developed an extension of the walls of novelty and creation in music by the dimension of meaning and by the requirement of added contents. This is a good direction: It opens novelty to a potentially infinitely deepening of meaningful music, and it also dispenses you from waiting for divine inspiration. It is now your own responsibility to add new contents, and to explore how musical works may become meaningful to our society and with respect to the works which your predecessors have composed. So let us see how strongly you can deepen musical meaning in the following topics. Try to always question given meanings, given forms, and given standard procedures.
7 Rhythmical Aspects
We now suppose that you found your motivation to delve into the art and business of inventing music. Let us stress that we are not presupposing any given musical system of rules, instruments, or musicians. We want to see how music can be created from scratch, from the chaotic universe of sound and its possible generators. You are totally free to start this enterprise, but you want to create music, and we want therefore to investigate the basic realities of music. The first of these realities is time. Time is a mysterious thing. Saint Augustine once stated that he knew what time was, but when asked about time, could not define it. So let us get started with that fascinating phenomenon of time.
7.1 What Is Your Open Question? Let us first listen to some examples of music and focus on the music’s time structures. Suggested examples: Bach: Well-tempered Piano, Beethoven: Appassionata, Scriabin: Vers la flamme, Ligeti: Po`eme Symphonique for 100 metronomes, Japan’s traditioal Nˆ oh Music, Coltrane: Meditations, Taylor: Live in the Black Forest. You will observe that there are so many different ways to deal with time in music. Exercise 4 Please describe (in your own words, no music theory needed!) the different variants of time in the music that we have just listened to. You become aware that music unfolds in time, but it also creates time, it is an art of time. It strongly matters how time is shaped in music. It is similar to painting, which is an art of space; the canvas is given, but the painter has to make the artistic space when shaping the canvas with brush and paints. You (the model student in our tutorial) therefore come up with the big open question: G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 7, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
29
30
7 Rhythmical Aspects
How can we shape the body of time? And what kind of time is this? Is it given—do we just fill in our notes in a given timeline—or do we make it, and how?
7.2 Let Us Describe the Context! What is the context of your open question? We think about shaping time in music. So the context is anything that relates to time in music. Let us name those time-related concepts that come to mind. Tempo: This relates to the speed with which you produce sound events. In music, there are classical names for different tempi, such as largo, andante, moderato, allegro, presto, etc. But tempo is not the critical concept we are looking for, because it just tells us how fast the shaping of time is performed. Beat: The beat is a basic regular pulse in a music piece, and it is usually perceived by musical events being played louder. Beat is also played at a certain tempo, so it helps shape time at an elementary level, but it is totally regular and cannot claim to be the critical concept. It is only auxiliary like tempo. Groove: This is a feeling mainly created by rhythm sections (bass, drums, guitar, keyboards). It is akin to beat because it also refers to regularly played material. But it is very subjective and might be too complex, too ‘critical,’ to give us the critical concept. Also, there are many music styles where there is no groove, and the shaping of time is very strong, like Nˆ oh music. Duration: This refers to how long a sound lasts. Of course this is important, but it is far from central. Conduct an experiment: Play a melody with its notes having normally set durations, and then play it with all durations being very short (staccato). You will still recognize the melody, although it sounds strange. So there is something more essential than duration when shaping time. Observe that when you look at a Western score, durations are given by the notes’ heads and a number of flags for short notes. The upper half of Figure 7.1 shows notes of different durations. And also note that the written duration in the score is not the real duration, in seconds, say. This one is only defined if we know at which tempo the piece is played. The metronome, invented by Johann Nepomuk M¨ alzel in 1815, is the machine that gives us the tempo with its clicks of variable speed. Pause: In music, we do not only have events, but also eventless moments, moments when you should not play anything and you should do this for a certain duration. Pauses are precisely the symbols invented to prevent a musician from playing sounds. One might at first be astonished to think of pauses as being positive structures in music, but if we think about time being also shaped when nothing sounds, this is not miraculous anymore: Silence is a positive musical quality. The lower half of Figure 7.1 shows pauses of different durations. Time Signature: When musical scores organize time, they use the socalled time signature. This means that we divide time into units of the same
7.3 Find the Critical Concept!
31
Fig. 7.1. Notes and pauses of different durations in Western score writing. The durations are, from left: 1, 1/2, 1/4, 1/8, 1/16, 1/32, 1/64. It is wrong to think of durations as multiples of certain beats, such as the whole note being composed of four beats. Durations and beats are totally independent concepts.
duration, such as 2/4, 3/4, 4/4, 6/8, and so on, and each of these units is delimited by barlines and defines a measure. So in signature 3/4, the measure has duration 3/4, i.e. three quarter-note durations. But it is more than that: The numerator also tells us into how many beats the measure is divided and which note carries the beat. So, there are three beats in 3/4, but six beats in 6/8. Although the duration of one measure is the same (3/4 = 6/8), the beat of the music is different. Gesture: In music, when we view it as related to dance and to body movements of performing musicians, gestures play an important role in the shaping of time. Gestures are, however, very complex and difficult to describe in precise terms. Like groove, they might be ‘too critical’ as a concept to get off the ground with shaping time in music. All these concepts define the context of time-related phenomena in music. Some are more symbolic and relate to scores, some are more physical and relate to the real time in performed music. But you will agree that all of them are somehow special, secondary, or even too critical to get off ground with our basic understanding of time in music.
7.3 Find the Critical Concept! There is still one concept that we have not named but is well known in timecritical discussion of music, and this is rhythm. Rhythm shapes time by definition via a collection of time events, each having a determined duration and being played at a constant or variable tempo. The other sound parameters, such as pitch or loudness, are not our concern here. Let us look at a typical rhythm in Figure 7.2. The figure shows the fanfare in the first measures of Beethoven’s op. 106, the famous Hammerklavier sonata. In the upper half we see the score, in the lower half we see the corresponding rhythm. We have eight notes, a first group of four (the red points) and a second group of four
32
7 Rhythmical Aspects
Fig. 7.2. Above: The fanfare in Beethoven’s Hammerklavier Sonata, op. 106, the beginning of first movement (Allegro). Below: The onset times and durations of the fanfare notes in multiples of 1/8.
(the green points). The collection of eight time events is shown in the lower half of the figure time unit is 1/8. The first note has duration 1/8, the second has duration 3/8, the third one again duration 1/8, the fourth one duration 2/8, the fifth and sixth one have duration 1/8, the seventh and eighth have duration 2/8. This rhythm is not only a collection of time events, but also shares a characteristic internal shape, namely that the first and second pair of events are each movements from short to longer notes, they are some kind of repeated slowing down. The second four-note group relates to the first in that it now is not a repetition of slowing down, but a slowing down of a repetition: Eighth notes are repeated and then their repetition is slowed down and we see a repetition of quarter notes. Beethoven’s tempo prescription (138 1/2 notes per minute) of this fanfare is quite fast, so we are hearing an energetic shape of time as an initial stamp given to this famous sonata. Rhythm has what psychologists call a “gestalt,” a shape; it is a collection of time events with a significant internal structures. Exercise 5 Look at other rhythms in music and try to describe them by onset and duration of their notes. Try also to play rhythms and if possible to notate them, even in your private notation.
7.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls!
33
So the open question is strongly connected to the question of how we may shape musical time (onsets and durations of notes and pauses) in rhythmical structures.
7.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! Exercise 6 Write down some rhythms you imagine in your own notation. Then try to normalize them according to time signatures on a score. What is the experience with time signature? Exercise 7 Now, do the converse: Give yourself a time signature and then write down your rhythms within this time signature on a score. Try out some not so common time signatures, such as 5/4 or 7/8. What is its effect on your possibilities? Does it help you or restrict your efforts? We see that first of all time signature is a wall: It helps normalize rhythms and could inspire your rhythmical ideas, but it might also imprison you into an artificial time frame. A second type of wall is the role of pauses. At first whern you’re writing, the pauses are just written to organize the notes’ onsets. If you want to have a second note not come immediately after the first, you may write a pause to indicate how much later the second note must be played. The Beethoven fanfare shows this technique in the upper staff, where the first chord must wait 3/8 after the barline (pauses 1/4 + 1/8 = 3/8 before the chord). Exercise 8 Write down some rhythms with pauses and try to feel that silence is also an important musical event. Why are pauses a wall? You feel after these exercises that what is not played is not just the absence of rhythm, but suggests a whole universe of what could have been played in the pause. Remark 3 Overuse of the pedal frequently happens to amateur keyboard players. It is a method that in gastronomy is known as covering the main ingredients with a thick sauce to give the recipe body and substance. In reality, it destroys the substantial flavor and also the possibly bad quality of the cooking. In music, this might be caused because they rely on the covering pedal effect, as they are afraid of silence and are insensitive to the body of time of a performed sound. The third wall for rhythms relates to who is shaping time. This looks like a subtlety. But when composing music, and then performing it in a creative way, we must make sure that the responsibility is clearly taken by those who make the music. When looking at the first wall, time signature, it may happen
34
7 Rhythmical Aspects
that you feel that time is already there, and you just have to fill the slots. And also with pauses: They look like empty space, dead silence. This is the subtle third wall: The normalization of music notation on scores (on paper or in computerized representations) suggests that you are just a servant of an already given time out there, like in Newtonian physics, where we all had to follow the one and only divine time. But creative composition and performance would be paralyzed by such a passive role in artistic expression. Music is not a set of divine laws; we have to make it from its first fundamental moment on.
7.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! In order to soften these three walls, complete this series of exercises: Exercise 9 Take a rhythm written in a given time signature. Now forget the time signature and just play the rhythm. Try to develop it without any reference to the time signature. Do you feel that wall now? Exercise 10 Now try to play enriched rhythms using the pauses in our previous rhythms. Investigate the richness of the possibilities not being played in your previous pauses. Also try to vary the tempo of your rhythm and find out what this changes in the enrichment of the rhythm’s pauses. Exercise 11 To open the third wall, the passivity toward a given ‘divine’ time, play one of your rhythms and sing with it. Then stop and wait, do not follow any given external framework. Decide spontaneously, or just following your feeling about when to play. Do not count; try to make time into something that’s only there because you’re playing and making effort on your instrument. Remark 4 The system of time signatures is what you choose and utilize. But the time signature should not cast your composition. It might come after having set your rhythm.
7.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? Let us now try to extend the three walls of the rhythm concept. Before we make our own extension, let us listen to some famous composers who in fact successfully extended these walls: Cecil Taylor: Garden, Guerino Mazzola: Synthesis, third movement, Byungki Hwang: Jasi (Night Watch), The Beatles: All You Need Is Love. The extension we are proposing after your experiments and after listening to some famous extended rhythm creations is that
7.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
35
1. we take the full responsibility of positioning time events when we want them, as long as we want, 2. we don’t count any time signature to cast our time events—such a time signature may come after we have created rhythm, not as a precondition, 3. we open our ears for the silence in pauses as an enormous potential of notyet-played rhythms, of a universe of silent tongues1 that will sing when we let them do so. We should also add that it is not implied in our model of rhythm that only one voice is performing the rhythm. It may very well happen that several voices perform different rhythms simultaneously (generating a polyrhythm) with overlapping sounds.
7.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension With these extended walls of the concept of rhythm, the student now embarks in a series of exercise performances to test the effects of these extended rhythmical powers. Exercise 12 Play your rhythms, if possible also together with other students, everyone on his/her own instrument. Try to step from a time-signature-driven one to a freer one, or to another time signature. Try to “ride the horse,” as they say in free jazz, to take full responsibility of what you are playing. Try to listen to what you have not played yet, in the silence of pauses, but also behind the sounds you are producing. Don’t follow a given scheme or memory of heard music—make your own creation! You are the only one who determines what to do and what not to do!
1
This is a title of one of the most famous solo piano LPs by Cecil Taylor [116].
8 The Pitch Aspect
When shaping the body of time in music, we have to think about what material we want to distribute over time. Time as such has no sensual quality: You don’t see, smell, hear, touch it. We need to think about what is being dealt with in time. This tutorial unit deals with this theme. And it, in fact, will answer it in such a way that we understand why music deals with sound and not with, say, odors or visuals.
8.1 What Is Your Open Question? To begin with, we want to look at all possible ways to shape the body of time. We do not want to shape it in an abstract reality of pure thoughts, but in a sensual way. We are concerned with art and human expression for other humans and therefore are focusing on the five human senses1 : touch, smell, taste, hearing, and sight. Note that we have other senses, such as kinesthetic sense, senses for temperature, pain, balance, and acceleration. But let us focus on the most prominent ones. Exercise 13 Describe the five classical human senses and their qualities. What can you express with these senses? How precise is this expression? How can you perceive them? How can you produce them? How about their communication to other humans? Your discussion evokes the open question of this tutorial unit: Why are we using sound in music, and how do we deal with sound? 1
These senses are classical. They were classified by Aristotle but also recognized in other cultures, such as the “five material faculties” in Buddhism or as the “five horses drawing the chariot of the body” in the Katha Upanishad of Hinduism.
G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 8, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
37
38
8 The Pitch Aspect
It is, of course, not the question of defining music as the art of sound (in time), but the question of why this sense of hearing, and not any other, has such a prominent position in human artistic expression.
8.2 Let Us Describe the Context! We are now looking at the musical sense of hearing in the wider context of all five senses. The context is the multisensorial human reality of perception and utterance. Following your discussion of the qualities of our five senses, we can write down the following rough list of properties.
Sense touch smell taste hearing sight
Precision low low low high high
Complexity low average average high high
Production high low low high low
Perception high high high high high
Speed fast slow slow fast fast
Memory low average low high high
In this sensual context, hearing is the most skilled. More precisely, it is the only one where we can make fast and fine-grained sensorial output (sounds) and perceive it with no extra efforts. We have a voice and are also sensitive to sound for reasons of biological survival! We can communicate by sounds. The sense of sight is a passive one, since we can see but we cannot make what we see, whereas the sense of hearing can both receive and produce sounds. Exercise 14 Try to invent and use different instruments to make sounds. Try the same for visuals, touch, taste, and smell.
8.3 Find the Critical Concept! Within the context of the sense of hearing, we want to find a critical concept. This would be a concept that is central to our sense of hearing and ‘sounding.’ Let us first listen to different sounds from instrumental and environmental recordings. Exercise 15 Describe the different concepts coming to your mind when talking about sound. You have exhibited a number of such concepts: Loudness, the sound’s character (bright, dark, cold, hard, etc.), the development of the sound’s presence (envelope, play a piano sound backward to hear the envelope!), the spatial position and distribution of the sound, its male or female voice, etc.
8.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls!
39
There is one concept whose role seems to be very strong in sound perception and production: high and low, male or female sounds. We are extremely sensitive to the level of a sound. This might be for biological reasons: Babies have high voices and attract our attention; sexual selection also relates to male and female voices. This fact adds to the observation that we may perceive different heights of sounds being played at the same time! In music, several voices of a choir may sing and be perceived simultaneously. The quality of sound ‘height’ is called pitch. It is a crucial quality of sound in every musical culture. Let us choose this concept as a critical one in this tutorial unit. Exercise 16 Listen to different music with pitch and without pitch. Try to describe the types of pitch your perceive—if any. For example: piano, human voice, whistle, siren, snare drum, bass drum, saxophone, triangle, explosion, river, sea waves, wind. When looking at the physical phenomenon responsible for sound and pitch, we learn from acoustics (see section 21.1.1 for technical details) that sound stems from more or less regularly altered air pressure around its atmospheric average value, acting on our ears’ eardrums, and that pitch arises when the alteration is periodic (it repeats after a time period of P seconds) and it is proportional to the frequency f = 1/P , measured in units Hz (Hertz, 1/second) of this alteration. For example, the concert pitch a has frequency 440 Hz, i.e. the sound alteration repeats 440 times per second. A piano sound of this frequency 440 Hz is shown in Figure 8.1. A drum sound typically has no regular pressure variation; we see an example in Figure 8.2.
Fig. 8.1. The periodic pressure variation of a piano sound of concert pitch at 440 Hz.
Fig. 8.2. A nonperiodic sound variation of a drum, no pitch is perceived.
8.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! So far, we have learned about pitch as an important quality for music. We have seen that pitches can be perceived and produced simultaneously, yielding what are called chords. Pitch is a very powerful specification of sound qualities. But it is also imprisoned by a number of walls. A first wall relates to the very simple question: How do you make sound with pitch?
40
8 The Pitch Aspect
Exercise 17 Invent ways to make pitch, look for instruments that have pitch and describe how it is produced. When you compare a piano and a violin, for example, you will notice that you cannot produce pitches on the piano, beyond those that are defined by pressing one of the 88 keys that in turn hit the metal strings with felted hammers. But on the violin, you can produce an infinity of pitches (within the range of the violin’s overall pitches) by just pressing down the string on a variable position over the fingerboard (see Figure 21.5 for the violin’s anatomy). So the first type of wall is the instrumental accessibility of pitches. Some instruments may restrict your access by their mechanical construction.
Fig. 8.3. A selection of historical and present music notational systems. Most of them are locally displaying note events. Only the Tibetan Yang-Yig notation (middle) has a more gestural flavor.
A second type of wall relates to the question of how you memorize pitch. How do you communicate it to fellow musicians, scholars, and others who want to study your compositions? Exercise 18 Try to invent a notation for pitch on different instruments (also your own invented instruments, of course). And look for already existing such notations, as in Figure 8.3, which shows some old and new notation systems.
8.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls!
41
The wall character of notation is based on the fact that notation always not only represents pitch, but also limits pitch to what can be notated in the given notation standard. Let us look at the standard Western notation for piano, as shown in Figure 8.4.
Fig. 8.4. A classical score in Western notation.
Here we have two staffs of five lines each, a treble clef for the upper and a bass clef for the lower staff (starting at the end of the second measure). You can place note heads for specific pitches on each line or in between, and also on or between some higher or lower ledger lines. The line encircled by the treble clef is the pitch g below the concert note a. The line between the two points of the bass clef is the pitch f one octave and a major second below the g of the treble clef. The pitches that are possible in this system are the white keys on a piano. If you add some alteration signs (♭ for next lower (black) key on piano, ♯ for next higher (black) key on piano), you can describe all keys (the white and the black ones) that can be played on the piano.
Fig. 8.5. A scale with all pitches on a piano between two octaves.
Exercise 19 Play all keys from middle c on the piano upward one octave (playing each key, black and white, in order as you move to the right). Write this also in Western notation as a ‘scale.’ See Figure 8.5 for a solution.
42
8 The Pitch Aspect
We see here that the notation just selects a system of pitches and does not allow for notation of any other pitch. For example, if we want a pitch between e and f , Western notation does not allow it. For such a reason, Arabic maqam music, for example, cannot be notated with our Western system. Some composers and theorists, such as Ferrucio Busoni and Alois H´aba, have proposed and composed pitches between the piano key pitches. These systems are called microtonal and can yield very interesting music. Let us hear a quarter tone (a pitch in the middle of each successive pitch of the Western system) string quartet composed by H´ aba. Exercise 20 Create all scales of any seven different pitches within one octave starting with c (select from the 12 pitches from c to the next upper b). For example, the seven white keys on the piano (the major scale: ascending, c, d, e, f, g, a, b, see also Figure 8.5). Notate your scale’s seven pitches on a piano score system. One of them would be c, d, e♭, f, g, a♭, b, the so-called harmonic minor scale. The third type of wall that we want to exhibit is perhaps the most important, but it is also the most hidden one. If we want to organize pitch for music, the whole organism we want to construct cannot just consist of a set of disconnected pitch events in time. In other words, and in a somehow circular spirit, the third wall is pitches themselves as isolated entities. We need to connect pitches to make music. We need something like a networking structure between pitches.
8.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! So let us try to soften these three walls of pitch. Exercise 21 How could you soften the instrumental wall? Play an instrument or a sound software (such as Max MSP) on a computer and try to go beyond their pitch limitations. Don’t be shy, be experimental! Exercise 22 How could you soften the notation wall? Could you invent new notations for microtonal pitch or for your own pitch selection? Try! Exercise 23 How could you soften the pitch isolation wall? How could you find a bridge between two pitches? These exercises are very important to let you experience the walls as limits of musical expression and also the possibilities to break them down against established norms!
8.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls?
43
8.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? The opened walls have been extended in different ways; let us look at some of them: The instrumental wall of the piano has been extended by playing inside the piano, by using rubber or metal pieces to change the sound, and by inventing piano sound software allowing for new pitches or slightly changed original pitches. These software are built by sound synthesis methods, which we describe in detail in sections 21.1.3, 21.1.4.1, 21.1.4.2, and 21.1.4.3 of the theoretical part. Other extensions have been realized on the saxophone, by jazz saxophonist Pharoah Sanders, using overblowing techniques. On the violin, there is a whole arsenal of sophisticated techniques to alter the sound (see section 21.1.2). The notational wall has been opened and extended by many contemporary composers and theorists. H´ aba has written a harmony book [48] using his notation for microtonal pitch. Many electronically working composers have quit the traditional notation and work directly with frequencies. Of course, such notation cannot be used for normal instrumental performance, but it is absolutely adequate for computerized music production. It is also important to acknowledge the oral tradition, those composers and musicians who do not rely on notated pitch but play it directly from their instrumental skill and their practical memory. This is true in particular for many traditional Arab and Asian music cultures. The third wall, isolation, is the most important. How can we overcome this one? In your experiments in the above exercises, you have suggested that we try to measure the step when moving from one pitch to another, for example, when moving from c to g. There must be a way to fashion this movement between two pitches. Remark 5 The isolation of the selected seven pitches of a scale is a state of structural non-understanding of the scale’s anatomy. The naive listeners might just feel that there is some character of happiness (major scale) or sadness (minor scale), but they do not know what is responsible for this emotional qualification and therefore nurture the mystification of music. With isolated pitches, any music would be possible because it would neglect the possible relationships between its pitches. Conceiving the movements between a scale’s pitches creates a scale’s anatomy and connects its pitch spots. Exercise 24 Play several sequences of two pitches on the piano. Play c to g, then d to a. Or else d to f ♯ or g to b. What do you notice? Any suggestions? You rightly observe that some movements between two pitches sound the same. The movement c to g sounds like d to a, for example. This means that there is a relationship between c and g that is also the case for the movement d to a. This means that there is a connection between pitches that forgets about the absolute pitches and only expresses their ‘distance.’
44
8 The Pitch Aspect
This quality is called interval between pitches. It is a quality that classical music theorists in ancient Greece, the Pythagoreans, discovered. They worked with three such intervals. First: the octave, which means that two pitches x, y are in octave interval relation if the frequency f (y) of y is the double of f (x), f (y) = 2.f (x). Second: the perfect fifth, which means that x, y are in perfect fifth interval relation if f (y) = 3/2.f (x). Third: the perfect fourth, which means that x, y are in perfect fourth interval relation if f (y) = 4/3.f (x). Exercise 25 Play an octave (two adjacent c notes), perfect fifth (e.g. c to next higher g), and perfect fourth (e.g. g to next higher c) on the piano. Try the same on a violin or on a flute. For the Pythagoreans, it as a miraculous experience to create these intervals on their simple monochord, an instrument having just one string spanned over a resonance box. Exercise 26 You can also try this out! Take a string of the violin and pluck it, then fix it at its middle. Plucking a half of it yields an octave higher pitch. Now fix the string at 2/3 and you get a perfect fifth, finally fix it at 4/3 and you get a perfect fourth. Exercise 27 Make again a scale of any number of pitches in one octave (think of scales with four, nine, eleven pitches!), or even including microtones if you can notate them and ideally also play them on an instrument or computer. When you choose the pitches, be aware of the semitone contents of the intervals that you generate with this scale. Choose carefully what pitches you want while considering these interval qualities (see Figure 8.6). Those are just not the intervals between successive scale notes but they generate different value/flavor depending on your choices. This is called a well-tempered tuning: All twelve successive interval steps are equal and add up to the octave. These small intervals are called semitone or minor second intervals, and the interval of two successive semitones is called a whole tone or major second interval. For this reason, one also represents the octave as a clock with twelve hours, where every hour is a pitch, starting from c at 12, then c♯ at 1, etc. until b at 11. But why a closed circle? It is true that after an octave one is at a higher pitch. But music theorists have taken into account that notes that are one or several octaves apart from each other sound very similar. This has motivated them to even identify pitches that are one or several octaves apart from each other. Therefore we may use a clock, where we return to the same point after 12 interval steps.
8.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
45
8.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension In music, the concept of an interval has been very successful, and you should be aware that there are infinitely many intervals even within a single octave. The interval between two pitches x and y would be defined by the ratio f (y)/f (x) of their frequencies. Exercise 28 Try out any possible interval on a violin or trombone. Exercise 29 Listen to various existing scales. Here are some famous examples: melodic minor, harmonic minor, gypsy major, gypsy minor, whole tone, messiaen 2, messiaen 3, blue notes, major (= ionian), dorian, phrygian, lydian, mixolydian, aeolian, locrian, pentatonic, octatonic. Each scale has its own intervallic property and flavor.
Fig. 8.6. These are the classical intervals, in parenthesis the numbers of semitone steps: Unison U (0), minor second m2 (1), major second M2 (2), minor third m3 (3), major third M3 (4), perfect fourth P4 (5), tritone TT (6), perfect fifth P5 (7), minor sixth m6 (8), major sixth M6 (9), minor seventh m7 (10), major seventh M7 (11), octave P8 (12).
The classical intervals in Western music are shown in Figure 8.6. The Western counterpoint and harmony are based upon these interval categories, so the intervals are of practical relevance. Their relevance comes not from their abstract formal characterization as frequency relations, but from what their expression means to the theorist, composer, performer, and listener. Counterpoint and harmony are essentially defined upon the meaning of such intervals. For example, counterpoint is built upon the distinction of consonant (sounding agreeably) and dissonant intervals (sounding disagreeably). Exercise 30 Write a melody (a sequence of pitches) and determine all the successive intervals. Exercise 31 Play all these intervals as pairs of simultaneous notes. Do you experience different qualities of these intervals? Or do they all sound same to you? Also play intervals on the violin; do you experience different qualities?
46
8 The Pitch Aspect
Summarizing: There is an infinity of intervals. We may try to play them on certain instruments and also try to notate them, but then we would have to extend the classical Western musical notation. The relation of intervals shows different qualities, some sound nice, others rather harsh. But we should think of the entire variety of intervals when creating music. This relational thought of intervals does not mean however that the absolute pitch is irrelevant. There are many musicians and composers who perceive absolute pitch. So intervals are important but cannot replace pitch as an original sound quality.
9 The Harmonic Aspect
Harmony is a magic word in music theory and practice. It is not only a technical term but also refers to more transcendental layers of existence. In ancient Greece, harmony was the ultimate ground of the universe. In Pythagorean philosophy, the ultimate formula of the universe was their tetractys, a triangular arrangement of ten points starting at the base with 4, then 3, then 2, then 1 on top. You have already seen in the previous chapter on intervals that the successive ratios of these triangular numbers—2/1, 3/2, 4/3—are the intervals of an octave, perfect fifth, and perfect fourth. So the tetractys was the universal law behind both music and the universe. This formula was an expression of harmony since these intervals were considered to be particularly agreeable, Fig. 9.1. Johannes Kepler or “consonant,” as music theorist call them. In wrote the five books Haropposition to consonant intervals, they speak of monices mundi about the “dissonant” intervals; for example, the minor sec- world’s harmony and its reond or the tritone are dissonant and sound less lation to the five Platonic agreeable to many persons—but not all. We come bodies as a guiding principle back to these interval qualities in tutorial 11 about of astronomy. counterpoint. In 1619, when astronomy was developed using modern mathematics, Johannes Kepler wrote the five books Harmonices mundi (see Figure 9.1) about the world’s harmony and its relation to the five Platonic bodies as a guiding principle of astronomy. He was concerned more with the musical harmony of planet motion than with any other rationales for natural laws. And we should not forget that a modern foundation of physics, string theory, is also based upon vibrations of microscopic strings, much like the vibrations of violin strings. G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 9, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
47
48
9 The Harmonic Aspect
9.1 What Is Your Open Question? Now that you’ve read about the history of harmony and its deep impact on the understanding of the universe, what do you think is the role of harmony in these philosophical approaches driven by music? Exercise 32 Think about harmony and its role in the grand view of this universe. Also think about music-related harmony. What could be its overall role and structure? Your answer might be this: Harmony gives the world a deeper content. And this is what we are also experiencing with harmony in music. Now, in music such harmony is built starting from the traditional harmony as expressed by those consonant Pythagorean intervals. So our open question would be about how the composing or playing of combined pitches—possibly referring to their intervallic relations—constitutes harmony in the sense of a deeper content in music.
9.2 Let Us Describe the Context! Let us now locate the open question within a reasonable context. Exercise 33 If you are to create meaning with music, what context of such action would you propose? Think about it in the sense of creating a communication by music as if you were speaking in a language. This means to deal with music as a system of meaningful signs. If you recall the introduction to this book, section 2.3, you will remember that systems of meaningful signs are called semiotics. Harmony then is to be viewed in the context of a music semiotics. We want music to be a system of meaningful signs. And then we are also concerned with connecting such signs, like when you build sentences that connect signs functioning as subject, verb, object, and so forth. Recall from section 2.3 that this is called syntagm, while the pointer from expression to meaning or content is called semantics. In other words, harmony relates to the making of meaning in music in the dimensions of semantics and syntactics. But it relates to this process in a special way—namely, when combining different pitches. The classical situation is that such a combination is played simultaneously, which is called a chord. In Figure 7.2 we saw a number of chords in Beethoven’s fanfare. Although this seems straightforward, it is an important topic in music philosophy to ask whether music means anything at all. In fact, most music does not refer to a thing or object in the external world’s reality. When we say “tree,” this refers to a meaning showing an object in the real world. In music, such a reference is absent (except for program music—for example, mimicking
9.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls!
49
the sound of sea waves—but this covers only a small part of musical expressivity). Let us keep this conflict in mind and come back to it at the end of this chapter.
9.3 Find the Critical Concept! The open question about the mechanism for constituting substantial meaning in music by combined pitch performance is a semiotic one. It must focus on the musically central concept of harmonic signification. The classical concept for this is a harmonic function. This function attributes to any combination of pitches (played simultaneously or successively, it does not matter, we abstract from the pitches’ onset time or duration) a meaning in the semiotic system of music. Exercise 34 Suggest some kind of harmonic function. For example, a chord could mean an emotion, color, objects, etc. What does a major triad chord mean to you? And any rule works, just think about how it would help you give meaning to music. For example, a diminished seventh chord followed by an augmented triad could mean “distorted reality being resolved to a floating dream.” This exercise might sound strange, since it looks like you are allowed to invent any kind of meaning in harmony, irrespective of any other given meanings of musical objects (melodies, rhythms, instruments, etc.). The situation is, in fact, somehow wild. Of course, one may attribute emotional or biological meanings to musical chords or similar pitch-defined objects. But a reduction of musical meaning to such everyday signification would not satisfy the idea of musical content or meaning. Exercise 35 Listen to Bach’s Well-tempered Piano and think about its content beyond emotions and biology. The work is known for its careful melodic and harmonic construction. Exercise 36 Now let us try to define more precisely what you think is the meaning of a chord. Try to define the emotional meaning of chords by looking at their intervals and using their consonances. But recall from our earlier observation that the intervals’ consonance/dissonance are subjective.
9.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! If we think about the harmonic function of a chord, the first wall thereof is that we automatically think of a fixed meaning, like for signs in language: The sign “cat” has a uniquely determined meaning. It should not depend on the
50
9 The Harmonic Aspect
day time, weather, or other contingencies. Is it reasonable to look for such an unchangable harmonic function in music, too? Exercise 37 Think about reasons for rigid or nonrigid harmonic functions for chords. For example, whether functions could define the harmonic environment of a chord, or whether the harmonic environment defines the function of that chord. The second wall is the domain of values we may attribute to a chord. What do we expect from such valuations? Let us look at the classical harmonic functions in music theory. Here a chord can only take three quite abstract values: tonic, dominant, and subdominant. More precisely, if we are given a tonality, like the one determined by the C-major scale (c, d, e, f, g, a, b), the triad chord {f, a, c} would have harmonic subdominant function (denoted by S), while the triad {g, b, d} has dominant function (denoted by D) and the triad {c, e, g} has tonic function (denoted by T). Remark 6 We should notice that the main theorist of harmonic function theory, Hugo Riemann, in fact defined tonality very elegantly by the harmonic function attributed to chords (all possible chords were envisaged!). For example, the C-major tonality would be defined by the function values (out of three values D, S, T) attributed to chords as described above. In other words, these functions create the tonality. We could then write C-major({c, e, g}) = T, etc., but F-major({c, e, g}) = D, etc. This is elegant because we do not have to restrict our pitches to the particular scale; chords with pitches not in that scale would also be given harmonic function values with respect to that tonality. See Figure 9.2 for a sequence of harmonic functions. This seFig. 9.2. A cadence in Cquence, T, S, D, T, is a typical syntagmatic figure: major with the standard seIt is called a cadence in C-major. Any chord sequence T, S, D, T. quence with this harmonic function associated is then called a cadence in C-major. This is a type of ‘grammatical’ sentence similar to a language sentence. It is used to say in a few chords that we are working in this tonality. You will find this very frequently in classical and in popular music. Listen to some examples: Go to the end of these works, please, and listen to the final chords. Exercise 38 Why would you want to have only these three main values of harmonic functions? Why not much more, and different values? Could you also think of taking fuzzy values: not only “yes” or “no,” but something between, 60 percent of a value, say? Listen to a piano solo by jazz pianist and composer Thelonious Monk. It is full of beautiful dissonances. Try to give such fuzzy values to his chords.
9.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls!
51
A third wall can be recognized when thinking about aesthetics in music, dealing with what is beautiful or ugly. Does such a function have to represent beauty or truth? Or both? Setting ugly chords in beautiful way also works in music! Does beauty follow a logic, or does logic shape beauty? Recall the famous poem Ode on a Grecian Urn by George Keats (1819), concluding with the beautiful verses “Beauty is truth, truth beauty,”—that is all Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know. Exercise 39 Think about beauty as a possible value of a harmonic function. Isn’t this much more important than an abstract logical value or such an abstract value like tonic, dominant, or subdominant? We don’t have to stress that these properties are really walls, i.e. they prevent the harmonic function concept from becoming connected to what useful meaning would give us. We should develop the keen sensitivity about how narrow the function concept is if one keeps these walls upright. The point of this sensitivity is that we do not want to compose music within a priori fixed semantics. We are by no means limited by given external, real world contents. As said above, the situation is somehow wild, but it is not true that anything goes and that meaning does not matter. It matters a lot, but it is not set and fixed forever. Composers and improvisers should actively set such contents in their music. This is probably one of the most exciting moments in musical creativity! We not only may create musical forms, objects, chords, melodies, and rhythms, but we are also asked to organize their meanings. We have to go to the initial moment where there is virtually no given meaning, at least beyond those elementary emotional or biological elements. In this moment, we create the harmonic functions with their relation to tonality.
9.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! We have these three walls: • • •
Rigidity: The harmonic functions are unchangeable. Abstractness: The poor value set of domains of harmonic functions. Beauty: The question about aesthetical values of a harmonic functions.
We could summarize the three walls and say (quite exaggerated) that harmonic function tends to be rigid, abstract, and aesthetically useless. Why should we need this type of semantical values at all? We needn’t because they are paralyzing any creative work that searches for meaning and not just formal games. So let us run against these walls and try to break them down! The first wall of functional rigidity already shows fissures. We have seen that harmonic functions in Riemann’s theory are not absolutely rigid. The
52
9 The Harmonic Aspect
formula C-major({c, e, g}) = T is relativizing functional values for the sake of a definition of tonality. This is an exciting new perspective in that it opens the wall toward the use of harmonic functions for the construction of higher musical contents. Tonality is such a higher content, and Riemann’s idea was to use harmonic functions to imagine and construct the concept of tonality. Why is this a decisive step? Because larger musical sentences, not just single chords, are often conceived as expressing tonality—the composition is in C-major, F♯-minor, etc. This means that we are interested in having the function values of the composition’s chords be connected by their role as expressions of tonality. Tonality and then modulation, i.e. the transition from one tonality to another one, are extremely important in the construction of harmonic meaning in music. Therefore, the first opening of this wall consists of the question of what the value of harmonic functions is for establishing larger musical coherence. Could such a scope be a door to overcome the rigidity of harmonic functions? Remark 7 We should add the observation that despite the prominent position of Riemann’s approach, it has never been completed, i.e. it has never been possible in traditional music theory to assign a reasonable function value to any chord as an expression of a given tonality. The function values usually are limited to simple chords, such as major triads (like {c, e, g}), minor triads (like {c, e♭, g}), etc., and some tetrads. But already chromatic triads, like {c, c♯, d}, are problematic. This might be one reason that classical harmony was given up by Schoenberg and others in the first decade of the twentieth century. You see here that harmony is not only a given constant of theory but could be used to construct new meaning! Schoenberg’s ‘solution’ to quit harmony altogether with his dodecaphonic approach in 1921 looks quite confusing here. We shall come back to this topic in tutorial 13 on serialism. The second wall of value domains is a bit harder to soften. In common language, we have a rich repertory of meaning, such as the real world’s objects, ideas, emotions, etc. They do all offer contents. But with music, the semantical domains, such as the traditional Western triple T, D, S, are extremely poor. Exercise 40 Try to draw a (even fictitious) graphical image of a musical composition with (tonality related) dominant, subdominant, and tonic values of its chords. Compare with the same semantic image for a real world English sentence. Are you satisfied with this kind of semantic control of music? There are a number of straightforward enrichments of such semantics. To begin with, one can add some more refined values. This is quite common in Western harmony. For example, one adds the value Dp, dominant parallel, which would be taken by the minor triad at e in C-major, see Figure 9.3. Another method would consist of allowing several values at the same time for a given chord. This only makes sense if we attribute weights to these distributed values (for example, 30% D, 20% S, 50% T in G-major). This is the fuzzy logic
9.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls?
53
approach, where truth can have any value between truth and falsity. We have realized this fuzzy approach in our software RUBATO for musical analysis [74]. So softening this wall a bit is possible, but we are still left with the main question of whether we really have those harmonic values that we want to address when creating music. Is harmony a question of three values: T, D, S (with respect to tonalities)? Fig. 9.3. Dominant The third wall, the aesthetic question in harmonic triad (left) and domfunction, is the hardest. What is beauty? What is truth? inant parallel (right) If Keats were right, why then is it so difficult to talk in C-major. about logic to musicians and composers? Why then is any logical discourse in music so critically reductive? Which composer would ever reduce his/her composition’s meaning to logical categories? Although Schoenberg said, “Musik soll nicht schm¨ ucken, sie soll wahr sein,1 ” he created much more than truth values. The point is that between ornamentation and truth values there is the most important thing: beauty. I would prefer to claim, “Music should be neither ornament nor truth but beauty.” At this point we see that there must be harmonic values to be taken other than logical ones of simple truth or falsity. We have at least softened this constituent of the wall: Let us search for value domains that are more susceptible to expressing beauty than abstract logic. And also look at and listen to other music systems, such as the Indian Raga music with its mela scales or at the Korean traditional music, or at the Tuvan throat singers’ overtone-based system, for example.
9.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? The first wall: Rigidity has been softened in order to define tonality via harmonic functions. How could we extend this wall? We could just take a set of functional assignments to chords in order to define higher structures, such as tonalities. We need not reproduce known tonalities, as they are usually derived from scales. We may define a new tonality by a creative construction starting from given Riemannian tonalities. For example, we may take two tonalities, C-major and F-major, and their Riemannian definition that assigns values C-major(X) and F-major(X) to a chord X. We may then define a product tonality by the formula C-major×F-major(X) = (C-major(X),F-major(X)). Here the harmonic function values are pairs of classical values. So, for example, we would have C-major×F-major({c, e, g}) = (T,D). This yields a bitonality function, and its values are a combination of values for each tonality that are already known from Riemann theory. Exercise 41 Try to construct other generalized tonalities using given classical Riemannian tonalities. 1
Music should not ornament but be true.
54
9 The Harmonic Aspect
The second wall, abstract values, could be extended by a new approach to functional assignments. We have in fact seen that the normal functional value in Riemannian theory is to give every chord a value without looking at values of other chords. This defines, for example, all chords with tonic value just by checking each chord and seeing whether it has the value T or not. If it has that value, we get the set T(Z) = {X|Z(X) = T} of all tonic chords in tonality Z. This is a bottom up method: define T(Z) by the values of single chords. But we could start on top and then go down, by first defining sets of chords VZ describing a tonality Z in an abstract way, without specifying values of single chords first. For example, take a piece of music that has a score and a recording. Listen to the piece and start finding a pitch t you think is the “tonal center” of the piece. Listen until you believe that the tonal center has been changed. Take all the chords until this moment of change and give them the functional value X(t). Then all these chords have obtained their value not because of their individual properties, but because you put them into the ‘bag’ of chords expressing that tonal center t. It does not matter how you conceive the property of “being a tonal center,” it is just a feeling, but this works. Then you go on in the piece with the second tonal center, etc. This is a typical top-down procedure. And it could happen that some chords have two or more values in your system. Suggest how to define a functional value in such a case. Feel free to invent whatever you believe is reasonable! Exercise 42 Listen to Hindemith’s Ludus tonalis, prelude in E, to see how he creates the harmonic function using the tonal center E. Exercise 43 Listen to Lutoslawski’s Two Studies for Piano, I, and look at the end of the piece to see how he builds creatively the cadence. It is not T, S, D, T in the conservative harmonic functions, and the harmonic functions are his own creations. Remark 8 This is also the strategy in the mathematical theory of counterpoint [77], where we do not first say which intervals as individuals are consonant or dissonant and then define the set of all consonant intervals, but we first determine the set by a special set property and then say that an interval is consonant because it is member of that set. This is opposite to the classical acoustical consonance theory where consonance is first given for individual intervals, for example by Euler’s gradus suavitatis function. See our tutorial on counterpoint in chapter 11 for a more detailed discussion of this topic. This means that you, the composer, are free to define harmonic values by describing sets of chords that you consider having a determined harmonic value. The value is defined by the set of chords and not by a technical property to be checked for single chords. And if you want to to define a tonality in your own way, you have to propose sets VZ of chords that you think share a property V that defines an aspect of your concept of a tonality Z.
9.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
55
Exercise 44 Try to construct other generalized tonalities using this top down approach. The third wall is the most exciting to be extended. We are asked to introduce values that might be more akin to beauty than those abstract Riemannian T, D, and S and their variants. Let us first think about the nature of these values. As opposed to the common language semantics, musical semantics has no external references. Harmonic functions do not refer to external meaning; they do not mean anything from the outside—works, an apple, love, temperature, desire. They can only have values internal to the music system. So if we review T, D, and S as internal values, T refers to the tonic of a tonality, the basic pitch c of the C-major scale, for example, and D refers to the interval of a perfect fifth above the tonic, a position that is thought to create a force toward the tonic in a final harmonic situation as described by the cadence T → S → D → T described above. And opposed to D is S, it is a fifth below the tonic, or a perfect fourth above, and it can help open the harmonic pathway when starting from the tonic. So we see that these values are derived from a simple aesthetic idea. If we use this opening of the aesthetic wall, we may think of harmonic function values as structures describing beauty in the harmonic movement. Yes, but what is beauty here? Is there a general basis for beauty? Is the movement D → T a general fact of beauty? Isn’t it just a conventional movement that has gained its prominence by a virtually infinite repetition? We do not have to decide upon these questions, but you, the young composer, may now extend the wall by introducing structures that you consider to be beautiful. In other words, why don’t you define beauty by naming and listing musical harmonies that you consider beautiful. This would mean that you create your own harmonic semantics of beauty, the meaning of your own language. This means to create internal reference structures that you consider beautiful, without any further reference, just your own vocabulary of beauty. If you apply the top-down strategy described above, you may then introduce sets of chords that you define as carriers of music contents of your language. This means that you can make beauty, not just applying given schemes of more or less formal and abstract aesthetics.
9.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension Exercise 45 Build sets of chords that you consider elements of an aesthetic harmonic content. Try to write compositions (also in your own notational system, this does not matter) that express statements about your harmonic vocabulary. Exercise 46 Build sets of chords following the classical Riemannian approach. Try to compose following this scheme. Test the difference of success as compared with your own harmonic principles.
56
9 The Harmonic Aspect
These testing exercises are not meant to create easy decisions, but they should invite you to think about how a harmonic function might affect the way you create musical works.
10 Melodic Aspects
Melody is a central aspect of musical creation. In most popular music, the melody is the only characteristic feature that is retained and memorized by everybody. This is certainly also due to the fact that the human voice is the first of all valid musical instruments, and that melody relates to music for and by human voices. Knowing this dominant role of melody, many instructors stress composing cantabile (in a singing manner) and then also performing as if one were singing—even on instruments (such as the piano) where this approach is somewhat artificial in view of their mechanical construction (the piano being more a percussive than a melodic instrument). Mozart was in fact famous for his “oily flowing” pianistic attack. In this tutorial unit, we want to investigate the creative potential of composing melodies. Melodies have two roles: 1. They are complex motivic shapes in themselves, and 2. They play a role as germs for the dramatic story they may tell as a composition’s theme. Before discussing these roles, we have to stress that the invention of good melodies is still one of the most difficult compositional tasks. There is no theory guaranteeing good melodic creations, and there are no computer programs; it seems that this task is the hardest in all directions of musical creation. The lack of theory is not only for composing good melodies, but even more elementary: In contrast to harmony, there is not even an established theory of melodies. Rudolf Reti’s classical work The Thematic Process in Music [100] is a first heroic approach to the topic, but it suffers from ambiguities (Reti does not even believe that precise concepts can be built in this field) and even contradiction (for example, Reti’s concept of identical themes is not even transitive, i.e. theme A can be identical to theme B, and theme B identical to theme C, without A being identical to C!). For a more rigorous new approach to the theory and its computerized implementation, we refer to the theory of musical motives [77, chapter 22] and its software implementation [77, chapter 41.2] as developed by Chantal Buteau, Guerino Mazzola, and Oliver Zahorka. G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 10, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
57
58
10 Melodic Aspects
This means that the present tutorial unit (like some of the other units) is more a strategic catalyzer than a set of recipes to find those melodies that make you rich.
10.1 What Is Your Open Question? As a musical structure, melody involves, above all, onset time and pitch. See Figure 10.1 for an example, the melody of the famous Beatles song Michelle. But it is not only a structure in time and pitch. It also has a meaning like
Fig. 10.1. The first eight-measure sentence of the famous Beatles song Michelle.
chords, but this meaning is radically different from a harmonic function. It is not coincidence that melodies are strongly correlated to lyrics, with short texts that create a human story. Melodies have the potential of stories. They are musical germs of entire tales to be developed in the musical composition. One can take parts of such melodies, short motives, and encounter them all over the composition. One may find them in similar forms, deformed or transformed, but still acting as placeholders or delegates of the original ‘mother’ melody. This sounds familiar as long as we focus on the linguistic metaphor. But musical stories are usually not loaded with extramusical contents; melodies and motives are not words and therefore cannot create novels and stories similar to common language1 . This is a big problem and in fact our open question: How can melodic structures create meaning in musical compositions that takes over the function of a story in common language? 1
Although lyrics refer to extramusical stories, the musical quality of a melody is independent of the lyrical thread.
10.2 Let Us Describe the Context!
59
10.2 Let Us Describe the Context! The context of melody and its associated open question are easily described once you look at a melody and try to explain it to someone. Exercise 47 Focus on the above melody from Michelle and try to explain the melody in detail to a fellow student. Use whatever technical tools or limbs to do so. You will immediately realize that this melody relates to a movement in time. It is a kind of gesture that you might describe by a movement of your hands or by dancing it while you sing the melody. You will also observe that this entire movement could be called a shape, or what psychologists call a gestalt. In fact, psychologist Christian von Ehrenfels introduced gestalt theory using a melody as a model [38]. He characterized gestalt by two attributes: A gestalt can be transposed (or more generally: transformed) without changing its identity, and it is super-summative, i.e. it is more than the sum of its parts. In our case this means that a melody is more than the collection of its single notes. And we should add to the Ehrenfels criteria that a gestalt is also invariant under small deformations. When you make a gesture, it is not so important that you move exactly the same every time; perception is quite tolerant. Otherwise we could not even recognize letters that are written in different fonts, let alone in different handwritings! This first bunch of contextual topics is what one calls paradigmatic, and it pertains to associative fields of concepts or objects. Observe that the paradigm can be either a transformational one (transposing a melody) or a topological one (namely, deforming a melody to a similar shape; topology is the science investigating deformations). To this paradigmatic context we have to add another one, namely the fact that if you tell a story, be it in common language or in music, you have to place plot, your melodic units, in time, simultaneously or one after the other. This is the syntagmatic axis, the timeline on which a text is displayed. Let us look at a classical situation of such a story: a fugue, as shown in Figure 10.2. In the first two measures, you have a melody (the fugue’s dux, in the alto voice), which is answered by a second appearance of the melody in measures 3 and 4 (the fugue’s comes, in soprano) and transposed a fifth upward from the dux. Then a second comes, in bass, appears on measure 7. And so on. The composition is a story displaying this initial melody’s shape in time and pitch space (Attention: We have more than just the time axis in musical syntagm, we also have pitch!). Putting these two perspectives together, the melodic context is paradigmatic and syntagmatic, and we have to investigate the distribution of melodies in this two-dimensional field.
60
10 Melodic Aspects
Fig. 10.2. The classical situation of a musical story: a fugue. In the first two measures, you have a melody (the fugue’s dux, in the alto voice), which is answered by a second appearance of the melody in measures 3 and 4 (the fugue’s comes, in soprano) and transposed a fifth upward from the dux. Then a second comes, in the bass line, appears on measure 7.
10.3 Find the Critical Concept! Melodies can occur just as nice ornaments in pitch and time, but their power is only fully developed when they bear a potential of ‘telling a story’. As such, they are a kind of germinal structure that unfolds in the course of the composition, they become omnipresent like a story’s dominating subject2 . The concept that is loaded with this potential is called the composition’s theme. Beethoven is famous for having worked out the thematic potential. In music theory, his method is called motivic-thematic work. In intuitive terms, one could call this the art of telling a story as a musical emanation of the composition’s theme. Exercise 48 Listen to Beethoven’s Piano Sonata op. 2, No. 1, in F-minor, first movement, to see how he unfolds the motif in a motivic-thematic way into his entire music. 2
It is a challenging question whether, conversely, a story in common language is also in its intrinsic quality conceived as a musical tale and less a message about extramusical contents.
10.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls!
61
Exercise 49 Listen to The Beatles’s Michelle entirely and try to describe the story that is developed around the main theme shown in Figure 10.1. The difficulty of a theme is to understand what its potential is, how it can unfold its forces to shape the composition’s syntagmatic display. If the theme were just that assembly of notes in the time-pitch space, it would be a simple thing, but this is not how it must be viewed as loaded with the story’s subject’s power. This makes clear that the theme’s wall is its identity: What is the theme more than that structural entity? What makes the theme to what it is as a theme?
10.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! As we already stated in section 10.2, a theme is what psychologists call a gestalt, a shape that has three characteristics: It is more than its parts (supersummativity), it can be transformed, and it can be deformed without losing its identity. Therefore its wall is this complex set of attributes that define it as a gestalt. But why is this a wall? The first reason is that it is not clear how much more than its parts it is. And also: What are these parts more than the theme’s notes? Second: If the theme can be transformed, what is a transformation, and how can a transformation be realized in the composition? Do we just have to recognize that there is an original structure X in the score and then somewhere later in the score is its transformed version f (X) by transformation f ? Third: How much can we deform a structure X such that its deformed version X ′ is still recognizable? Example 1 Let us look at the Bach example in Figure 10.2. The dux theme appears again as comes 1 in measure 3. This one is a transformation f (dux) of the dux, namely by two measures in time, and then by a perfect fifth upward (c → g) in pitch. Here the comes 1 is easily recognized as being a transformed version of the dux since playing later and somewhat higher is an easy task for human cognition. If Bach had chosen a more complex transformation instead (for example, a rotation or a shearing), we would not recognize the transformed version so easily—if at all! But the comes 1 is not only this transformation, it is also a deformation of f (dux). The fourth note is a g in the dux but is not a fifth higher, a f (g) = d, in comes 1; Bach takes the perfect fourth higher c instead. This is not very different from the expected perfect fifth, so it does not destroy the overall shape. There is a simple reason for this deformation: Bach would like to have a consonant interval with the e♭ of the alto voice. The note d would not meet this requirement, as we would have a dissonant minor second d − e♭. But then Bach could also have chosen the c one octave higher, with the same consonance argument. However, the shape would then be different, and the deformation not really acceptable, because the movement would be ascending instead of descending at the fourth note.
62
10 Melodic Aspects
When we state the theme as a gestalt, we should be aware of the fact that a theme is not just there like an object of nature, but it is created by humans. And it is created as a gestalt, not as a set of uncorrelated notes. It is an organism that grows from the composer’s constructive effort. This creative work is then reflected in the composition’s development. The composition’s tale is also a reflection of this constructive genealogy. This means that when we discuss the theme’s wall, this is also a wall for the creation, not just for the compositional usage or theoretical analysis of a theme. After all, a composer should be completely aware of the theme’s ‘anatomy’ when working out a thematic composition3
Fig. 10.3. The second group of four notes (over the lyrics “these are words that”) is a deformation of the retrograde of the first group. The group of four notes in measure 4 plus the first of measure 5 (over the lyrics “go together well”) are in a peak shape that reappears in a shortened version, like a ‘tail,’ (transposed in time) for the last three notes.
Example 2 As a small example about the theme’s anatomy, let us reconsider the Beatles song Michelle from Figure 10.1. The theme starts with a four-note motif over the lyrics “Michelle ma belle.” It is a horizontal movement into the peak note d and then descending to a. The next four notes in measure 3 are of similar shape but in inverted time direction: ascending from g to the peak c and then descending to a horizontal pair of gs. Therefore, one could say that the second group of four notes (over the lyrics “these are words that”) is a deformation of the reflection (in time, a retrograde) of the first group at the vertical axis. The group of four notes in measure 4 plus the first of measure 5 (over the lyrics “go together well”) are in a peak shape that reappears, like a ‘tail,’ (transposed in time) for the last three notes (over the lyrics “my Michelle”). We even observe a correspondence between the lyrics that parallels the motivic one. 3
There are also athematic compositions, but we do not discuss them here.
10.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls!
63
Exercise 50 Try to construct a simple theme by use of the above types of transformations and deformations. Try to make it sounding interesting. Make first a drawing and then the corresponding musical shape.
10.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! What we should have in mind now is to open this wall in order to be able to build, handle, and decompose themes as if they were living body gestures of sound. The aesthetic aspect of such themes is less our concern than the dynamical management we can think of. Here is the limit of our theory of melodies, but we believe that the techniques we shall describe are quite powerful. First, let us look at the wall of the theme X’s parts. What can we do there? As we have seen in the above Bach and Beatles examples, we can take subsets of a theme as parts. We could envisage all of the theme’s parts and consider the powerset 2X = {Y ⊂ X} of the theme set. This is a large repertory of parts; for example, if X has 8 notes, the powerset has 256 elements, starting with the singletons {x} for the theme’s notes x and ending with the whole theme set X. In the above Beatles theme, we had just four out of the 216 = 65, 536 possible subsets. So the first opening would consist of considering all possible subsets of a theme, or, when constructing it, considering any combination of subsets of notes to build the whole theme. So far this is quite primitive, as we cannot make more than just select subsets. But there is more, namely the entire set-theoretical machinery of set unions, intersections, and complements, and this is what is known as Booelan calculus: Take sets, unite them, intersect them, look at complements of subsets of a large set. OK, now you, the musically interested student, would probably react against such “abstract nonsense,” right? We understand, since such mathematics is not really what you think is helping your creativity. But be assured, this is wrong for two reasons. To begin with, famous composers, such as Iannis Xenakis, have used this method of Boolean operations on sets of notes (also known as sieve calculus) with great success, e.g. in the famous composition Nomos Alpha. Second, the Boolean calculus is nothing but the formalism necessary to describe and manipulate sets of notes regarding common notes or shared notes. There is a beautiful simple example of how this can be understood in five minutes. Take one octave of the scale of C-major, X = {c, d, e, f, g, a, b}, a set of seven pitches. Look at the seven triadic chords that you know from elementary music theory, namely: I = {c, e, g}, II = {d, f, a}, III = {e, g, b}, IV = {f, a, c}, V = {g, b, d}, V I = {a, c, e}, V II = {b, d, f }. The Boolean calculations of the intersections among two or three of these triads is very important in harmony because it tells which chords have common tones, and then we may use this information to connect chords by common tones in voice-leading theory. Arnold Schoenberg called this connection between triads the harmonic band. What Schoenberg did not know is that when you look at all the pairs
64
10 Melodic Aspects
or triplets of these seven chords that have a non-empty intersection, you get a fascinating geometric picture:
Fig. 10.4. The harmonic band of C-major is a M¨ o bius band. Two triads are connected by a line if they have one or two notes in common. Three triads are connected by a triangular surface if they have a note in common. For example I and V are connect by a line, whereas I and II are not. And III, V, V II are connected by a triangular surface since they have the note b in common.
Exercise 51 Draw each triad as a point on a piece of paper. Connect two of them by a line if their intersection is non-empty (e.g. I is connected to III since the tones e, g are common). Draw a triangular surface among any three of these triads if their intersection is non-empty (e.g. I, III, V are vertices of such a triangle since they have g in common). Check out what this geometric obius band!) figure looks like! (The solution is in Figure 10.4. It is a M¨ Therefore the Boolean operations on subsets of the theme tell us a lot about the common pitches (if we forget about time) or times (if we forget about pitch). This approach is a kind of musical geography: The parts are like charts of an atlas, and their overlaps tell us how geographic charts are connected. You see that if you select as charts just the single note sets, you get a quite trivial geography: only isolated singletons, no connection. The connectivity of your theme’s “charts” is a sign of how these parts are connected with one another. So it is important that composers and improvisers should look for these subset possibilities and try to construct interesting intersecting configurations in their musical creations. Exercise 52 Listen to the melodies of your favorite music. Is it just an amorphous sequence of pitches? The composer utilizes the submotives of the theme
10.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls!
65
in an interesting way. We have seen this in Beethoven’s Piano Sonata op. 2, No. 1, F-minor, and in The Beatles song Michelle ma belle. Example 3 Take four chords such that their Boolean intersection geography looks like the surface of the Earth’s globe! Can you do this? One simple solution is to take a tetrachord, like X = {b, d, f, a♭}, and to look at its four triadic subchords defined by omitting one of the four notes of X, i.e. Xb = {d, f, a♭}, Xd = {b, f, a♭}, Xf = {b, d, a♭}, Xa♭ = {b, d, f }. We then see that any three of them have a note in common but all four have no note in common, and therefore the intersection geography looks like a tennis ball that is covered by four triangular pieces (see Figure 10.5).
Fig. 10.5. The intersection geography of a tetrachord that is covered by its four triadic subchords looks like a spherical surface.
Now, let us look at the wall’s aspect relating to transformations. We have seen in the Bach example that transposition in time and pitch is a common transformation. In the Beatles example we also recognized reflection at a vertical line, the retrograde transformation reversing time direction. To give you an idea of how to make transformations, work in the plane whose x-axis is time and whose y-axis is pitch, where you might draw semitone distances as equal size. If you draw a melody (or a part thereof) as a point set, the points will all have pitch values in that grid defined by semitone distances. Take that plane and think of a common transformation thereof. Translation by a multiple of time units and/or pitch units (like a perfect fifth, seven semitone steps) moves that melody into another position whose pitch is still in that pitch grid. And if you make the reflection at a vertical line, the pitches will still be in that pitch grid. But what about a rotation? See Figure 10.6 to understand this situation.
66
10 Melodic Aspects
Fig. 10.6. A transformation of a melody (blue circles) in the semitone-quarternote grid can create a ‘melody’ (red squares) that is no longer in this grid. For example, the rotation by 45o produces pitches that are no longer in the semitone grid.
Exercise 53 Try to draw an image of the rotation of a melody by 45 degrees in counter-clockwise direction. What do you observe? Yes, you see: It can happen that a rotated note no longer has a pitch value in that grid of semitones! So we are confronted with this problem: Either only perform transformations that keep pitch in that semitone grid, or else we have to shift the rotated pitch down or up to the next semitone value! And this is a deformation. This means that deformations are a natural tool helping us stay in the pitch domain that makes sense in the usual notation system. Of course, the same necessity can arise in the time domain if the onsets or durations fall out of a grid of time quantization after such a rotation. Summarizing, we see that transformations may be a strong tool but may also endanger the parameters of sounds: Pitch may fall into values that are no longer standard in the usual pitch domain. Let us now focus on the wall of deformation. We have just seen that deformations may help us stay in a given parameter domain. But the question here is another one. If we are allowed to deform parameters, what is the amount of deformation that we can accept while conserving the original shape? To what extent can we accept to have the deformed shape in sufficiently near neighborhood of the original one? We want to deform, but not ‘too much.’ This aspect of nearness is totally different from the transformational situation. A transformation may move the original shape quite far, whereas deformation deals with proximity and similarity. This is the problem of this opening of the wall of a theme.
10.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? The three wall extensions are built upon Boolean operations, transformations, and deformations of thematic material, essentially operating in the plane
10.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
67
of time and pitch but, in a more general setup, also on other melodic parameters such as duration or loudness. These operations are not only paradigmatic, but also cover the syntagmatic distribution of thematic components, since the overall theme may be viewed as a union (Boolean) of a number of translated (transformation) parts. The theme is then covered by parts that are results of the three operation types. Whereas these methods can be a priori applied in any order and quantity, there are a number of measures to take to keep the result transparent to the listener. It may be important to the composer to communicate what has been done in order to tell the story in a way that is perceived and understood without having to Fig. 10.7. The three basic operation types of delve into deep analytical ef- melodic creativity. forts, which, after all, are not the primary message of a composition. For Boolean operations, clarity may be achieved by separating parts into different voices or making them disjoint, without overlapping parts. For the transformations, it is important to create a certain evidence of the correspondence between transformed parts, like in the Beatles piece, where the retrograde of the first motif is played right after the original motif. For the deformations, it is important to keep the distance short between the original and deformed shapes. For example, in a normal context, it would be confusing to deform a melody by raising or lowering pitches by an octave.
10.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension As a first test of the above methods of melodic creativity, we would like to present two examples of such constructions from our own compositional works. Example 4 In this example (see Figure 10.8), we look at the main theme of Joomi Park’s composition Black Summer, see chapter 23 for a thorough discussion of the CD Passionate Message where the composition is included. Part A is a minor second descending interval. Part B is an extension of part A. Part C has the same interval property as B but puts the lowest note in the middle. Part D starts like B, but the third note is one octave higher. Rhythmically speaking, the theme is divided into a double sequence of three eighths (the first eighth of the first sequence being given in the initial chord), followed by equally long (2 × 3 = 3 × 2) three two-eighths groups. This is a
68
10 Melodic Aspects
perfect example of using Boolean operations (the parts!) and transformations between these parts to build the global anatomy of the main theme. Joomi develops the main theme as follows (see Figure 10.9). The second appearance T’ of the theme in the treble clef is a fifth higher than the original theme T. The third version T” of the theme is a locally inverted shape, with ascending contour. This Fig. 10.8. The main theme and means that the four parts A, B, C, D of its four components in Joomi Park’s the original are inverted and yield four new composition Black Summer. parts in the same order in version T”. The shape Tp is derived from the parts C and D of T”; it refers to it in its inverted shape and intervallic content (minor ninth). The shape Tp’ is the same as parts C and D of T”, and it is repeated again in Tp”’, while interweaving the Tp and Tp”.
Fig. 10.9. Joomi Park’s development of the main theme.
Example 5 This example stems from Guerino Mazzola’s CD Synthesis [73]. It is the composition’s main theme. It was used in all four movements. In the first movement, the theme was played on percussion instead of pitched instruments. In the fourth movement, it appears twice in the beginning, played by electric bass. The theme is shown on top of Figure 10.10. The lower part of the graphic shows a grid with horizontal onset times in multiples of eighth notes, and semitones on the vertical axis. The theme is shown in red points. The theme is a union of twenty-six three-element motives. They are quite overlapping. Each of the three-element motif is shown at the bottom in blue. The number of each motif is the number stemming from a classification of all three-element motives
10.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
69
Fig. 10.10. The main theme of the composition Synthesis is shown on top. The lower part shows a grid with horizontally onset times in multiples of eight notes, and vertically in a grid of semitones. The theme is shown in red points. The theme is a union of 26 three-element motives. They are quite overlapping. Each of the threeelement motif is shown at the bottom in blue.
that has been achieved using methods of mathematical music theory. We do not delve in these technicalities here. Suffice it to say that every three-element motif is the transformation of exactly one of these twenty-six motives. The transformations include translations, rotations, inversion, etc., from the theory of musical transformations, but see [77, chapter 11.6.3] for details. Therefore, this theme is, in a certain sense, the most general theme as it is composed from all possible three-element motives. Exercise 54 The following composition exercise is to complete a melody based on the given materials. The students are supposed to look at, play, or sing it
70
10 Melodic Aspects
and choose one or two motives to complete one melody. Try to compose another melody from your completed melody, using transformations and deformations.
Fig. 10.11. Four motives to be completed to a theme.
Look at the four motives in Figure 10.11. These are the motives: 1. 2. 3. 4.
B♭-major, light and oily A-minor, lyrical E-minor, 5/8 time signature, dance-like atonal, strong expression
Examine carefully what property/possibility the given material has. Try to compose out of it, developing from the original, keeping the initial ideas, and also contrasting the original. Try to apply transformations, too, such as inversion. See the examples of The Beatles’s Michelle, and Beethoven’s work in the last example of this chapter (see Figure 10.13). Try several different directions once you have composed. For example, when you have composed an ascending melody, then try to compose a melody with the same given material but descending, and so on. As discussed above, Boolean operations are important to imagine the localized possibilities and their connections. Also try different contours, different leaps, different articulations. Think about all options to create a good melody, and choose the best. Example 6 As a last example, we want to mention that Beethoven, in his famous Hammerklavier sonata, op. 106, used only one basic theme, a chromatic zigzag of a minor third, as shown in Figure 10.12. All his motivic and thematic
10.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
71
Fig. 10.12. Beethoven’s germinal zigzag theme in op. 106. (The formula e6 G means the temporal shift of G by six time units.)
work is derived from transformations of parts of this germinal theme. One example, a vertical shearing of the zigzag, generating a melodic unit (Allegro, measures 75-76), is shown in Figure 10.13.
Fig. 10.13. A vertical shearing transformation of the zigzag in Allegro, measures 75-76.
11 The Contrapuntal Aspect
Counterpoint is perhaps the most critical topic when it comes to the search for creativity. In fact, counterpoint is strictly codified and taught as a sort of catechism of classical compositional discipline in polyphony, the art of combining several voices to a balance interplay. In its most formalized shape, counterpoint has been described in Johann Joseph Fux’s famous treatise in 1725, Gradus ad Parnassum [44]. It was written in Bach’s time but consciously refers to Fux’s idol Giovanni Pierluigi da Palestrina (February 2, 1526 (or possibly February 3, 1525) - February 2, 1594). In the foreword, Fux even stresses his conservative position: “Why should I be doing so (writing about music) just at this time when music has become almost arbitrary and composers refuse to be bound by any rules and principle, detesting the very name of school and law like death itself.” This last sentence could have been written in our time where everything seems to be possible. Our challenge will be to inspect the deep structure of this theory to discover its inherent potential for a creative extension. In view of the role of counterpoint pedagogy in music schools, this seems to be an important enterprise. Counterpoint is commonly understood as a frozen knowledge that at best can serve as a gymnastic exercise in compositional rigor, but never as a tool that one would actually use for contemporary composition. It is amusing to see that even progressive present music theorists appear somehow shocked if any attempt to bring counterpoint to new horizons is undertaken. See [118] for such a case, where the mathematical models of generalized counterpoint designed and programmed by Guerino Mazzola, Daniel Muzzulini and Jens Hichert [77, Part VII], Julien Junod [60], and Octavio Alberto Agust´ın Aquino [3] have been attacked in defense of classical counterpoint as a perfect catechism for eternity. This situation refers to a core problem in music that we have already pointed out in chapter 5: Are composers required to follow eternal rules of music theory or are we still in that early stage (the Planck time) of human thought where the final laws are not found yet? We hope that the students of G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 11, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
73
74
11 The Contrapuntal Aspect
composition will be inspired to think about this fundamental question when working through this tutorial unit.
11.1 What Is Your Open Question? Let us get started with the simplest situation in Fuxian counterpoint (see Figure 11.1). We are given a melody line, called cantus firmus, c.f. Classically, it is composed according to the style of Gregorian chant, but this is not important for our concerns. The contrapuntal assignment is to invent a second melody, called discantus, to be added to c.f. and fulfilling certain rules. In our example, we have the simplest case, called first species, where over each c.f. note we position a discantus note of same duration. The contrapuntal rules give us constraints of how to position these notes. There are two parts of this rule system. The first part is completely rigid: It allows us to set a discantus note over the c.f. note only if the interval (number of semitone steps) from the c.f. to the discantus note is a consonant interval. This means that this consonance can be either a prime (or unision) (0 steps, same pitch), a minor third (3 semitones), a major third (4 semitones), a perfect fifth (7 semitones), a minor sixth (8 semitones), or a major sixth (9 semitones). We may also use intervals derived from these when adding an octave (12 semitones)—for example, the octave (0+12 = 12 semitones), the minor tenth (3+12 = 15 semitones), etc. All other intervals are called dissonances, and they are strictly forbidden. In our example, numbers above each interval are the steps in the C-major scale, i.e. 5 stands for the fifth (the fifth note above e), 8 for the octave (the eighth note above c), etc. The second of the
Fig. 11.1. The contrapuntal assignment is to invent a second melody, called discantus to be added to cantus firmus (c.f.) and fulfilling certain rules.
contrapuntal rules prescribes which intervals may succeed which intervals. In this rule system, one distinguishes between perfect consonances (prime, octave, fifth) and imperfect consonances (thirds, sixths). Further, different movements from one interval to the next are described: direct motion: Both voices ascend or descend; contrary motion: One voice ascends while the other descends, or vice versa; oblique motion: One voice moves while the other remains on the same pitch. Here are the fundamental rules as stated by Fux:
11.1 What Is Your Open Question?
75
1. From one perfect consonance to another perfect consonance one must proceed in contrary or oblique motion. 2. From a perfect consonance to an imperfect consonance one may proceed in any of the three motions. 3. From an imperfect consonance to a perfect consonance one must proceed in contrary or oblique motion. 4. From one imperfect consonance to another imperfect consonance one may proceed in any of the three motions. Essentially these rules are rule one and rule three, and the others just allow for any motion. In particular, one is not allowed to move from a fifth to another fifth by rule one. This is the famous “forbidden parallels of fifths” rule. One may also summarize these rules in a single rule: Any motion to a perfect consonance must be contrary or oblique. Exercise 55 Take the same cantus firmus as in the example of Figure 11.1, but compose another discantus according to the above rules. These rules are very formal, but they intend to produce a double gesture of cantus firmus with discantus that alternates between perfect and imperfect intervals. In fact, once you are at a perfect interval (prime, octave, perfect fifth), there is not much of a choice to move to another perfect interval, therefore you want to go to an imperfect interval, where the choice is larger. But again, what we experience in music is not these formal properties, but rather a well-shaped pairing of voices, one that has a dynamic power. The rules seem too be the formal result of a principle of interacting forces. But what is the force guiding this interaction? It is somehow related to the inner life of consonances, but it is unclear how this happens. Our open question therefore might be this: What are the forces that drive the contrapuntal movement of voices? Remark 1 Let us stress the situation in regard to musical creativity that we meet with the formal contrapuntal rules. There is no valid artistic or scientific behavior that would just accept formal rules without asking for their generating thought and impulse. When we look at Fux’s rules, they are totally empty, and there is no reason to follow them except for historical imitation of Palestrina’s style. But this cannot be of interest to anyone who takes the responsibility for what is constructed. It is paradoxical, but it seems that it is exactly the absence of responsibility that has favored the dissemination this musical catechism (like any catechism disseminates as a package of empty forms of indoctrination), and it is not coincidence that the question-answer style between master Aloysius and student Josephus of the gradus is also the style of catechism. We are not claiming that Fux’s rules are wrong, but we strongly ask for their generative content since no creation can ever be accomplished on the formal surface. Creativity must always delve into and extend meaning and content. Please refer to section 19.1.2 for an in-depth presentation of this characteristic of creativity in our approach.
76
11 The Contrapuntal Aspect
11.2 Let Us Describe the Context! The context of our question is multifaceted. On the one hand we recognize the melodic context: Counterpoint deals with a multiplicity of melodic voices. We have seen the cantus firmus and discantus voices here, but the general setup deals with three, four, or more voices. Second, the intervallic aspect refers to harmonic considerations. Consonances and dissonances are harmonic functions on intervals. They are not Riemannian (no T, D, S values here), but have two values κ (for consonant) and δ (for dissonant). We do not consider more complex chords, only intervals. And it is a strict theory that attributes to six intervals exactly one value. And that value is also invariant under octave extension, i.e. consonances are defined on pitch classes modulo octave, this is the so-called octave equivalence. We might therefore define the set K = {0, 3, 4, 7, 8, 9} of consonant intervals (of pitch classes), whereas the complement D = {1, 2, 5, 6, 10, 11} contains the dissonances. We use here the domain Z12 of the twelve chromatic pitch classes with semitone steps, which might be best represented by the common clock circle that has twelve hours (0, 1, 2, 3, . . . 11, Fig. 11.2. The sets K (red 12=0 (!)), and where every hour represents a key squares) and D (blue cir- on the piano, up to octave. Then K and D unite cles) of consonances and dis- to Z12 , i.e. K ∪ D = Z12 and have no interval sonances. They cover the in common: K ∩ D = ∅ (see Figure 11.2). This set of all twelve intervals setup in counterpoint is quite exceptional because of pitch classes, contain six the perfect fifth (7 semitones) is consonant as we intervals each and have no expect it from Pythagorean tradition, but the percommon elements. fect fourth (5 semitones) is dissonant, which contradicts the Pythagorean tradition and the acoustical theories about consonance altogether. Counterpoint is not an acoustical theory since the simple frequency ratio 4:3 for perfect fourth is not an argument for consonance. We learn that counterpoint is a highly symbolic theory that is independent of acoustical reality. It is a construction for the sake of composition of melodies, not for frequency ratios. The allowed consonant intervals are a kind of gestural movement from c.f. to discantus, and the entire discantus melody could be understood as the final position of a big sweeping gesture starting at the c.f. melody. The common understanding of counterpoint is that its Latin etymology, “punctus contra punctum,” point against point, means the interval’s note ‘points’ are opposed to each other. The discantus is then viewed as a ‘vibrational’ deformation of the c.f. It is straightforward that such a vibration requires the consideration of the forces of ‘elasticity’ that relate c.f. to discantus.
11.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls!
77
11.3 Find the Critical Concept! In music, the movement of voices and their interplay express a dynamic exchange of forces that creates the interesting connections of parts not as static entities, but as poles spanning and being spanned by a force field. This is a remarkable phenomenon in musical syntax: Although its components look like static structures, they are in fact the visible part of an entire system of tension and relaxation. We therefore suggest to focus on the critical concept of a contrapuntal tension and relaxation. Before delving into the details of this investigation, we should remark that the idea of musical forces has been forwarded by famous theorists, such as Arnold Schoenberg. He often speaks about forces between chords in his classical treatise [107] on harmony (nothing dodecaphonic, just classical harmony!). He even uses the metaphor of sexual attraction and repulsion between chords. Of course, this is utterly anthropomorphic, chords certainly have no sexual impulses whatsoever, but it is not a far-fetched idea at all that chords are more than static structures and by this added property create a dynamic force field of harmony in a composition. In mathematical music theory [77], we have described a model of tonal modulation, i.e. the change from one tonality to another, that is based upon a force concept derived from certain symmetry transformations. This model is capable of simulating Schoenberg’s modulation theory, which he described in [107].
11.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! When we talk about tension, the first question that arises is about its direction: between what and what does the tension span? The first answer might seem to be obvious: It spans between the two voice gestures, and this is what common understanding of counterpoint suggests. But then, why should this be a tension? We have only consonances that move the c.f. to its discantus. What kind of tension can this be? The second wall is the question about the nature of such a tension: What is creating the force between the tensed parts? It is also a wall because in view of the first wall, we do not see any kind of tension within the consonances.
11.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! The first wall looks quite hard. The only direction that is visible is the gestural movement from c.f. to discantus. This is due to the fact that the classical construction of counterpoint begins after the c.f. melody has been built. But let us look more carefully at a composed counterpoint in the sense of a gestural movement. We have the c.f. gesture, and this one is taken as a starting point of a gestural movement toward the discantus gesture. But if we look more
78
11 The Contrapuntal Aspect
carefully, this “hypergestural” construction (gesture of gestures) consists of a sequence of tiny intervallic gestures. We first build the c.f. gesture and then successively move in each interval to the discantus gesture, see Figure 11.3, where this movement is indicated by a vertical arrow.
Fig. 11.3. Two interpretations of counterpoint as a hypergesture. The first is a hypergesture of melodic lines from c.f. to discantus. The second, a hypergesture of intervals, is more aligned with to the original contrapuntal thinking.
But this is not mandatory. One may also view the resulting counterpoint as being generated by a hypergesture that moves horizontally from left to right. And this one would then take each interval gesture and move it to the next interval to the right. This alternative is a very simple special case of what in gesture theory is known as the Escher Theorem: One may always exchange the order of generating gestural movements, see chapter 24 for a detailed account on this far-reaching principle. Is this reinterpretation musically reasonable? Historically speaking, it is, since it has been shown that the concept of punctus contra punctum was not the vertical opposition of voices, but the opposition of successive intervals. In other words, the concept of a point (punctus) in this contrapuntal approach was the entire interval! Each interval is thought of as a kind of ‘thick’ point, a point in the contrapuntal space. This is completely natural. The contrapuntal idea takes intervals and moves them around. This is not in contradiction to the Gregorian construction of the c.f line, but it tells us that the tension has another direction: The movement proceeds from interval to interval, although the intervals are all germinating from the c.f. notes. Does this opening help approach the second wall: the nature of the contrapuntal tension and relaxation? The question now is no longer about a tension between c.f. and discantus notes, but between successive consonant intervals. We are looking at the set of consonant intervals and move around in this set. But can there be any kind of tension on this seemingly compact set of consonant intervals? After all they are all consonant. This is true, but we know that there are intervals that are more consonant than others: Some are perfect, the others are imperfect. It is interesting that in the historical development of contrapuntal theories, imperfect intervals have also been called dissonant; see [102] for a detailed account on this terminological finesse in the history of counterpoint! The question about this second wall would then be whether the set of consonant intervals bears something dissonant and whether
11.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls?
79
some intervals might be infected by a dissonant character, and then moving from perfect to imperfect intervals would be a hidden change from consonances to dissonances. So think about consonance and dissonances less as given qualities, but as properties you may redefine in your own creative context. For example, a minor second and the tritone are “consonant” in the system no. 78 to be discussed below. In fact, many contemporary listeners don’t feel uncomfortable with the tritone.
11.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? The opening of the first wall refers to what can be done for the second wall. We are confronted with the set K of consonant intervals. We are searching for forces that might explain the tension between successive consonant intervals. The next question is therefore about the nature of such a tension. Obviously, this is a deep problem since it regards the very definition of consonances and dissonances. How are they characterized? Is there any chance to conceive of such a tension from a deeper understanding of the dichotomy of intervals defined by splitting them into the complementary sets K, D? We have already seen that there is no acoustically valid definition of consonances in counterpoint, since the perfect fourth is dissonant, whereas the perfect fifth is consonant. Also observe that no acoustical theory of consonances would allow for a strict separation of consonances from dissonances; there are only degrees of consonance in acoustical theories. Let us look how these theories would define consonances. They would define a function (like Euler’s gradus suavitatis function) that would be evaluated for each interval and yield more or less high ‘sonance’ values. But this is not the only way to define K! One may also define the whole set instead of first collecting its members. There is, in fact, a beautiful way to do so and to arrive at the set K. The solution looks like this: We look at all splittings of the ensemble Z12 of all intervals (of pitch classes) into two six-element complementary sets (X, Y ), i.e. X ∪ Y = Z12 and X ∩ Y = ∅. But how do we find our exact candidate (K, D)? We have a first very important property of this splitting namely that there is exactly one symmetry that maps each element of K to an element of D, and vice versa, and this symmetry is A(x) = 5x + 2. It is called autocomplementarity symmetry. Exercise 56 Verify that the formula A does indeed map K onto D, and vice versa. And check that there is no other symmetry (a function of the shape f (x) = ax+b with all variables in Z12 ). For example, we have A(7) = 5×7+2 = 37 = 1 in Z12 , the perfect fifth is mapped to the minor second. This formula means that every consonance is turned into a dissonance, and vice versa.
80
11 The Contrapuntal Aspect
In Mathematical Music Theory [77, chapter 30], it has been shown that there are essentially1 only six such interval dichotomies, called strong dichotomies. Here they are, together with their unique autocomplementarity symmetry; their number relates to the classification theory in [77, chapter 30]: 1. No. 64, Δ64 = (I, J) = ({2, 4, 5, 7, 9, 11}, {0, 1, 3, 6, 8, 10}), A64 (x) = 11x + 5. 2. No. 68, Δ68 = ({0, 1, 2, 3, 5, 8}, {4, 6, 7, 9, 10, 11}), A68 (x) = 5x + 6. 3. No. 71, Δ71 = ({0, 1, 2, 3, 6, 7}, {4, 5, 8, 9, 10, 11}), A71 (x) = 11x + 11. 4. No. 75, Δ75 = ({0, 1, 2, 4, 5, 8}, {3, 6, 7, 9, 10, 11}), A75 (x) = 11x + 11. 5. No. 78, Δ78 = ({0, 1, 2, 4, 6, 10}, {3, 5, 7, 8, 9, 11}), A78 (x) = 11x + 9. 6. No. 82, Δ82 = (K, D) = ({0, 3, 4, 7, 8, 9}, {1, 2, 5, 6, 10, 11}), A82 (x) = 5x + 2. Besides the last dichotomy, which is the classical Fuxian consonance and dissonance dichotomy, we have another remarkable one: number 64, the first; its consonant part is precisely the set of proper intervals of C-major from the tonic! This one is therefore called the major dichotomy. But why choose the last one for the classical consonance and dissonance concept of counterpoint? There is a beautiful geometric reason: It is the one in which the images A(x) of intervals x have the largest number of third intervals to be connected to each other. This means that A82 throws x farther away than every other autocomplementarity function. For example, the fifth x = 7 is mapped to A(x) = 1, the minor second, which is two minor thirds away. Also, the distances among all six consonances in K in terms of number of thirds between any two of them is minimal; they are grouped as tightly as possible, but see [77, chapter 30] for details. Therefore, the classical consonance-dissonance dichotomy can be chosen (among the six strong dichotomies) for its geometrically extremal properties. This is all OK, and we are viewing five other dichotomies on which one could potentially focus. But is this game helping us understand the nature of contrapuntal tension? We still have not understood how we could import the dichotomy of consonances vs. dissonance into the part K of consonances as suggested by the idea of perfect/imperfect consonances. The situation is really dramatic: On the one hand, we have to move from consonance to consonance, and on the other, we would like to move from consonance to dissonance. This is a plain logical contradiction. It is, as long as we view the entire setup as a configuration of sets of intervals. But we should see from the very definition of these strong dichotomies that they are effectively defined by their autocomplementarity functions. This 1
This means that any such dichotomy of intervals is isomorphic to one of these six under a symmetry of the intervals, see [77, chapter 30] for these technicalities.
11.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls?
81
is what we should really take care of. The sets as such are of secondary relevance. Can we try to move from a given consonance ξ to another consonance η as if the latter were a dissonance? This would mean that we have to construct a limiting line between ξ and η that turns the latter into a kind of dissonance. Exercise 57 Try to find ways to view such a limiting line as a separation between consonances and dissonances. Exercise 58 Think about the concept of consonance and dissonance in your music. Didn’t you just try to avoid the traditional concepts when creating unheard music? Why don’t you define your own concept of consonance and dissonance? The major seventh could be a consonance, depending on how you treat it in your music. Yes, you, our model student, are right: Why not just transform the consonance-dissonance dichotomy (K, D) such that parts of D overlap with K? And such that η, but not ξ falls into the transformed part of D? Let us make a picture of such an idea (see Figure 11.4). To the left you see the two halves K, D covering the interval set. The transition from one consonance to another would be the problem when living inside K. But we could, for example, add a tritone (6 semitones) to K and to D. That would yield Δ82 +6 = (K +6, D +6) = ({0+6, 3+6, 4+6, 7+6, 8+6, 9+6}, {1+6, 2+6, 5+ 6, 6 + 6, 10 + 6, 11 + 6}) = ({6, 9, 10, 1, 2, 3}, {7, 8, 11, 0, 4, 5}), and we see that the image of minor second 1 is the perfect fifth 7! So 7 appears as a transformed dissonance (see right half of Figure 11.4). If we had the consonance ξ = 3, then the consonance η = 7 would be a transformed dissonance, i.e. a consonance that is on the other side of the transformed dichotomy (K + 6, D + 6), while 3 is a transformed consonance. In this way we may move from one consonance to another consonance but move from the ‘imaginary’ dichotomy’s consonant part K + 6 to its dissonant part D + 6. In our example this would enable us to move from the minor third to the perfect fifth, a movement that we observe in our very first example in Figure 11.1 from the third to the fourth interval. The idea here is that we simulate a separation of consonances from dissonances by a ‘deformation’ of the (K, D) dichotomy that would create imaginary consonances and dissonances within K. We would understand this deformation as the result of a force action (the transformation we used above!) upon (K, D) to make it produce the imaginary dichotomy. In the theory of this approach, it can be shown that such deformations in fact strongly relate to what physicists call “local symmetries,” which are responsible for force fields. Good, but is this a reasonable approach? Does it produce the rules that Fux has given to us in his catechism of counterpoint? The answer is yes, it does. In particular it produces the forbidden parallel of fifths and no other forbidden parallels, see [77, chapter 31.4]. Summarizing, we have proposed an extension of the wall of tension by local symmetries, which transport the dichotomic tension of (K, D) into K. But we
82
11 The Contrapuntal Aspect
Fig. 11.4. We may move from one consonance to another consonance but move from the ‘imaginary’ dichotomy’s consonant part K + 6 to its dissonant part D + 6.
have much more than this interpretation of tension in terms of symmetries of intervals: We now have five other strong dichotomies, Δ64 , Δ68 , Δ71 , Δ75 , Δ78 on which we can try to compose contrapuntal music! This type of creative work is not one of direct compositional work, but one of the invention of new strategies to compose contrapuntal music based upon other concepts of interval consonance. We retrieve the classical theory but also five new contrapuntal worlds in which to be creative.
11.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension Let us first make a small example of a first species counterpoint on another dichotomy. We are taking the major dichotomy Δ64 and allowing ‘consonances’ to be the intervals in its I part. This yields a composition as shown in Figure 11.5.
Fig. 11.5. We take the major dichotomy Δ64 and allow ‘consonances’ to be the intervals in its I part. This yields the composition as shown.
It is evident that such an extension of contrapuntal worlds provokes a number of questions and also a number of new tools that might be helpful
11.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
83
for composing in these new worlds. To begin with, we have a software that was developed by Julien Junod [60] to compose contrapuntal works in all six worlds. Second, one may ask about the relationship between works in different contrapuntal worlds (the worlds associated with the six strong dichotomies). Junod has succeeded in solving the following problem: Suppose that you are given a counterpoint composition X1 according to the rules of contrapuntal world W1 . How can you deform X1 to a composition X2 that follows the rules of contrapuntal world W2 ? He has systematically investigated all possibilities. And now his software can take any nice Bach counterpoint (well, it is still species one, but the idea is clear) and deform it into a composition of any other world. We refer to his dissertation [60] for technical details.
Fig. 11.6. Left: the strong dichotomy of class No. 78, together with its unique autocomplementarity symmetry. The ‘consonances’ are the six red pitch classes. Bottom: The numbered intervals of the score of Figure 11.7 are shown at the bottom.
Another test would be to look for modern composers and to see whether they have been working with dichotomies other than the classical ones. Let us just look at one, to which this book is closely related: Joomi Park’s composition Black Summer, which is included in our CD Passionate Message discussed in the case study of chapter 23. It has been created without any conscious reference to the contrapuntal worlds described above. It is therefore remarkable that she uses the dichotomy of class nr. 78 in her interval selection. The left hand of this homophonic composition is dominated by five of six intervals from the ‘consonant’ half {1, 3, 5, 6, 9, 11} of the dichotomy (see Figure 11.6). Let us look at the score as displayed in Figure 11.7. These intervals occur in an agreeable and relaxed way as if they were normal consonances. The
84
11 The Contrapuntal Aspect
Fig. 11.7. The intervals of the left hand are belonging to the ‘consonant’ half of the strong dichotomy No. 78. The numbers of the intervals relate to Figure 11.6.
traditionally consonant unison in the last line then surprisingly appears as a tension! It plays a dissonant role. And it is remarkable that it is ‘resolved’ to a series of minor seconds in the last measure, since the (consonant) minor second is the interval that corresponds to the unison under the autocomplementarity symmetry of the dichotomy! In view of these examples, we urge the student to work in one of the non-classical strong dichotomies to create new contrapuntal compositions with a different flavor of the tension between ‘consonances’ and ‘dissonances’.
12 Instrumental Aspects
After a series of abstract sound-oriented topics of creativity we want to consider a practical aspect of music: musical instruments and how they are played by humans. We give an in-depth description of the physical theory of instruments in the theory chapter 21, and especially in section 21.1.2 devoted to technical question regarding the making of sound. Here we focus on the creative rather than the descriptive aspect: How can we be creative when we play an instrument? It might have been observed by the attentive reader that we are looking at humans playing instruments, not computers, player pianos, or other machines. This is not by coincidence, and the reason is that we should first learn to understand what making music is about before we delegate this (still poorly understood) phenomenon to machine-made imitations. But be aware: Our limitation is about those who operate instruments, not the instruments themselves. Instruments can be fully computerized—however designed for human use beyond pushing buttons. See the section 17.3 for more thoughts about computer models of creativity.
12.1 What Is Your Open Question? It is well known, and Beethoven and Schoenberg are no exceptions here, that performers are commonly understood in their ‘waiter’ role of ‘serving’ the music sound, which was conceived and written on paper by those ingenious composers; there is no more, and no less than this delivery. They are executors of orders given by higher instances, much like the MIDI (Musical Instrument Digital Interface) slave paradigm has realized making music as electronic slaves (see 21.3.2 for details on MIDI). The reality is very different. To begin with, classically important instruments, such as the family of violins, are hard to play; the musician has to go through a long and hard educational process until a reasonably agreeable sound can be produced. Second, the shaping of sounds is extremely important G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 12, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
85
86
12 Instrumental Aspects
to expressing the contents of the scores in a significant way. Playing the score literally as written is like eating a deep-frozen pizza. The instrument is not merely a machine that upon pushing some dead buttons produces sounds as prescribed by the score. This is wrong even when playing piano, where one is inclined to think of the keys of being such sterile buttons of sound command. Although pushing a single key with a determined fingertip velocity might be a trivial action, the connected operation of the hand’s movement upon the piano’s keyboard cannot sound intelligent unless the hand connects and integrates the single keystrokes in a quasi-dancing gesture. Hitting the keys is only the moment where the dancing hands touch base on the ‘instrumental stage.’ Playing an instrument is only valid if we view it as a complex interaction of the musician’s body gestures with the instrument’s user interface. We are far from understanding this interaction in the concrete making of music. We do not know about the resonance dynamics between the musician’s gestures and the musical invention, be it in composition or in improvisation. Therefore, it is a good choice to pose this open question: To what extent does the instrumental interface define music?
12.2 Let Us Describe the Context!
Fig. 12.1. Neanderthal flute excavated in Slovenia.
Fig. 12.2. Digital drumpad from Yamaha.
The context of this topic is triple. First of all, we are dealing with a physical device, the so-called instrument, which generates acoustical sound events by a specific and mostly sophisticated action of human body limbs (hands, feet, lips, arms, legs). The inner life of such an instrument is an extremely important and variable material configuration, spanning from simple mechanical constructions (such as the Neanderthal bone flutes excavated in Slovenia, see Figure 12.1) to extremely complex electro-acoustical devices such as a digital drumpad (see Figure 12.2). Second, this instrument’s output is an expression of a system of signs, called a composition1 . A composition is highly symbolic and is viewed as a 1
We disregard here improvisatory constructions to make the open question more profiled.
12.3 Find the Critical Concept!
87
mental entity whose instrumental realization is not even necessary; the composition is understood as existing independently of the instrumental realization. Third, this context includes the performer’s body, whose complex gestures act upon the instrumental interface but are not merely abstract commands to produce sound mechanically. This context is highly artistic and essential for the production of a valid performance. There are musics in which gestures are even the essential part and do not rely on any kind of written composition, such as free improvisation or traditional oral music cultures such as the traditional Korean song genre Pansori, performed by a singer with percussion accompaniment. Exercise 59 Describe these three contextual components for different musical traditions, such as hip-hop, rap, and Indian music. Consider different epochs and cultures.
12.3 Find the Critical Concept! Although the complexity of playing an instrument is known among performers2 , it is communicated exclusively on an oral basis, and this culture is not communicated to composers and theorists. We therefore want to stress a critical concept that contains all those disconnections between instrumental performance and what one could call ‘paper music’ of the scores. The critical concept we would like to choose looks harmless (and this is one of the tricky points of walls!), namely to play. The concept is critical because it seems so obvious that playing is what an instrumentalist does. However, the concept is ambiguous: It means to play an instrument, but also to play a composition. But these two targets of playing are totally different. How can this splitting be understood as one and the same thing? It can be done if we recall that there must be someone who plays the composition on a specific instrument. Although the action of playing focuses on the compositional objectives, it is the agent of this action, the human performer, who gives the whole enterprise a reasonable shape. But this agent is not only hidden in the verb “to play,” it is also downsized to a person who plays a game, an individual who leans back and games with some instrument and composition somewhere ‘down there’. The connotation of a gaming activity brings up the social role of a performer: He/she is just a kind of (hopefully) agreeable gamer, and the historically well-known low status of performers might be related to this (dis)qualification, whereas the composer is perceived as being a divine creator. Exercise 60 Compare the activity of playing the violin to playing soccer or chess. What are commonalities, what are the differences? 2
. . . and even more when it should be creative.
88
12 Instrumental Aspects
12.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! From the above we learn that there is a wall in the critical concept of playing, namely the disconnection between the two aspects: playing an instrument versus playing a composition. The essence of this wall is the hidden agent connecting these two perspectives. How is it hidden, what is there more than in a soccer game? The common access to this wall is that the musician plays a given composition, that set of creatively compiled symbols, on an instrument to produce the sounds symbolized by the composition’s score. This is the deliverer role of a performer: to humbly bring the composer’s dignified creation to the audience.
12.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! In order to soften the wall of disconnection, we should first of all recall the genealogy of a score. Historically and also for a good number of composers, the score is not the first creation, but a symbolic projection of instrumentally generated gestures. Western music notation is an abstraction from neumes, which signify gestural contents, small movements that ultimately became casted into rigid note symbols. We are not alone to have characterized the score as a repertory of frozen gestures, in this characterization of Western notation. We are joined by authorities such as Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno, Roger Sessions, Renate Wieland, and Manfred Clynes, the latter having even claimed that “score notation kills music” [89, chapter 14]. And a number of acclaimed composers, among them Beethoven, who shaped many compositions from his improvisation at the piano, do create music from their own anatomically driven performing action much more than from abstract symbols [68]. Exercise 61 Without seeing a score, listen to legendary pianist Vladimir Horowitz playing Scriabin’s Po`eme op. 69, No. 2. Imagine how the notation would look. Listen again, now with the score. Are you surprised about the simplicity of the notation? And there is even no time signature change. The piece itself is short and shows a small number of musical ideas. Think about how interestingly Horowitz unfroze the score by not following any clich´e but actively directing the interpretation of the composition, which would sound “flat” without such expressive shaping. This a major reason why the audience enjoys Horowitz’s performance so much. Exercise 62 Play Scriabin’s Po`eme op. 69, No. 2 with a music software (Finale or Sibelius, for example) that only plays the written symbols. Note the difference to a performer’s rendition. This means that the waiter metaphor is wrong insofar as the composition is the paper projection of an originally gestural creation. Not all composers are aware of this fact, and they might even disregard (consciously or uncon-
12.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls?
89
sciously) the gestural origin of score notation and compose directly from score symbols. This is not forbidden, but it guarantees a musical success as much as combining arbitrary deep frozen ingredients would yield a good meal when unfrozen3 . It is known that some composers of the so-called New Complexity style effectively disregard the playability of their frozen symbols and turn the evident deficiency into a compositional strategy (see Figure 12.3). We do not condemn this approach, but it is symptomatic of a culture of seemingly dead and disembodied utterances, a culture where works titled Mouvement (– vor der Erstarrung) f¨ ur Ensemble [64] or Pray for Death [37] become fashionable. If you only pursue the complexity of the scoring, for example, a sixteenth subdivision simultaneously with a nineteenth subdivision, then don’t be surprised somebody already did it before you. Once the relationship to the composition that is being played is reconsidered, the role of the instrument radically changes. It is no longer the mechanical interface that makes available some ‘knobs’ and ‘buttons’ to output a planned sound object, instead it plus a fundamental role in the making of music. The sound you produce is only the last member of a long and complex chain of actions and reactions upon the instrumental interface. Once the performer no longer has the waiter’s obligation to move a determined message of symbols to sound, the question of the inter- Fig. 12.3. A typical contemporary complex face’s nature and function arises. music score. We are dealing with an emancipation of the instrumental interface from its symbolic drivers.
12.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? The emancipation of the instrumental interface does not mean to put aside scores and start everything from scratch on the instrument. But it suggests that we might reconsider the perspectives offered by the interaction with the instrumental interface before we go back to reproduce abstract symbols. To begin with, we should reconsider the interface as an expressive surface, as a stage, where the musician dances instead of simply pushing buttons. Let us give two examples of such an interpretation. The historical example is the traditional Japanese Nˆ oh theater (see Figure 12.4). The stage of this art is not 3
Pianist Mitsuko Uchida in an interview on her performance of Schoenberg’s Piano Concerto, op. 42 mentioned that Schoenberg does not consider performative instrumental aspects.
90
12 Instrumental Aspects
only a passive surface, it is an instrument because it is built above several big drums that are hit by the actor when he stomps on the stage’s floor. The actor is a drummer, his dance a drummer’s action. A similar stage instrument, the floor xylophone XALA, was invented by Swiss musician/dancer Ania Losinger (see Figure 12.5).
Fig. 12.4. Nˆ oh theater stage with drums below main stage (below Shite).
Fig. 12.5. Ania Losinger dancing on the floor xylophone XALA.
It is not true that such a stage configuration is only realized for these large dimensions where humans dance, because we encounter the stage situation also for common instruments, such as the piano or the violin, and, of course, the drum set. Cecil Taylor, the monstre scar´e of free jazz piano, has stressed that he tries to imitate a dancer’s leaps with his hands. And playing the violin is such a complex interaction with the instrument’s body that it is not exaggerated to call it a dance gesture (see section 21.1.2 for details). All of this goes far beyond what is traced on a score’s symbolic language. It is not an ornamental action added to the ‘real’ music, but it defines music as such. The sounds that are associated with such dancing expressivity are not the music, but its acoustical outlet. One could even state that music deals with sounds among others, and that the dancing reality is the comprehensive statement of this art. The score’s symbolic reduction must be unfrozen and deployed into a dancing gestuality in order to make something that deserves the name of a work of music.
12.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension To test these extensions, we recommend that the student take a score and perform it in a dancing movement, that he/she try to dance the composition instead of focusing on the simple sounding surface. Exercise 63 Choose a composition you like and listen to it from a dancing point of view. Try to imagine the dancing movements of the piece. Choose a simple and familiar composition you like and play it as a dancing expression.
12.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
91
Exercise 64 Think about the restrictions of the notation system. It is straightforward to play a score following all of its restrictions. But think about how you could actively realize the score’s performance as your own creation. Example 7 In Asia classical music education has produced a huge number of good professional performers. They are definitely well represented on the global stages, but the critical point is that their education usually has one ideal way of performing that everyone is eager to reach: Standardized posture, demanding techniques, and even pianistic attack. We have to be aware that this kind of education may endanger the arists’ performing personality. We should be aware that listeners actually enjoy the presence of the artist’s unique individuality. Have a look at one of the videos showing extremely individualist pianists Vladimir Horowitz, Glenn Gould, or Fazil Say. Do you enjoy their nice delivery of the score or their own personality in performance. It doesn’t sound the composer’s piece anymore, but has become theirs. Let us conclude with an example of a different approach to performance and composition as conceived in the dance paradigm. Example 8 This example thematizes the question of designs of new musical instruments following the approach of a dancing creation. There are many such instrumental interfaces, mostly using gestural tracker systems that translate to sound output. Let us just mention, for example, the work of Andrey Smirnov at the Theremin Center of Moscow State Conservatory, or the work of Jared Bott, James Crowley, and Joseph LaViola Jr. exploring 3D Gestural Interfaces for Music Creation in Video Games [16]. Refer also to New Interfaces for Musical Expression, also known as NIME, an international conference dedicated to scientific research on the development of new technologies for musical expression and artistic performance [93].
Fig. 12.6. Musical instruments are played through several gestural interfaces. Clockwise from top-left: drums, guitar, violin, theremin. Figure from [16].
92
12 Instrumental Aspects
Let us just recapitulate an interface for musical composition, the BigBang rubette developed by Florian Thalmann, which is discussed in the Boulez case study in chapter 25, section 25.5. Besides the classical input of musical compositions via MIDI files, his interface allows for graphical input of note objects by the mouse; one can directly draw sets of notes. And then such material can be manipulated with most general geometric transformations defined by three-finger gestures on a trackpad. It is also possible to squeeze and stretch such music data in nonlinear form, for example compressing the beginning of the composition and expanding it successively toward its end. This means that we can manipulate musical objects in a direct intuitive way of gestural interaction. Our recomposition of Boulez’s Structures pour deux pianos as described in chapter 25 has used these tools of gestural creation.
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism
In this tutorial we want to think about dealing creatively with a given musical system. There are many such systems—the traditional Western tonal system is one of them, and other cultures have their own systems, such as Indian Raga with its mela scales, or the traditional Korean musics like Pansori, Pungmul, Sanjo, Nongak, etc. with pentatonic scales. In what follows, we want to investigate a system that is an ideal candidate for such a reflection: the serial composition technique. It is an ideal candidate for our tutorial because it has been invented from scratch; it has no dark and complex historical roots and can be viewed as an experiment in musical composition systems. Moreover, the serial system is particularly simple and explicit. Its rules are clear, and it is operated more like a game than a deep musical thought. It has inspired musical composition during the first two-thirds of the twentieth century but has also paralyzed essential aspects of music, such as new directions in harmony or generalized tonality. Serialism was invented in pitch dimension under the title of dodecaphonic composition technique by Arnold Schoenberg around 1921 and realized in his first dodecaphonic composition, the Waltz for Piano, op. 23, No. 5. Later, the dodecaphonic idea was extended to all other parameters— duration, loudness, and attack—and then called serialism. The motivation for Schoenberg’s invention was a deep dissatisfaction with the systems of tonality and associated harmony in the first two decades of the twentieth century. Composers had transgressed the system of classical harmony; its theory was no longer applicable and left composers in a chaotic field of unoriented creativity called “free atonal music.” Schoenberg invented his dodecaphonic compositional technique as a theoretical ‘counterpoint’ to the principles of tonality—in particular, he wanted to ‘emancipate’ dissonances, which had been degraded from Pythagorean theory to classical counterpoint as standardized by Johann Joseph Fux. Let us describe the dodecaphonic idea before we delve into creative manipulation of such a system. Schoenberg’s idea was to give all pitches of the chromatic scale the same chance, as opposed to tonal music, where the tonic and dominant play a strong role against the other pitches. As he did not add G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 13, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
93
94
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism
any other conditions, he postulated that we have to select these twelve pitch (classes) each once, in any of the possible 12! = 479, 001, 600 orders. And such a selection is called a 12-tone or dodecaphonic row. For example, the first row in Schoenberg’s own compositions was the row of the Waltz for Piano, op. 23, No. 5, it shows the pitch sequence G = (1, 9, 11, 7, 8, 6, 10, 2, 4, 3, 0, 5), with 0 ∼ c, 1 ∼ c♯, . . . (see also Figure 13.1). For every composition one has
Fig. 13.1. Arnold Schoenberg’s first dodecaphonic row for his Waltz for Piano, op. 23, No. 5, published in 1923.
to make a choice of such a row, which is then called “Grundreihe” or “tone row.” For probably historical reasons, Schoenberg then permitted generation of a paradigmatic field of derived rows by use of the group F of all 48 transformations f that were allowed in classical counterpoint: 12 pitch transpositions, 12 pitch inversions, 12 retrogrades, and 12 retrograde-inversions. This generates a set F.G = {f.G|f ∈ F } of 48 derived rows. An example of the original row, together with inversion, retrograde, and retrograde-inversion is shown in Figure 22.1. Exercise 65 Calculate the set F.G of the 48 derived rows for our example shown in Figure 13.1. This is nearly all of the system! Schoenberg allowed distribution of any collection of such derived rows on our composition, and the temporal sequence
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism
95
of row entries was quite elastic: One may also display a subsequence of notes in a row as a chord. Figure 13.2 shows an example from Schoenberg’s op. 33.
Fig. 13.2. An example of a dodecaphonic composition from Arnold Schoenberg’s op. 33.
We see the tone row G, starting at (transposed to) b♭, then its retrograde inversion KU , starting at a, then the same KU , but starting at a, then the retrograde K, starting at e. Observe that the first row G has chords, so from that representation of the row, the original order of G cannot be retraced since the order of the notes in a chord hides the order in which they have been placed on the chord. This problem is also the case for the general question of retracing the original tone row from the composition. If we are not given the patchwork of rows but only the resulting set of notes, it is often impossible to find out the patchwork, and then even knowing the patchwork, it is often not possible to find out which is the original tone row. In fact, any of the 48 paradigmatic variant could be the original one. Besides the a priori impossibility1 to retrace the construction from the resulting composition, Schoenberg also has not given any additional rules for how to distribute such derived rows. Anything goes—no harmonic or contrapuntal or rhythmical rules are required. They may be played in temporal overlapping as shown in our example in Figure 13.2. There is no syntactical rule in dodecaphonism. And this is a significant difference to the tonal system, where 1
By analytical activity, but even more when listening to a performance of dodecaphonic music.
96
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism
harmony also prescribes certain rules of syntagmatic order, e.g. the cadential order T, S, D, T. Perhaps to compensate for this totally chaotic syntagmatic display, huge attention has been given to the internal structure of a tone row. For example, a row may show all proper intervals when stepping from one pitch to its successor. Such a row is called “all interval row.” Dodecaphonic rows have been completely classified, see [39] for a reference. Dodecaphonic composers sometimes were so proud of their rows that they even would patent them (Schoenberg did so!). The composers thought that their rows were hiding a mystery of inner beauty that, hopefully, would be revealed in the course of their deployment in compositions as built from the 48-element row matrix derived by transpositions, inversions, retrogrades, and retrograde-inversions. In serialism, the idea to organize pitch in rows was later generalized to other tone parameters and was conceived in 1947 by French conductor, composer, and writer Ren´e Leibowitz. In 1952 and 1961, Pierre Boulez composed a famous piece, Structures pour deux pianos, I/II [17, 18], where he not only prescribed a sequence of twelve pitches, but also of twelve durations, twelve loudness values, and twelve pianistic attack modes. See our case study relating to this composition in chapter 25. In the following tutorial unit, we somewhat deviate from the previous presentations in that we shall not only present a creative aspect of a theory but also question the theory, namely the serial system, in the sense of transcending it in its totality. But we shall not just reject the serial system and replace it with still another one like Schoenberg did with the tonal system. We want to help students open their minds to new directions without necessarily having to rebuild a system to compose new music.
13.1 What Is Your Open Question? It is undeniable that music history and cultures all over the world have invented systems of musical thought and musical composition. And it is also unquestionable that these systems have helped generate a big number of musical compositions complying with these frameworks. In philosophy, systems have also been constructed and rejected. It has become a major challenge in philosophy to overcome such systematic approaches and to take philosophy beyond systems. In music, we also want to thematize this approach and to ask whether musical systems are a necessary condition for composing music with a thorough discipline. So let us ask this open question: What can be the role of a musical system for the composition of valid musical works? Exercise 66 Describe some musical systems that come to your mind. Don’t worry about precision or technical vocabulary, just use your natural language to specify them in your understanding. For example, the system of traditional
13.2 Let Us Describe the Context!
97
Korean music has pentatonic scales with many sliding techniques producing microtones in performance.
13.2 Let Us Describe the Context! Let us collect the ingredients that constitute musical systems. 1. They are all built on a set of available sound events, be they defined by pitch collections (such as scales in tonal music) or rhythms or melodic repertories (such as series in dodecaphonism). 2. This material can be manipulated following a set of rules (such as the selection of chords in tonal music or transformation of series in dodecaphonism). 3. These rules must be built according to a defined logic and be logically consistent, i.e. contradictory rule conflicts should not be possible. For example, the contrapuntal rules must be defined in such a way that the composer is never led to dead ends in the contrapuntal construction, i.e. to situations where the continuation of a contrapuntal construction is impossible because of too strong constraints. 4. The rules must be of a certain simplicity to enable constructions of compositions with a reasonable effort. Simplicity also means transparency. A rule system that can only be controlled by a computer is not what we aim at; there is not substantial delegation of musical creation to external devices and authorities. 5. These rules must be communicative in the sense that compositions that follow these rules make them evident to the audience. Rules that are beyond communication are possibly interesting to the composer in his/her intimate work, but the system has to solve the problem of transferring them into the musical utterance. 6. These rules must be flexible enough that musical creation is possible and even boosted. They must be catalyzers of musical invention and not only directives that kill the composer’s fantasy. It is like with traffic rules: They enable maximal freedom within the logic of a working traffic system. 7. The system must help create musical meaning, not just forms. This is in accordance with our principle of creativity as a generator for new meaning in music. We have chosen to discuss the serial system in more detail here because it is very explicit in its structure, in particular with regard to the possible production of new contents. It was not grown from long historical processes of evolution, but introduced as a creation initiated by one man in a very precise moment and for very precise reasons. Schoenberg even believed that this system would guarantee German music a dominance for the next hundred years! So this invention was conceived as a strong motor for future musical creation. It is a bitter irony that its Jewish inventor was exiled from Nazi Germany in 1933.
98
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism
Exercise 67 Listen to Schoenberg’s Waltz for Piano op. 23, No. 5 published in 1923. Does the composition inform you about the six ingredients of a musical system described above? Play the composition’s row shown in Figure 13.2. Try to hear the row or one of its transformations when listening to the waltz.
13.3 Find the Critical Concept! Within a musical system, there is a core instance that may be called the primary motor for the construction of musical works, and this is the set of rules, together with the primary material that is fed into these rules’ action. Let us therefore select the concept of system rules as the critical concept. The system’s rules play a mysterious role. On the one hand, they enable what the composer might want to construct; on the other, they direct and restrict his/her production. It is the admitted or hidden hypothesis of a system’s architects that these rules may foster creative production. In terms of contemporary cognitive science, one may restate this attitude as a construction of artificial musical intelligence. It is assumed that such rules encode processes that are responsible for well-formed and ideally interesting musical output. In the case of serialism, the rules are very simple: Take a series and generate its 48 derived series by musically standard transformations inherited from the successful tradition of contrapuntal composition that had matured since Palestrina’s early days in Western art music. And it is argued that the basic material, the series, has also been built following a generative principle that guarantees a balanced display of all pitches available in our standard semitone chromatic repertory. The first problem of this approach is the creation of meaning. How do we step over from such formal constructions to new contents? This must be seen from the condition that all these serial devices do not rely on any of the known semantics. How can a row set up contents? And why do the 48 paradigmatic variations thereof help build a story in the composition? A story of what? What is the thematic power? Is the series a theme? And if yes, how does the theme unfold in the course of the composition? Is this unfolding communicated to the audience in any perceivable way? Is it a secret story that can only be understood in an intense introspection while listening to this music? These questions are extremely important to the composer—and ultimately also to the audience. Can he/she be creative while applying such rules? What is the space of freedom that serial construction offers? To answer these questions, we have to inspect the walls of the critical concept. What are the limits, and what is the potential of these rules when working as a creative composer?
13.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! When we are applying a set of rules, we think of the situation as an automatic mechanism that could be delegated to a computer. In serialism, our model sys-
13.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls!
99
tem, we would program the computer to generate any series and then calculate the 48 variations. We could then do anything with this material. The theory does not add further rules, so any random walk would do in the spreading of such variations over the score. The same algorithmic approach can be made for counterpoint, harmony, and other systems. In such an approach, the subject which applies the rules has been eliminated. The rules have become formulas that yield output upon any materially admissible input. This is the approach used by American composer Tom Johnson, who has devoted much of his compositional efforts to get rid of the individual and subjective layer of composition. His string quartet Formula is typical for this approach: Each of the eight movements is based upon a mathematical formula. The wall of the rule concept is exactly this seemingly unavoidable constraint: to apply the rules. The wall properties of this situation are characteristic for walls: They are so strong and omnipresent that even the question about their necessity and function seems absurd. They are part of the definition of the concept. A rule is there to be applied, what else? But this is exactly the moment where we have to step back and look at the complete context of musical composition. To reduce compositional activity to apply a rule system is a huge step. What happens in this process? Are we playing an empty game, or is the system so strong and intelligent that we are dispensed from rethinking everything once we have understood the logic and power of these rules? It could be the same as with mathematical formulas: Once we understand a formula, we can implemented it in a calculation program and do more interesting things than unwrap the formula each time we have to use it. Let us recall that one of the greatest successes of metro-nome inventor Johann Nepomuk M¨ alzel was his chess automaton (see Figure 13.3), where he cheated everybody with a machine that could play chess better than most humans. His career ended abruptly in Cuba. He died from alcohol poisoning on the seaway back to the U.S. shortly after it was discovered that he was hiding a chess-playing dwarf in the machine’s innards. This episode nour- Fig. 13.3. M¨alzel’s chess automaished many dreams of artificial intelligence ton showing a Turkish puppet playing seemingly machine driven chess in the arts. It is a typical example of peoand the dwarf who was in reality ple’s dreams of a machine system that cre- playing the game. ates something intelligent and artistically valid.
100
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism
13.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! The formulaic approach to composition by a system of formal rules is a style of depersonalized activity. The agent is hidden if not eliminated. The rationale is manifest: The rule system is supposed to be powerful enough to produce intelligent and interesting musical structures. But can formulas take over the roles of composers? Let us look at a very classical formula: the cadence sequence TX → SX → DX → TX of tonic, subdominant, and dominant chord functions in a given tonality X. If the essence of the cadence formula were this sequence, any realization thereof by a set of chords would do. But this is exactly what does not guarantee any interesting musical output. In tonal music one could argue that voice-leading rules must be added to the cadential formula, and so forth. But is that a sufficient rule set for interesting music? It is not. We are always facing this situation: The set of rules is exhausted, and we still do not have interesting music. In serialism it is the same situation, and even simpler: How could any random distribution of row variations on the score generate interesting music? We have known a number of sophisticated computer-driven systems of accompaniment in improvisation, e.g. [5]. They are defined by refined mathematical formulas, but it is always a failure. Our experience is that the formula congeals music rather than nourishing it. To be clear, we neither defend nor attack the claim that a rule system can produce intelligent music. It is something different that fails. And this is hidden in the meaning of the verb “to apply,” which we identified as the wall of the rule system. It is obvious that this keyword reminds us of the wall in the tutorial on instrumental aspects in chapter 12. Recall, that wall was about the nonconnection between the two aspects: playing an instrument versus playing a composition. When we face the wall of applying a rule in this chapter, we have a similar conflict: We just bring the formula to the audience. We are waiters of the formula and hope the client will appreciate the precooked meal. And we also had the critical concept “to play” in chapter 12, and here we have a similar one, “to apply”! In our analysis of the instrumental aspect, we could resolve the wall of “playing” by a reconstruction of the composition’s original movement, which is a dancing gesture that is performed on the instrumental stage. Is there a similar solution here? Can we go to the rule system in its early state where it was, like the neumes, not a dignified authority, but a living organism, so to speak? If “playing” could be resolved by “dancing on the instrumental stage,” then the rule system’s execution resembles the application of the theater’s screenplay. If we may dance the composition, should we then also choreograph it instead of applying the screenplay’s prescriptions? Recall that in dance, choreography is also beautifully known as dance composition. In other words: Could we replace the rule system’s screenplay with a choreographic autonomy?
13.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls?
101
Exercise 68 Think about the difference between a playwright and a choreographer of a dance. Who is responsible for what? Could you compare the author’s written play to a musical system’s symbolic rule system, while a choreographer is more concerned with the the system’s embodied performance?
13.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? Let us try to extend the wall of rule application with the last section’s question on choreography or dance composition. What does a rule system look like if we choreograph it (with autonomy) instead of applying it faithfully? First of all, we have to appropriate the system; it must become ours instead of us being its slaves or delegates. This means, in particular, that its components must also be given a meaning that we cover with full responsibility. We (the composers) cannot refer to contents that are charged to others—all of it must be ours. If, for example, we use a row of pitches in serialism, it must be ours, meaning that we know and are fully responsible for the row’s pitch sequence. We must know why we have chosen this row and no other, and we must express this choice musically, not only as an abstract and private thought. It must be created and presented like a theme in the melodic process, full of anatomical shape of which we know(!), and ready to be unfolded in the composition’s screenplay. Otherwise it is exactly like a composer who says “I use a tonal system” but the audience cannot realize any tonality. There is no Platonic sky (the ‘refrigerator’ of deep-frozen gestures) where abstract ideas are deposited; we have to make them move here and now. Second, and this relates to the first point, we must communicate the system’s substance in the compositional work. This is why no formula can be applied as is; we have to unwrap it and to unfold its ‘innards’ in the compositional result. This is a delicate point because we do not want to be the delegates of an absent divinity. We follow Aesop’s sportive imperative: Hic Rhodus, hic salta! (Here is Rhodos, jump here!) This means that all of the content we are thinking about when composing should, if ever possible, be materialized as a concrete musical substance, notes, pauses, whatever. A theoretical system of thoughts is not what we show in choreography, we show the musical shape and its body. This is a hard and exhausting requirement, but we have to meet it, otherwise there is no opening of the rule application wall. Choreography means to drag to the sensible surface of musical realm those system rules and materials. Let us look at the situation in serialism to illustrate these points. To begin with, when we present the original tone row X, we have to make sure that it is perceived and fully understood by the audience. It is absurd to play it just once and then go on to whatever variated versions. We have seen in Figure 13.2 the first presentation of the row in a compact shape even containing chords. This
102
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism
is definitely not the choreographer’s approach. It is nothing but Schoenberg’s “private music”2 world. It is not trivial and annoying at all to insist on X before stepping to other things. A row is a complicated object, and its transformations are also tricky variations of the original. Similar to a tonality, it needs a cadential statement: Here I am, have a firm look at me. We could, for example, play X several times in different time modes, or different dynamics, or different instruments, etc. We also could blow up the single notes to multi-instrumental big sounds with a temporal unfolding in long durations. Exercise 69 Listen to Gy¨ orgy Ligeti’s beautiful composition Lux Aeterna for such long-lasting sound effects. Exercise 70 Listen to Pierre Boulez’s Structures pour deux pianos, a prototype of a serial composition, beginning of the first part, to see how one should not present rows in serialism. Exercise 71 Suggest other ways of making the tone row X more approachable in the beginning of a serial work. When we play a first transformation of the tone row, why should anyone recognize this one as a variant of the original? A composer can, of course, refute such a transparency, but why? There must be a good reason for doing so. Perhaps does the composer attempt to install a seemingly independent second row? But if he/she does not want to create this independence, then all efforts must be made to communicate this relationship. Otherwise it is like a modulation in tonal music but the composer has no idea how to modulate. If the second row is just a transposition, this is easy, because everybody recognizes transpositions as transformed versions, but it is not easy to perceive dependency when the row is inverted or retrograded. Exercise 72 Try to compose the inversion of tone row X in such way that the relation to the original can be perceived by the audience (and not only by analytical efforts). The problem relates to the idea of developing the theme (the original tone row X in our case) into a story or choreography, as you prefer. We want the listener to say: “Aha, now they step over this variant, I hear the correspondence, wow, so interesting that the original can appear embodied in this new shape.” It must be a pleasure to listen to the second shape. The pleasure can only occur if we deploy the transformational process into the musical material, and not only in our heads. 2
He is famous for his anti-audience and anti-communicative elitist attitude.
13.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls?
103
Example 9 Here is an example of communicating row inversion by decomposing the original row in a sequence of small two- to three-note motives X1 , . . . Xk and then playing after each Xi its inversion I(Xi ) with a second voice/instrument before proceeding to the next unit, so we get the sequence X1 , I(X1 ), X2 , I(X2 ), . . . Xk , I(Xk ). After that we could play the entire inversion I(X) at once and proceed with this one. If the inversion of the first row is the meaning of the second row presentation, then please, communicate this meaning. The story must be choreographed and danced, not only conceived.
Fig. 13.4. The four measures 124-127 in op. 106, Allegro, showing an inversion that is responsible for the following modulation from G-major to E♭-major.
Fig. 13.5. Left: pitch-onset points in measures 124-127; right: all pitches transposed to one octave, showing that the first two measures are inverted at g (equivalently tritone d♭) to yield the third and fourth measures.
Example 10 Let us give a second example of materializing musical thoughts. Beethoven was a master of such techniques. See Figure 13.4 for the score’s shape of our example. If we look at the pitch-onset points described by this part, we see in Figure 13.5 that Beethoven composed an inversion-symmetric configuration around pitch g (equivalently tritone d♭), which maps the G-major scale to the E♭-major scale. Summarizing our extension, we may say that we have to complete the rule system by choreographing it for the sake of communicative embodiment of
104
13 Creative Aspects of Musical Systems: The Case of Serialism
materialized musical gestures. It is not so much the system per se that is put into question, but its musical realization. Nevertheless, we have to relativize the significance of a system in favor of the possibilities it offers and the options we have to make music out of abstract rules. In this sense, the serial system is a particularly weak corpus, because it lacks the most important features for creating musical compositions.
Fig. 13.6. The modulatory process induced by an inversion at d♭ in measures 11-12 in Guerino Mazzola’s sonata composition L’essence du bleu.
13.6.1 Another Extension We have focused on the composition realization of the serial system without asking for the extension of the system as such. Let us do this now to complete the perspectives opened with this discourse. The serial system is built upon two components: (1) the initial material, the tone row X, and (2) the group G of symmetry transformations that are applied for the creation of the 48 variants of X. One may break up this catechism with two initiatives. They result from the fact that X and G have no intrinsic connection, they are totally independent choices. This means that we can replace X with any initial material Z and also, independently of this choice, replace G by any system H of transformations or deformations. Young composers are, in fact, often annoyed with having to follow the classical serial rules. This means we used the serial system only as a raw material and not as a system, like paint and canvas to make a painting. They now can free themselves from these constraints: On the one hand, they may use a row X because is offers a wide perspective on pitches that must be used. This can help invent interesting melodic structures that are incorporated in a tone row. But they may then use their own system H to create derived structures. Or they may generalize the row X to a non-dodecaphonic structure and then use the given group G to generate its derived specimens. Or
13.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
105
they may quit altogether these two standards and apply a generalized system H to a generalized initial structure Z.
13.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension We have applied Beethoven’s modulatory idea in our sonata composition L’essence du bleu [79]. Figure 13.6 shows the modulation process from Cmajor to B♭-major in measures 11-12. This compositional part is built around the inversion symmetry around d♭. Exercise 73 Try to compose a dodecaphonic series X and make it evident to the listener in your score. Then, take a transformation thereof and add it to the score so that the transformation becomes evident. Exercise 74 Think about the dodecaphonic system as a system in your music. How does it affect your piece when composing differently from your previous approach. Think this time about the dodecaphonic system as a raw material. Then it is not your system. What do you need to add when composing. Compose each case and find out what is more suitable to your compositional style. Exercise 75 Read Fred Lerdahl’s critique of serialism in the article Cognitive Constraints on Compositional Systems [66]. Do you agree with his opinion?
14 Large Form Aspects
The topic of large forms is a culmination of our previous tutorials: All of them converge to this one, as can be seen from the leitfaden (Figure 3.1). This means that large forms use all of the preceding aspects: systemic, contrapuntal, and instrumental—of course including their own predecessors. But what are large forms? We have dealt with small forms: melodies, harmonies, rhythms. Large forms are combinations of smaller forms to express added meaning to the contents given by small forms. We stress “smaller” here in the sense that a large form is a combination of already defined forms, but these forms may also be large forms (well, not so large, but not ‘atomic’ either). The idea is a recursive one: We start with really small ‘atomic’ forms: elementary melodies, harmonies, rhythms. We then build combinations thereof, and then combinations of these combinations, and so forth. The complexity of these constructions depends on the complexity of contents the composer wants to build. But the essence is that musical contents result from such multiple interlocking of parts. To get a concrete idea of forms, we first look at two simple examples of large forms of the same size: the period and classical developmental sentence (see Figure 14.1). They are considered to be prototypes of a non-atomic form. Both are usually eight measures long and are built from two-measurelong phrases. Phrases are also not atomic, but they constitute minimal closed statements, similar to a linguistic sentence. In both sentences, you see the first phrase built from motives a and b. The second phrase in the period is one motif, c, whereas in the developmental sentence, the second phrase is a nearly literal repetition of the first phrase with transformed and deformed motives a′ , b′ . This repetition is characteristic of the developmental sentence type. In the period, this repetition with transformed and deformed a′ , b′ is postponed to the second half of the period (the consequent, following the first part, the antecedent), while the phrase c first develops the motivic statement before the initial phrase is repeated. To understand the multiple interlocking method in large forms, let us look at the sonata form. This one is considered really large in this chapter. AccordG. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 14, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
107
108
14 Large Form Aspects
Fig. 14.1. The period and the classical developmental sentence with their phrase parts a, b, c etc.
ing to the standard concept of a sonata form, the movement contains four parts, to be played in temporal succession: exposition, development, recapitulation, and coda. Each of these parts is itself a highly complex large form, which we do not further investigate here. Rather, suffice it to say that the form is a rhetorical one: The exposition presents a theme, possibly together with secondary subjects; the development unfolds the theme and its consequences, the recapitulation comes back to the theme after the insights of the development have been exposed; and the coda concludes the sonata form. Each of these parts has its own parts and parts of parts down to single periods, phrases, and motives. The sonata form’s parts may also include complex harmonic processes such as tonal modulations. For example, the Allegro, the first movement of Beethoven’s op. 106, is a sonata form and displays eight modulations, starting and ending in the sonata’s main tonality B♭-major. The sonata form is, however, not the global form of a sonata. Often, as a standard, it is just the first Allegro movement’s form, while other movements—a slow Adagio movement, then a dance movement Scherzo, and finally the faster Finale movement (often again in sonata form)—follow. The four-movement sonata is frequently used in string quartets and symphonies. Observe that sonatas with four movements have only one or two movements in sonata form. But we should be aware that composers have always transcended given form norms when they wanted to express a content with a special flavor. For example, in Sonata, op. 109, which we discuss in the case study of chapter 26, Beethoven has written three movements, the third being a big sequence of six variations of a single theme! We are not going to describe the entire classification of large forms. Their types are numerous; one counts more than sixty of them, varying according to their historical position: medieval, Renaissance, Baroque, classical and romantic, or contemporary. We are more interested in the creative potential when
14.1 What Is Your Open Question?
109
dealing with large forms in the sense of how much more they are then a mere accountability of extended musical structures.
14.1 What Is Your Open Question? When looking at the classification of large forms, it seems to be an accountability subject. We see parts A, B, C,. . . and then, for example, the twelve-measure Blues form ABA, or the classical song form of jazz compositions: AABA, with “bridge” B, each part having eight measures, etc. But this is only the trivial external syntax of these forms. It has no deeper musical content and could as well be used for common language texts. The essence of large forms is not their syntactical schemes, but what content is generated under the surface of such a configuration. For a composer, however it is important to set up a balance between the form and the contents he/she wants to express. A form could be compared to a dress that expresses the body’s shape. Both the dress and the body have to correspond to each other. A composition can be overdressed by a form that by far passes the poor contents. And vice versa: A poor form can blur a body’s complex shape. But the dress-body metaphor is also somehow dangerous because the form not only expresses contents, but it also creates them. Let us explain this with an example from poetical creations in language. If a verse rhyme form ABAB is created, we may have “God” at the end of the first A, and then “bankrupt” at the end of the second A. This rhyme position of the two words creates a correspondence that may set up a correlation of contents, like “God = bankrupt,” say. So the formal position of these two word contents adds a content and does not merely describe given contents. This phenomenon has been called poetical function by linguist Roman Jakobson [58]. He considers two axes: first the axis of paradigms, i.e. associative fields of concepts. For example, the paradigm of “car” would contain “automobile,” “van,” etc. The second axis is the syntagm, i.e. the position of concepts within the thread of a text, like the position of “car” in the sentence “Claudia’s car is yellow.” Jakobson’s theory is that any poetical effect is generated by “projecting the paradigmatic axis to the syntagmatic axis.” This means that he is addressing the distribution of associative fields of concepts in the text’s thread. Rhyme poesy is one example of this theory. The idea is that this arrangement of paradigms creates a body of contents that is richer than the sum of the paradigms of its parts. It is not about two independent contents designed by “God” and “bankrupt,” but about the increase of contents setting “God = bankrupt” because of their syntagmatic position. In this sense, the construction of large forms is not only a distribution of given contents, but the anatomy of a form also creates added content values by the relationship of the paradigms defined by their positions within the formal architecture. In other words, the dress is not only a passive expression of the body, it also defines the body. Therefore, we suggest that the open question
110
14 Large Form Aspects
here is about the relationship between the external shape of a large form and the content of a composition written in such a form.
14.2 Let Us Describe the Context! The context of this topic relates to strategies of larger musical content creation. How can we compose musical works that compile complex aggregates starting from atomic structures? This is definitely a topic in music semiotics, the theory of music signs. The semiotic context is more precisely that of semantical production in the sense of Jakobson’s poetical function: What is the mechanism of poetical contents creation in musical large forms? Observe that we cannot transfer linguistic premises one-to-one to music. There is a difference here in that linguistic contents are given from common contents, it is not necessary to explain the common meaning of the words “tree,” “love,” “eternity” in a poem. In music, this first condition fails, and we have to apply radically different strategies in content generation. This difference is dramatic: We cannot rely on externally created contents, so the musical form must take the full responsibility for whatever it contains. But observe that the contextual question also has a historical dimension— every semiotic system has its diachronic evolution—and this may be responsible for contents. In language, every word has its etymological development—for example, “discipline” stems from Latin “dis-capere,” “to cut into pieces,”— that is a strong historical root for the word’s content. In music, we also have this weight if the musical language of a composer and his/her audience share a strong historical reference. For example, in Western culture, nobody can cite Beethoven’s main motif of his Fifth Symphony without evoking the Beethoven reference. But in the musical environment of one of the numerous small Indonesian islands, this may be without any semantic charge (meaning). Such a historical reference need not stem from a musical community. One can also create a ‘historical’ reference within a single work by repeating a motif so often that the listener ends up recognizing the motif as a returning base point. Michael Cherlin [24] has related this to the idea of memory in music, and he distinguishes three types of memory: reference within a work, reference between different works, and reference to topics outside works. The latter case is the exception: We are given a content of human life and compose as an expression of such content. For example, Gy¨orgy Ligeti admitted that many of his musical networks stem from an early recurrent dream he had where he was captured in a fetid, nauseating spiderweb.
14.3 Find the Critical Concept! We have seen that large forms deal with the creation of content in music. Couldn’t we just take this concept, “musical content”, as the critical concept
14.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls!
111
of this tutorial unit? We could, but this would not hit our main concern in musical creativity. The critical concept is not content as such but its expression in a poetical musical communication, so let us call the concept meaningful expression. Let us also explain this choice. We stress expression here, not the meaning. We do so because the creation of content is not the critical aspect; it is a semiotic operation that can work if done in a logically clean way. Accordingly, Schoenberg, in his book on principles of composition [108], refers to two criteria for a good large form: logic and coherence. The criterion of coherence, if it is not a logical one, must be an aesthetical one, dealing with the refined connection between parts in a large form. Schoenberg adds that composing a large form is not comparable to a child who juxtaposes wooden cubes; the composer creates a living organism, not just a collection of separated material units. But the logic of this organism is not sufficient, it needs to be complemented by an elegant connectivity. And we should add that this connectivity should be a movement between parts, like a living body that is not just a collection of dead of limbs but lives by their smooth interaction. The composer has to become aware that his/her composition has to express its contents; it is not sufficient (as Schoenberg believed1 ) that music is true, but it must also express truth in an aesthetically valid way. One could call this requirement a rhetorical one, one that tells you something that is true ‘anyway.’ But this is not what composition is about. It is about embodiment, about making and not merely representing. Unlike mathematics, there is no abstract reality where the musical truth is deposited, so that the composer has to pass it to the audience. We saw already in our tutorials on melodic and systemic aspects that the waiter’s role of serving a precooked meal is not what music is about. The truth of a large form’s logic can only be realized in its embodied communication: in short, in its poetical expression. In his famous definition of musical contents in [49], Eduard Hanslick states: Der Inhalt der Musik sind t¨ onend bewegte Formen2 . This provocative claim unites the form and the content.
14.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! What can be a wall of meaningful expression? The concept has a mysterious aspect because the content is deeply intertwined with its formal aspect. It describes a seemingly paradoxical situation in that the two components, contents and form, are combined in a circular reference of seemingly complementary constituents: content ⇆ form. If a composer wants to compose in a creative way, this circle must be resolved. It is a hard wall, since circular configura1
2
Musik soll nicht schm¨ ucken, sie soll wahr sein. Music should not ornament, it should be true. Musical contents are sounding moved forms.
112
14 Large Form Aspects
tions often have a vicious character, and vicious circles3 are the dead end of a thought—it destroys itself in an impossible configuration. Our hope is that this circle is not vicious!
14.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! In order to understand the nature of this circle wall content ⇆ form, we have to investigate the nature of contents and then see what are the general construction principles of contents. For a more in-depth discussion of concept architecture, please see section 21.3.6. If we look at how a concept is structured, it becomes clear that most concepts are understood by some kind of reference to other concepts. For example, if you talk about a musical motif, this refers to a set of notes, and a note refers to two (or more) coordinates: pitch, onset time, etc. So talking about a motif refers to other concepts. This implies that the content of the word “motif” refers to the content of the word “note,” and this refers to the contents of the words “pitch,” “onset time” This is the general principle: You refer to other already-conceived concepts, and then to a method to derive the new concept from these antecedents—in this case, a set of notes, and for each note a list of coordinates: pitch, onset, and time. This example is typical: concepts refer to (1) other concepts, and (2) specific building methods starting from these other concepts. So the contents of a concept are constructed from contents of already-built concepts and the architectural methods to step from these preconceived concepts to the new one. Contents are built referencing other contents; they are recursively constructed from other contents by well-defined reference ‘arrows.’ In other words, contents are given by formal schemes to refer to other contents. They are a system of arrow links to other contents. Contents are a formal arrangement of other contents. Of course, this looks hopeless because then we have to ask for the referred contents to understand the new concepts. The latter may also refer to their own antecedent contents, and so forth. The unanswered question is: Will there be an end in such referential recursion? Before answering this question, it is important to acknowledge that content heavily relies on formal constructions, and it is not just an amorphous fact. In section 21.3.6, we present all types of recursive reference architectures in conceptual constructions. Their number is very small, essentially only three types: collections, lists, and libraries. In the above example of a motif, it is constructed as a collection (set) of notes, and a note is a list of its pitch and onset coordinates. 3
Vicious circles are logical constructions that lead to contradictions because of an impossible self-reference. For example, the barber saying, “I shave all men in this city who do not shave themselves,” is such a circle: If he shaves himself, he would be one of those who do not shave themselves. If he does not shave himself, he should shave himself. There is no solution to this logical problem.
14.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls?
113
There are two answers to the unanswered question: First the reference may end in some ‘atomic’ concept, whose content is elementary for our understanding. For example, if we look at the motif concept, pitch and onset refer to numbers. And we may assume that these concepts are somehow ‘atomic’ to the music theorist. The second answer is that a reference can also be an autoreference or circularity: a reference to itself. For example, the Fourier series of a sound, describing its partial tones, is defined as a list consisting of (1) the fundamental sinusoidal wave, and (2) the overtone series, and this latter one is again a Fourier series! But see section 21.3.6 for details. This discussion of conceptual architectures makes clear that contents are built from • •
the form of referential architecture and either atomic first concepts or circular reference (autoreference).
This lesson can be applied to understand the circular wall content ⇆ form of meaningful expressivity. In fact, the first component of contents is a form! Therefore, the circular wall can be understood: Form is one half, so to speak, of content. If we can manage to understand the second half for large forms in music, we have solved the problem.
14.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? Coming back to the musical situation of large forms, the critical concept of a meaningful expressivity, and the wall content ⇆ form, our analysis of conceptual architecture teaches us that we may first have to see what is the formal “referential” half of the concept of a large form. All large forms are defined by the poetical function setup where paradigmatic units are distributed on the syntagmatic axis: They describe a list of parts, such as AABA, or the four sonata movements. So the content of such a form is defined by the contents of its parts, together with the content that is generated by their mutual reference, such as the double repetition of A in the song form, or the repetition of the exposition in the sonata recapitulation. Although such repetitions need not be literal, they pertain to the same paradigm in Jakobson’s sense, but the precise way must be described by opening the form’s architecture of these parts. We see that this way of understanding concepts is completely analogous to what we saw above: The method relies on continued recursion. Before we discuss in detail recursive depth perspectives, we should reconsider the question of how content is generated by the formal display of parts. The most elementary situation is repetition. Why should repetition generate contents? First, the long repetition in time creates a firm grid, to which other musical structures refer. Second, it creates a regularity for a dancing trance movement. Third, a repetition changes the unit’s perception.
114
14 Large Form Aspects
In the case of repeating A once in the song form before stepping over to the bridge B, it makes you listen differently to its content. You may become aware of relations within A that a single listening would not have shown; it expresses a fact to you, the listener. This is useful for understanding the bridge B: We perform a major change of material, e.g. a tonal modulation, and therefore have to be given the reference to A as a starting point of the musical process. Finally, repeating A a second time after the bridge brings us back ‘home’ to the basic structure, which we only recognize as such because it had been played twice before the bridge. In the case of the sonata’s recapitulation movement, this is a repetition, but far from simply doing the same again. After the developmental movement, the original theme looks totally different. We know its ‘inner life’ and therefore cannot play and listen to it again as in the exposition. Also the tonal structure can look quite different from the exposition’s one. It is a second look at the main theme, but it includes and applies all the added knowledge. These are some examples showing how added content is generated by the simple repetitive process within Jakobson’s paradigmatic fields. But the harder problem is the last step when running through recursion: first and atomic concepts or circular reference4 . What can we expect in musical forms when we step down to the very beginning? The atomic concepts can occur. This is a characteristic feature when we build our forms upon motives or rhythms that are known from music history and/or culture. For example, Bach’s motif B-A-C-H (b♭ − a − c − b) is often cited, e.g. in Sonata No. 2 for violin and piano by Alfred Schnittke. The frequent citations of jazz and other musics in Schnittke’s Symphony no. 1 are also famous (e.g. Tchaikovsky’s B♭-minor Piano Concerto, Johann Strauss Jr.’s Blue Danube Waltz, Chopin’s Second Piano Sonata, etc.). Or Arnold Schoenberg’s citation of the popular song Oh, du lieber Augustin in his String Quartet, op. 10. Here the creative action of a composer is to build the formal framework where these semantic ‘atoms’ are embedded and act as motors of added content. The tricky point however is not the original content of these atoms, but their staging as constituents of enriched content. This may typically be achieved via transformations and/or deformations (as discussed in the melody tutorial in chapter 10) as mechanisms that generate new paradigmatic representatives of the atom or of of a derived form. Whereas the atomic approach could be called ‘music about music’, the second type of first concepts, circular reference, is more substantial in that it does not ‘borrow’ contents from elsewhere. Music that follows this constructive 4
In an architecture of concepts, an atomic concept is one that comes first without any further explanation, like “God” in religion, or “negation” in logic. A circular reference is given, for example, if you look up in a dictionary “point.” It usually defines it as, “A point is an element of a space.” And if you look up “space”, it says, “A space is a collection of points.” It does not create any contradiction, it is a nonvicious cycle of first concepts.
14.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
115
approach is often called “absolute music” because its contents are not linked to external references. A fugue is a classical example of such a construction (see section 10.4). The motif of departure is the dux. It is associated with a number of comes variants, which answer the dux as representatives of the same paradigm: They are transformed and/or deformed derivatives of the dux. The form of the fugue sets up a dialogue among these basic shapes, and the content is built by their autoreferential character. This example is fascinating because it simulates a quasi-literary dialogue without having to build upon external semantics. The dialogue makes sense without preconceived contents! Perhaps is it true that literary forms are also not so strongly dependent upon the given contents, but more on the form’s shape (we already mentioned this possible fact in a footnote of section 10.3). An extension of this idea is the construction of a musical drama, which imitates the literary drama with musical ‘subjects’ instead of real world persons. Beethoven is famous for having composed such dramas of absolute music. His music is dramatic in that it tells a complex story of musical motives and gestures without any extramusical references. The body of his music is a drama, and that drama is dressed in a complex form of references between musical subjects in such a way as to express a meaning of unfolding forces and energies. Therefore, our extension of the circular wall content ⇆ form is the attempt to build an inner-musical drama. Although the concept of a drama seems to suggest a temporal development of a story, this interpretation is a too narrow. A musical drama might as well be a development of perspectives of a given basic subject. In Beethoven’s op. 109, which we discuss in detail in the case study of chapter 26, he unfolds the drama as a sequence of variations of a basic structure. This spatial display offers a variety of perspectives upon a subject, whose function is to deepen the understanding of one and the same basic idea. It is an iterated view upon a given object. It communicates the expressive contents of a strong germinal structure and meets the dramatic character of the large form in its intense investigation as a force field of musical contents. It meets the principle that understanding is created by variation of perspectives, like with a sculpture whose shape is understood when one walks around it and looks at the object from all important points of view. Remark 10 If you want to learn more in depth about Beethoven’s deformation of standard large forms, yielding new meaning, please refer to our case study of the six variations in the third movement of Sonata op. 109 in chapter 26.
14.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension To understand dramatic constructions in absolute music, let us look at some beautiful expamples:
116
14 Large Form Aspects
Example 11 Listen to Beethoven’s String Quartet Grosse Fuge in B♭-major, op. 133 and try to describe its dramatic overall shape. Example 12 Listen to Scriabin’s Sonata op. 72 Vers la flamme and try to describe its dramatic overall shape. Exercise 76 Try to set up a thematic germ and compose a dramatic form thereof, using a system of formal parts where you express the germ’s contents in its variety of paradigmatic variations by transformations and/or deformations. Exercise 77 Listen to Beethoven’s String Quartet No. 9 in C-major, op. 59, No. 3, second movement. This movement is written in sonata form. Look at the score and find out where the recapitulation starts. Think about how he treats the recapitulation concerning the first and second themes. Do you recognize the second theme in the recapitulation? If not, think why he had to adjust its conservative role.
15 Community Aspects
This tutorial unit and the next one are a bit different from the preceding ones because these two touch less on the music and more on the human conditions that define the composer’s existence: community and commercial aspects. But we believe that they are nonetheless important to understand the shape music gives to composers’ lives as its creators. Community aspects are a hard topic. Cooper Moore, a relatively successful free jazz pianist and instrument constructor, has, in a recent interview with bassist William Parker [95], stated: “Although we say there’s community, there’s not community.” And he adds that his main concern is paying the rent. We will come back to the latter, but it is by no means an exceptional statement about community. All composers and creative musicians keep stressing that the only thing they care about is their own music—the personal, individual, and exclusive dedication to their music. So should we just cancel the topic and join the lonely genius’s one-man world view? If we recall Schoenberg’s paradoxical Verein f¨ ur musikalische Privatauff¨ uhrungen, his Company for Private Music Performances founded in Vienna after World War I, we would definitely resign from community discussions. Fortunately, there is more. These statements are strong, but if we analyze them, they are not against community as such but express a deep doubt about the community’s relationship to the music that these creators are inventing. They wish to have a better community, after all they are not antisocial, they are simply disappointed. Even the famous and successful free jazz pianist Cecil Taylor, who is known for his uncompromising style and for his extremely critical judgment of community in music, admitted that in his most lonely periods when he had no gigs at all (and was forced to wash dishes and earn money as a cook) he played his unheard rehearsals at home as he would perform for a virtual audience. He had to simulate the communication with music lovers. The conflict is a very clear one: On the one hand, you, the composer, want and must create your own new world of music, and as such you are—by definition—lonely because these new things are only conceived and imagined by G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 15, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
117
118
15 Community Aspects
your individual work1 . On the other hand, you absolutely need recognition by humanity, by the humans who have brought you up, who are your friends and fellows. This latter is an often unacknowledged desire, but it persists—despite some heroic claims of absolute autonomy. The present tutorial unit deals with this tension, and we hope it is able to give you some hints to overcome its existential challenge.
15.1 What is Your Open Question? God must have been very lonely when he created the universe. A composer is not a god, but he/she ideally creates a new small universe. And this makes the creator lonely. But unlike God, the composer has a community of humans (and sometimes also animals) who might be addressed to appreciate this creation. The tension of this situation is that the autonomy of a composer’s works and the appreciation of the human community are not a priori unified and may put each other into question. Cecil Taylor rightly stated, “Nobody asked me to play the piano.” Nonetheless, it is not acceptable to just let things go by without trying to find a solution or at least understand the duality of positions. The open question therefore is about the options that are available to negotiate between these two perspectives: the composer’s musical universe and the community’s appreciation. Let us put it this way: How can the composer’s right to create his/her own musical universe be reconciled with the community’s right to appreciate or refuse that musical universe?
15.2 Let Us Describe the Context! The historical context of musical composition is anything but isolated from community aspects. On the contrary, music was for a long time created exclusively for its social function, be it in religious or social ceremonies or for military targets (execution, march, heroic hymns). For example, in China during Mao’s cultural revolution, music was strictly channeled to its socialist function to support workers’ moral. Also, in certain restrictive present societies, music is still forbidden as if it were a destructive and immoral drug. In modern societies, one might add musical community functions such as Muzak in stores, elevators, and other social environments; entertainment music for dances, parties, and similar fun events; music for media such as films, games, or news background; and music as acoustical furniture. The pretension that music should be an individual world without essential community reference is relatively new and might go back to the Renaissance 1
This is not absolutely true, since creation of new works can also occur in community contexts, such as collective improvisation or technology-supported social music creation, see [114] for the latter. We shall come back to such perspectives later in this chapter.
15.3 Find the Critical Concept!
119
and its discovery of the individual position as an existential analogy to the discovery of central perspective in the visual arts. This does not question the autonomous claim of a composer, but it opens the view to a long tradition of music as a social art, as a functionally determined activity. Therefore, relating one’s composition to community concerns is not artificial and also makes us understand why communities have a tradition in their relationship to music. We have seen in the previous tutorial units that the creation of music in an autonomous individual universe essentially involves creation of new contents, which may be seen as extensions of the given music-semiotic system. If a composer creates such an extension, it is important to address the communication of such extensions to an audience that is familiar with the given system and that may understand the new contents from their artistic expression. This semiotic aspect was not critical as long as musical creation was an utterance in a given musical language, and where new contents were extremely rare. But in present times, when a composer creates his/her own new world, it is no longer guaranteed that any community would understand the content of such new expressions that lack any social acceptance. In other words: If you create new contents, the language that you use might be so far-out that nobody can understand it. You would then have to make extra efforts to create and bring to life a community that is familiar with your newspeak. The community context of musical creation is not only “here and now”, one should be aware that one’s compositions may be understood only after a change of civilization or culture (synchronically) or epoch (diachronically). If a composer is aware of these coordinates, it might be easier to make the targeted community more precise. For mathematicians this is a completely standard situation because mathematical research is usually only digested by a larger community after several decades, if not centuries. This mathematical attitude (which is strongly supported by the scientific community) could be a model for advanced composers, who would then be urged to build an elitist huis clos community of researchers in music. Schoenberg’s Verein f¨ ur musikalische Privatauff¨ uhrungen was such an initiative, and the famous Darmst¨ adter Ferienkurse are also conceived in this avant-garde spirit. The major difference from mathematics however is that the progress that would be achieved in such new music elitism is by far less demonstrable than for mathematics. A mathematician who was invited to a concert by a friend who wanted to offer him a nice evening was asked after the concert, “How did you like it?” His answer: “It was OK, but what was demonstrated after all?”
15.3 Find the Critical Concept! The critical concept for the open question about the composer’s musical universe and the community’s right to appreciate might be relevance, the problem of how important such creation could be, and for whom this matters.
120
15 Community Aspects
The critical concept is very general, but this is fine since the problem is fundamental: It regards the problem of why one should spend one’s life composing new music in light of the fact that there is already so much music, and there are so many more or less standardized ways to build music according to given rules and traditions. In the sciences, mathematical progress is objectively needed; the relevance is obvious. It is even argued among theoretical physicists [96] that any far-out theory in mathematics will sooner or later become a pillar of physics. Of course, Cecil Taylor is right: Nobody asked him to play the piano (in that way). He can do whatever he likes. And so can every composer—one-man universes are not forbidden. They are, however, kind of ridiculous if the artist does not care about the consequences of his/her creations. Schoenberg was also right: Musical composition of large forms is not a child’s playing around with wooden cubes, and we should add that it is not the infantile gaming of a child either.
15.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! Relevance is a delicate word, because it is loaded with instinctive rejection: Who cares? And aren’t we lacking any concrete answer when we deal with the arts? Can the mathematical situation be of any help here? One of the key walls of “relevance” is that it is a serious affair. What is relevant must be taken seriously, it is neither a simple game nor a joke. And this wall is again (like many others we have encountered in this tutorial) hard since it is tied to the very definition of the critical concept. The key point of being serious is that the affair is objectively important, we must recognize it as such and deal with it in an adequate way. There are many relevant affairs that are not taken seriously—until it is too late. Hence we are asked to behave in a serious way, and this is asked of the composers and the community alike.
15.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! So far, the wall makes an impenetrable impression: Is there any means to open this moral attitude? Or are we simply thrown back into outdated ethical categories? To be serious is a communicative category: You care about your work, but you also care about its reception, about transferring the complete message for which you are fighting so passionately. Seriousness is about dedication and precision. We do not believe that it can be achieved in an exclusive conversation with yourself. You need a minimal distance to what you are doing to escape narcissistic love. It is well known that there are always strong issues that escape the auto-conversation, and that communication always strengthens your inner dedication and message. And the community you choose should also
15.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
121
be the result of a reflection about whom you take for serious and who takes you for serious.
15.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? Yes, seriousness is about dedication and precision. We have to open the wall of seriousness and ask ourselves what exactly we want to say, and to whom we want to communicate this concern. We have seen highly talented young composers who were not capable of saying one single word about why and how they are working. This failure must be avoided at any cost to be successful as a creator of works that are relevant to humanity and not only to your own private one-man universe.
15.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension Exercise 78 Think about why you want to compose your works and to which community you want to communicate them to reach a mutual understanding of what you are creating. Exercise 79 Read the paper Who Cares if You Listen? by Milton Babbitt, High Fidelity (Feb. 1958). (Babbitt called this article “The Composer as Specialist.” The original title was changed without his knowledge or permission by an editor at High Fidelity.) This is an article about the problem of difficult music for the general audience. Babbitt compares this music with nuclear physics which is also too difficult for the general public. What do you think about this article? Exercise 80 Imagine your composition is being played in the Carnegie Hall, or any place you like. Imagine that you are the audience, enjoying your piece. Does it cause a doubt or pride to you? does it sound like a one-man world or does it say anything to the audience?
16 Commercial Aspects
When you have put all the ingredients together, from community to large form, you are confronted with the most annoying question: Where will I be positioned in the local or global marketplace? After all, you want or have to make a living out of your profession as a composer. Of course, you can become a teacher or even a university professor of composition and then you have also answered the survival question, but this is not our concern here. We want to think about earning money as a composer, not as a teacher. If you look at the composers’ economic situation, you find that since all have to compose, they must try to survive, whatever situation they may be thrown into. Cecil Taylor washed dishes, drummer Sunny Murray drove a taxi, Conlon Nancarrow was just wealthy, Beethoven was moderately paid for the publication of his works, pianist Cooper Moore’s most important question was how to pay his rent, and bass genius Sirone never resolved his money struggle. Some commercially successful contemporary music composers hate to talk about marketplace, but they know about their advantageous commercial position and simply refuse to talk about that aspect of their profession. Yes, the topic is nasty, and no universal solution is at hand. This is why we should spend some time thinking about creative answers to the money question.
16.1 What Is Your Open Question? Why is the commercial aspect of musical composition so annoying? A quick answer would be that because music is about beauty, passion, and highest spirituality, it is absurd to connect it to the down-to-earth question of making a living. Composers might prefer to live in the spirit of the Bible (Matthew 6:26): “Look at the birds of the air, that they do not sow, nor reap nor gather into barns, and yet your heavenly Father feeds them.” But this attitude is inadequate. Composers do sow, and they do it to a community of their choice. So why shouldn’t they gather? Gather recognition G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 16, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
123
124
16 Commercial Aspects
and income as citizens of a civilized humanity? Why should money only be earned from selling arms, real estate, and animal food? We have seen in tutorial 15 on community aspects that the serious relevance of a composer’s work in his/her communication with a community may establish a relationship of (mutual) appreciation. Why should this appreciation not be reflected in commercial value? But our question is somewhat more delicate: Is the aesthetical value of a musical work beyond any commercial valuation? And conversely: Is every commercial compensation of musical works their automatic degradation to merchandise? So let us envisage this provocative open question: Why shouldn’t money be earned from selling beauty?
16.2 Let Us Describe the Context! The context of commercial aspects of serious musical composition is immediately related to abusing highest human goods—in other words, as if it were “Love for Sale,” to cite one of Cole Porter’s jazz standards. The commercial system is in fact defined by an exchange of goods, of objects you can put onto a shelf to await purchase by a consumer. We have seen in tutorial 12 on instrumental aspects that music—if conceived in its full expressive power—it is a fully engaged dance of humans on the instrumental stage, which is incompatible with detachment and consumerism. How could such an intense existential utterance be deposited on a shelf like a labeled consumer good? Our context is also related to the gigantic music industry, where composers (called songwriters) are the first germ in a complex and brutal machinery between music publishing, performing, and recording, see [57] for an excellent reference. Although we understand every composer’s disgust, a closer look at this environment is important. You have to know about copyright for music works (©) as opposed to music performances (℗), etc. You have to know the copyright protection companies, otherwise you will be a loser whenever you sign a contract with one of those labels or publishing companies. In the music industry, a composer, even if he/she enters with good intentions, will very probably be squeezed until all ideals are eliminated and Cole Porter’s song becomes reality. So the context is that the factual environment is an industrial chimera while the kernel concern of a composer is to create living beauty. It could not be more split.
16.3 Find the Critical Concept! In this split world of commercial and aesthetical perspectives, there is one common concept that challenges all of them, and this is value. What is the value of what you are creating in a musical work? Is there any answer to the question of creating values here that might be valid in both systems? We suggest that our critical concept is this one: value.
16.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls!
125
16.4 We Inspect the Concept’s Walls! It is about values when we confront the creation of musical beauty in a composition with the problem of making a living. In these values there is one common aspect, namely that both are about life: Composing is the innermost value of life and making a living is about life in a very basic sense. The wall that we have to face is the value for life. This wall unites the entire paradox of high artistic aspects of life and its low everyday aspect. This split view makes the theme so annoying: The high perspective is what the composer desires, the low one is what must be suffered. During Mao’s cultural revolution, they killed intellectuals (where anybody who was reading literature except Mao’s red booklet was qualified as an intellectual) or sent them to the farmers to learn about “real life.” It was an ideology that wanted to destroy the “high” bourgeois aspects of life—everything had to be low. A composer had to compose music for workers, not those “useless intellectual and decadent Western artifacts”; see the interview with Chinese composer Gen Gan-ru in [95] for more details. The rigidity of this wall exists in the pair of opposites, “high” vs. “low.” The question is whether we could resolve this tension without destroying one of them in the manner of Mao’s cultural revolution.
16.5 Try to Soften and Open the Walls! To begin with, the polarity “high” vs. “low” of life values is derived from an implicit gravitational force. Low is where you fall when you lose control over your body. High is where you jump when you are in full control. So what is that gravitation of life values, against which Goethe’s Faust was fighting when the uht, den angels welcome him with the promise1 : “Wer immer strebend sich bem¨ k¨ onnen wir erl¨ o sen.”? It is the force of death against which every plant shows its triumph when growing towards the sky. But there is more than biology—it implicitly includes a divinity at which our high aspirations are targeted. There is a perfection and fulfillment toward which we are striving. For such a plan there is nothing more disturbing than everyday life’s contingencies. Perhaps should we spend a few minutes on divinities. After all, it’s them who create the gravitational paradigm. The plan is to approach them and ideally be united. Every composer, when he/she creates that mini-universe of compositions, implicitly portrays a god’s creational act. So let us question this attitude. Do we have to portray God when we compose? Or is there an alternative to this “divinity neurosis” that would not send us to Mao’s farmers? 1
He who strives on and lives to strive/ Can earn redemption still.
126
16 Commercial Aspects
16.6 How Can We Extend Opened Walls? Recall that we already had a similar situation when discussing instrumental performance in tutorial 12. It was about the performer playing a composition as if he were a waiter serving a dignified plate from the heavens. And we then suggested replacing this ignoble and musically destructive role with the musician’s embodiment of the composition in the role of a dancer, who interacts with the instrument as a stage and not as a sound-generating command station. Our alternative in the present situation would then be to think about replacing the divinity paradigm with one where we do not need to ‘jump to infinity’ to achieve our compositional goals. Essentially, we could try to apply the same strategy as described in the instrumental context: embodiment instead of reference to divinities. Take the composition inside ourselves and fill it with the intensity of our lives. Becoming a composition with all our vital energies, being filled with our work as opposed to setting them down like a mini-universe creation. This being filled with our composition is a promising display: We have replaced the polarity of “high” vs. “low” with a new one: “inside” vs. “outside.” We are identified with the composition, and our skin is the composition’s skin, so to speak. Why is this inside-outside paradigm a creative extension of the wall? Because now there is a natural interface between work and everyday life: the skin. There is an interface that before did not exist; there is no reconciliation between high and low. But the skin’s paradigm offers an exchange of energies and ideas—its vibration can transmit messages from inside and also from outside. We are all of a sudden provided with a sensitive channel between the life of a work and the work of life.
16.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension This metaphor is not only beautiful, it really means something in the understanding of one’s compositional work and one’s life environment. The work’s pulsation can and should be felt in life, and the life’s pulsation can and should be felt in the compositional development. Let me make a short example. Example 13 The Beatles, Bob Dylan, Witold Lutoslawski, and Iannis Xenakis modeled lives that balanced the values of the aesthetical inside and living outside experiences without having to sacrifice one of the two sides of life. Their music is highly artistic and beautiful, and also became a part of our life. Exercise 81 Think about how these artists or any of your favorite musicians developed their career. Could they have become your favorite musicians if they didn’t consider any of the commercial aspects and therefore didn’t have many chances to approach you?
16.7 Final Step: Testing Our Extension
127
Exercise 82 Think about the pulsation in your own life as a musician and person of a living society.
Part III
Theory
17 Historical Approaches
Historically, creativity was reserved for divine instances, which accordingly were also called creators. Humans were never endowed with the genuine capability of creating anything. In particular, when composers started being recognized as constructors of musical works in the Renaissance (as opposed to Pythagorean musicians who simply were reflecting eternal creations, not making new works), their creative actions were understood as inspirations, literally: getting some spirit from somewhere, i.e. being driven and shaped by a divine instance. Therefore, musical compositions were not human creations but simple outputs generated via the divine origins. Beethoven’s famous statement, “Musik ist h¨ ohere Offenbarung als alle Weisheit und Philosophie,” confirms this understanding of musical creation: It is a revelation, not an invention of the composer. When we speak of creativity today, we often refer to an ability that is beneficial in all sorts of domains: economics, politics, art, education, science, or technology, for instance. Even in everyday life we are often faced with situations that require us to find creative, non-evident solutions. If we, for instance, forget to buy a crucial ingredient to complete a dinner recipe, we might have to improvise with whatever is available in the kitchen. Or when we don’t know a word in a foreign language, we might have to come up with a creative way to circumscribe what we intend to say. There are countless situations in life where we are not even aware that we are being creative. But what exactly is creativity, and how can we describe what happens when we are being creative? A recent definition given by Sternberg and Lubart reads: Creativity is “the ability to produce work that is both novel (i.e. original, unexpected) and appropriate (i.e. useful, adaptive concerning task constraints)” [112, p. 3]. This definition well reflects today’s notion and is abstract enough to be applied to numerous domains of creative activity. Still, who is it who can be creative? What do we mean by ‘work’, and what is the product? Where and in what situation can someone best be creative? In what context does something have to be novel in order to be perceived as creative? Common answers to such questions are broad and often contradictory. This section G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 17, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
131
132
17 Historical Approaches
attempts to create a selective but multifaceted picture of recent and historic views on creativity. We first investigate where our concept of creativity comes from and how it developed over time. Then, we give an overview of early and recent psychological research as well as contemporary characterizations of the creative process. Finally, we briefly discuss the special case of musical creativity and examine previous research in the field.
17.1 The Concept of Creativity through (Western) History The urge to be creative has been central to human life and culture for tens of thousands of years, and it can be traced back to the early days of human civilization. It is common today to view the evolution of the concept of creativity as closely connected to art history. We know that already in the period of the Upper Paleolithic, almost 40,000 years ago, and presumably even much earlier1 , humans created objects, paintings, or musical instruments. Surviving artifacts such as the Venus of Hohle Fels, the cave paintings of Chauvet, or the Hohle Fels flute are undeniably linked to an activity that we would call creative today. The former two are clearly symbolic expressions of a human perception of the world, and their appearance hints at an interest in the aesthetic. The latter implies the existence of an early form of music, an abstract way of expression requiring interest in experimentation. Unfortunately we are unable to find out what exactly the motivation behind the manufacture of such items was. Even though we consider them works of art today, it is likely that they were created in a context significantly different from the context a present-day artist works in. They might have been expressions of a higher sense of creativity and meant to worship a higher creator, as was the custom thousands of years later.2 Throughout human history, religion and mysticism played a great role in activities that we would consider creative today. Creative acts were often analogized with the creation of the world by a higher authority, or at least put in context with the prevailing worldview, as we know it of the earliest civilizations known to us. At the same time, individuality and innovation were appraised as secondary, if at all. In ancient Egypt, for instance, it was not innovation that was central to creativity, but repeated ritual actions. These actions were perceived as preventing chaos and keeping the world rolling [6]. In ancient China, creativity was understood as a long and slow process in which not a single being, but numerous individuals are involved, much in the fashion of the Darwinian view of the evolution of nature. The goal of this process was again not innovation, but the transformation of what already exists [70]. Finally, in 1
2
The arguable oldest surviving sculptural object is said to be the Venus of Tan-Tan, about 400,000 years old [11]. It is of course equally possible that they were perceived to be as individualistic and innovative as we perceive a contemporary work of art.
17.1 The Concept of Creativity through (Western) History
133
Taoism and Buddhism, a seeker has to avoid goal-directedness, concentration, and especially self-consciousness and submit to the void and indeterminate in order to be able to transform and create. It is taught that one cannot want to be creative, but one has to yield to creativeness [54, p. 25-6]. Today’s Western concept of creativity is dramatically different from Egypt’s repetitive and ritual, China’s collective and long-term, and Buddhism’s selfless and passive notions. However, our notion is the product of barely more than a hundred years. In the early days of Western civilization, the concept of creativity was much closer to the ones of the aforementioned ancient civilizations. Even though the concept of creativity might have originated in artistic creation, it is often not associated with human creation at all. For a long time, God was seen as the only possible creator, and every creation was seen as emanating from him. But what do the words ‘creation,’ ‘to create,’ and ‘creativity’ mean, and where do they come from? It is important to note that all these words are far more recent than all the notions just described. In fact, it is not before the nineteenth century that the term ‘creativity’ appears. Etymologically, the word goes back to the Latin term creare (to create, to beget, to choose). Before that, the Greeks used the word poiein (to make) and limited its usage uniquely to a description of the work of poets, who were seen as people who ‘bring to life a new world’ based on their own personal perspectives. Still, a poet’s creative ideas were believed to be directly determined by the gods through the mediation of muses. Creative poets were seen to have been chosen by the gods to realize their poems [34, p. 16]. Artists3 , such as painters, sculptors, or even musicians, were merely supposed to skillfully imitate earlier works while following strict laws and rules in order to reflect the perfection of nature [115, p. 244-5]. It was a common belief that nothing new was possible in art. Nevertheless, artists were seen as individuals and they were publicly honored for their achievements [34, p. 20]. Closely associated to creative work was the Greek concept of genius, which stood for a mystical fortune and giftedness on the verge of madness. This concept reappeared in the nineteenth century and still exerts a considerable influence today [2, p. 18]. The Romans saw poets and visual artists as equally entitled to create according to their own will. They even had two verbs for creation, creare and facere, as well as terms for creating (creatio) and creator [115, p. 246]. In Roman culture, we first find the notion of imagination and inspiration being important in connection with a created artwork. This came close to today’s notion of the concept, and it took many centuries after the fall of Rome until the Western world had regained a similar valuation of individuality. In the Middle Ages, under the influence of Christianity, the meaning of the noun creatio was narrowed and uniquely interpreted religiously. It came to refer only to God’s act of “creation from nothing” (creatio ex nihilo). Neither art nor poetry nor any other human creation was perceived as a product of 3
Poets were not counted as artists by the Greeks.
134
17 Historical Approaches
a creative act. As in Greek antiquity, an artist should imitate nature, and even poets were now limited to imitation and compliance with strict rules [115, p. 247]. Every work of art was supposed to be created in honor of God, and the individual artist had no significance at all [34, p. 22]. If an artist was unusually gifted, his talent was perceived as originating from an outside spirit [2, p. 18]. The age of Renaissance brought with it the notion of creativity in art as we understand it today, with innovation being a crucial aspect. Architects, painters, and musicians were seen to ‘invent what is not’ (Paolo Pino), ‘realize their vision’ (Michelangelo), or ‘shape a new world, a new paradise’ (Federico Zuccari). A composer was defined as ‘one who produces new songs’ (Johannes Tinctoris) [115, p. 248]. Artists again found personal acclaim and increasingly worked under patronage independent of the Church. In the seventeenth century, the word creare started to appear again in connection with poetry and later with other art. Artists were said to ‘create anew,’ ‘in the manner of God’ (Maciej Kazimierz Sarbiewsky), and art was seen as “the completion of nature, as if it were a second Creator: It completes nature, embellishes it, sometimes surpasses it” (Baltasar Graci´ an) [115, p. 248]. In the Age of Enlightenment, creativity slowly became a more fundamental part of art theory. Writers began to both make the distinction between genius and mere talent, and demystify the concept of supernatural genius. They maintained that there was a potential for genius and talent in everyone and that it was highly dependent on the political atmosphere and social context whether it could be exploited [2, p. 22]. William Duff considered genius to be based on a combination of imagination, judgement, and taste [34, p. 25], which could only occur in total social freedom [2, p. 22]. Talented artists merely “followed the path blazed by the geniuses” [34, p. 29] and were highly dependent on formal education, whereas genius seemed to come out of nowhere [2, p. 22]. Nevertheless, a significant amount of diligence was seen as necessary in order to benefit from genius or talent. There were also skeptics of the concept of creativity. French philosophers Diderot and Batteux claimed that the human mind cannot create, but merely recombine, magnify, or diminish what already exists. “Even monsters invented by an imagination unhampered by laws can only be composed of parts taken from nature” (Batteux) [115, p. 249]. In the nineteenth century, art was fully acknowledged as an act of human creation. The terms creative and creativity were finally introduced and quickly disseminated. They were frequently used, but still only in connection with art: The only humans able to create were artists. The meaning of creation shifted, especially with the emergence of new explanations for the workings and the evolution of the world, such as Charles Darwin’s. It became irrelevant that something was created “from nothing;” what was important was only that it was novel [115, p. 251-2]. The association of genius and madness reappeared, and it was widely acknowledged what emotional tests creative personalities had to go through [54, p. 30-1]. William S. Jevons, for instance, defined genius as being “essentially creative” and he also believed that creative thinking to con-
17.2 Creativity in Early Psychology
135
sist in “divergence from the ordinary grooves of thought and action,” which anticipated theories of divergence of more than half a century later [10]. On the edge of the twentieth century, the concept of creativity was finally generalized and began to be used for other domains than art, e.g. the sciences (Jan L ukasiewicz) and nature (Henri Bergson) [115, p. 249]. The aspect of novelty is central to the concept to this day.
17.2 Creativity in Early Psychology With the emergence of experimental psychology in the late nineteenth century, it was no longer just the concept of creativity that was investigated and described, but the creative process. Psychologists and philosophers began to describe what precisely happens when someone is being creative. The beginning of the psychology of creativity was characterized by two main convictions about the nature of creativity, corresponding with the two major psychological movements at the time: the associationists and the Gestaltists. The associationists, under the lead of Sir Francis Galton, who was inspired by his half-cousin Charles Darwin’s groundbreaking theories, claimed that creativity consists of associating things or ideas in new and different ways. The associationists believed that the unconscious could be made conscious through association of thoughts. Galton described this process as follows: “Ideas in the conscious mind are linked to those in the unconscious mind by threads of similarity” [34, p. 28-9]. The Gestaltists, in turn, explained the creative process as seeing a Gestalt, a mental pattern or form4 , in a new way, i.e. from a different position or in a different situation [34, p. 30]. Max Wertheimer, for instance, a later Gestaltist, proposed that a new point of view on the whole of a problem is more effective than rearranging its parts. Such a change of point of view is often perceived as uncomfortable and stressful. For Wertheimer, this is the reason why people have a tendency to become rigid and stifle their creativity to avoid problems [34, p. 33]. In the early twentieth century, the creative process was associated with problem-solving, and there was a conviction that insight, the outcome of the process, is usually sudden and passive. Graham Wallas was one of the first to describe the creative process precisely. His model contains five stages [122]: • preparation: gathering of information, focusing on form and content • incubation: stopping to work on problem, maybe give up, letting information sink into unconscious mind; gathering more information proves counterproductive • intimation: feeling that an idea is on its way • illumination: having a sudden insight, perhaps an unnamed thought, not necessarily a clear solution; might lead back to more conscious work 4
The elements of a Gestalt form complex interrelationships that go beyond mere association, which makes the entire Gestalt greater than the sum of its parts.
136
•
17 Historical Approaches
verification: trying out and checking a solution
This five-stage model is the most influential characterization of the creative process, but it has turned out to be difficult to verify, for it is very unlikely that someone can be creative in an artificial research context. Another question discussed by early psychologists was about the origin of creative ability or genius. Sir Francis Galton dealt with it and he maintained that creativity and especially genius are inherited genetically. William James, in turn, suggested that a person’s environment and upbringing have the greatest influence on creativity [34, p. 32]. Many later psychologists followed James’s path and began to look for triggers and favorable aspects. The psychoanalytically oriented psychiatrists were convinced that creativity is highly connected with defense mechanisms against a state of frustration about an unfulfilled need (deficiency need). Sigmund Freud, for instance, claimed that creativity is established by a traumatic experience undergone in the first five years of life and then buried in the unconscious mind. He saw it primarily related to sublimation, which is artistic pursuit due to a lack of sex drive. Further notable psychoanalysts saw creativity being based on other kinds of defense mechanisms, e.g. regression of an adult to an ego-less, child-like state out of frustration (Ernst Kris), or compensation for feelings of inferiority in another area (Alfred Adler) [34, p. 36-9].5 The humanist psychologists opposed the view of Freud and his followers and proclaimed that creativity comes from being needs rather than deficiency needs. According to Abraham Maslow, when lower-level needs—i.e. physiological needs, safety, love, and esteem—are fulfilled, a person pursues her being needs. These include self-actualization needs, i.e fulfilling one’s personal potential, and aesthetic needs, i.e. understanding the world. The former are closely linked to creativity, and self-actualized people are prone to witness a peak experience, a state of unselfish ecstasy. Similarly, Erich Fromm claimed that creativity stems from the need to raise above one’s instinctive nature. Another humanist psychologist, Carl Rogers, listed the personality traits supportive of creativity as follows6 : • openness to experience • ability to evaluate situations by one’s own standard • ability to experiment and engage with unstable situations Rogers claimed that someone who possesses these traits is likely to be in excellent psychological health. Fromm proposed five additional but related necessary personality traits:
5
6
Only Otto Rank claimed that creativity is a realization of one’s will, an integration of one’s personality, and a reaction to a healthy environment, i.e. a family with supportive parents. These trays are also psychologically advantageous properties for the creativity process that we describe in chapter 19.
17.3 Creativity Research in Recent Years
• • • • •
137
capacity to be puzzled and surprised ability to concentrate objective knowledge of self ability to accept conflict and tension willingness to let go of security
All these theories and attitudes worked toward a clearer picture of what creativity is. Nevertheless, it was not until 1950 that creativity research was pursued in a systematic way with clearly defined experiments for verification.
17.3 Creativity Research in Recent Years Scientific study of creativity is often said to begin with the work of Joy Paul Guilford in 1950. He pointed out how neglected the topic of creativity was in psychological studies and initiated a rapid emancipation of systematic creativity research. His main idea was that creativity should be studied in everyday subjects instead of exceptionally creative individuals. Before him, several notable scholars had attempted to do systematic research, but with a strong focus on genius. Inspired by Galton’s and James’s empirical research, early twentieth-century psychologists such as Lewis Terman and Catharine Cox performed historiographic studies of individuals deemed geniuses by estimating their IQ based on their biographical and autobiographical data as well as their social contexts [2, p. 26-7]. A major consequence of these studies and later follow-ups was that developmental and family factors are more influential on creative abilities than intelligence and that at an IQ higher than 115, creativity and intelligence are more or less uncorrelated [2, p. 28]. Guilford proposed that there is no such thing as a general intelligence. He divided mental capacities into 120 factors, which could all be more or less distinct in individuals. Each factor is dependent on one or several of five operations: divergent production, convergent production, cognition, memory, and evaluation. Divergent production, which is an important part of today’s view on creative production, encompassed different contents (figural, symbolic, semantic, and behavioral) and products (units, classes, relations, systems, transformations, and implications). Guilford implemented psychometric tests to find products on the 120-factor matrix and concluded that the results originating in divergent production were by far the most significant [7, p. 14]. Based on Guilford’s work, E. Paul Torrance developed the famous Torrance Tests of Creative Thinking that rated multiple responses to problem-solving tasks according to fluency, flexibility, originality, and elaboration (detailedness). Typical tasks were asking as many questions as possible about a given drawing, or listing as many unusual uses for an everyday object, such as a cardboard box [112, p. 7]. In the 1950s and 1960s, research focused on the creative personality in a wave of a “new version of individualism” [2, p. 28]. Psychologists of the time believed that the best way to study creativity is to analyze individuals and
138
17 Historical Approaches
their motivations and goals as well as their internal cognitive representations. Traits similar to the ones listed by the humanist psychologists were found to be crucial for creativity. Later, the topics and subject backgrounds broadened and included research on creative types or styles and everyday creativity. In the late 1980s, researchers led by Mih´ aly Cs´ıkszentmih´ alyi and Dean Keith Simonton began to incorporate social and contextual environments to assess where and how creative work could best be performed [104, p. 24]. With his systems view, Cs´ıkszentmih´alyi claimed that whether or not something was perceived as creative work was highly dependent on and often determined by the context, or the field, in which it was produced. Inspired by this, scholars have started to investigate group creativity and interactive creative processes. They claim that “creativity cannot always be defined as a property of individuals” [104, p. 25] but as the property of an complex social network where members each contribute their parts. Other contemporary scholars have focused on the cognitive process underlying creativity and created models and even computer simulations of it. The Geneplore model, for instance, instead of confirming Wallas’s five-step model, assumes that there are two phases, the generative and the exploratory phase. In the former phase, the subject creates mental representations, which are then processed in the latter phase (via retrieval, association, synthesis, transformation, analogical transfer, and categorical reduction) [42]. The BACON software, to cite a further example, was designed to rediscover scientific laws through heuristics; it found Kepler’s third law of planetary motion from simple numeric astronomical data [65]. More achievements in the research of the cognitive process will be presented in the next section. There are many other directions and theories in the study of creativity, and we will not be able to give a full overview. The universal applicability of the word ‘creativity’ today inspires many scholars to do interdisciplinary studies and adopt ideas from other domains. Sternberg and Lubart, for example, draw from economics and say that creative individuals are willing to buy low (invest in an unpopular idea) and sell high (earn respect for the idea) [62, p. 30]. Simonton created a model for creativity that is inspired by evolutionary biology. To his mind, ideas are created in the subconscious mind and then purposefully retained by the conscious mind if they prove viable [62, p. 37]. This can be generalized so that society as a whole would be seen as a filter for viable ideas. Creativity would then be the force that quasi-randomly produces ideas that are integrated into culture if they prove viable. It would be the analogous force to genetic mutation in Darwin’s natural selection. This idea is, for instance, brought up by Cs´ıkszentmih´alyi, who refers to Richard Dawkins’s concept of memes, the informational units of selection in cultural evolution [33, p. 7]. Creativity would thus take the function of a generator of new memes. Yet, many scholars today have trouble accepting the assumption that generated ideas are principally random. There are, in fact, good reasons for such a critical attitude. First of all, reduction of creativity to randomness does not answer the problem of what creativity is, it just denies it in a killer argument and delegates it to
17.3 Creativity Research in Recent Years
139
the scientific concept of randomness, which is nothing but a nice rephrasing of ignorance. Second, creativity is a highly spiritual achievement of intelligent beings, which is never realized by random mutation, otherwise Picasso would not have created one masterpiece after the other. In contrast, Darwinian mutation is purely random without any spiritual dimension. Creativity is not a casino affair. It is remarkable that creativity was a divine process in ancient times, and now in certain theories, creational divinity has been replaced by randomness (like Darwinism replaced divine creation in biology). In their summary of theories of creativity, Kozbelt et al. bring to attention that it is not divergent thinking alone that counts for creativity but also a certain amount of moderation that ensures that the resulting ideas are not irrelevant to the problem [62, p. 20]. In Guilford’s terms, convergent thinking is equally important for creative results as divergent thinking is [62, p. 32]. This brings us back to the definition cited at the beginning of this chapter, where appropriateness was a requirement for something to be considered creative. In the context of this book, we think it is suitable to stick with this definition. The criterion of appropriateness is met in our own approach in sections 19.1.3, 19.1.4 when we search for the critical concept and then identify its walls in order to open new perspectives of creative extensions.
18 Present Approaches
18.1 The Creative Process Today Since we are proposing strategies and tools for being creative, it is necessary to briefly focus on contemporary theories that deal with describing the creative process. Before giving an overview of such theories, we will come back to the questions asked in the introduction to this section and attempt to give presentday answers to them that also reflect our view presented in this book. 18.1.1 The Four P’s of Creativity Instances of creativity are traditionally described using the four P’s of creativity: process, product, person, and place.1 The first P, process, is the most important in connection with this book and will be described in the next section. The second, product, deals with the outcome of the creative process, which can be just about anything: the conception of a car, a mathematical proof, a practical trick, a sculpture, an unexpected joke, or in our case, a musical composition or improvisation. We have seen in the historical overview that today, creativity is applied in all conceivable fields and thus everything that is both novel and appropriate can be seen as the product of a creative process. Person, the third P, and especially personality, as depicted earlier, was the main subject of most research and theory in the first two-thirds of the twentieth century. It is evident that there are differences in creative capacity from individual to individual, but in this book we assume that anyone can potentially be and often is creative. It merely depends on the context in which the creative activity takes place as well as the context from which the creative product is evaluated. If a person finds an alternative way to open a door if the key does not work, or if an unsuccessful deer hunter finds a way to get sated eating berries, we could consider the respective solution to be creative in the 1
Some recent publications presented extensions of these and added persuasion and potential [62, p. 24], which will not be treated here.
G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 18, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
141
142
18 Present Approaches
subject’s context. In our case, we think that a musician with any background can be creative, at least in his/her own context. Musical works are, however, often conceived to be valued in a greater context so that the musician has to know the context very well to be successful. The fourth P, place, deals with the environment in which a person can best be creative. We have already touched on this question in the theories of Galton, James, Freud, and Maslow, for instance, who were convinced that a person’s environment, such as her upbringing and family or her state of wealth, had the greatest influence on her creative potential. Generally, creativity seems to flourish when “there are opportunities for exploration and independent work, and when originality is supported and valued” [62, p. 25]. In musical production, there are often strict external constraints, such as a movie that the music has to fit, a certain theme or performance context for which it is commissioned, or simple time constraints. However, originality and experimentation is almost always valued to a certain degree. Studies in place and process are often very closely connected, and we will thus come back to it in our discussion of the first P, process. 18.1.2 The Creative Process Theories that deal with the creative process are bound to understand the mental mechanisms that occur when a person is being creative. We have already discussed Wallas’s five-stage model (see section 17.2), which is still one of the most popular today. However, many scholars have criticized its linearity and have allowed for recursion, where each of the stages can be reached multiple times, in different orders, and on different levels of abstraction [62, p. 31]. Some theories, instead of proposing a simple stage model, suggest component mechanisms, where prior knowledge and information as well as motivation play an important role in guiding the creative process. Mark A. Runco and Ivonne Chand, for instance, suggest a two-tier model (shown in Figure 18.1) in which the first tier represents a set of three basic skills, the controlling factors involved in the creative process: problem finding (identification, definition, etc.), ideation (ideational fluency, originality, and flexibility), and evaluation (valuation and critical evaluation). A second tier shows two additional contributing factors, knowledge and motivation, which are highly dependent on the primary factors. Motivation is, for instance, both dependent on ideation and evaluation [101]. One of the components of this model makes it significantly different from Wallas’s: the problem-finding component, which replaces the preparation stage. Many contemporary theories of creativity put a problem at the center of the creative process. Such a problem can be well-defined, such as a specific puzzle or winning a game with specific rules, or ill-defined (admitting many ‘good’ solutions), such as painting an aesthetically pleasing picture or writing an avant-garde string quartet. Now who defines such a problem or where does it come from? Among the theories that answer these questions, there are two
18.1 The Creative Process Today
143
Fig. 18.1. Runco and Chand’s component model of the creative process.
major categories opposing each other. The first one, problem solving, argues that in a creative process a problem is usually constructed by the creator, and if it is ill-defined, it can often be deconstructed into well-defined parts [62, p. 33]. Scholars proclaiming this view usually see creativity as a rational phenomenon and claim that both constructing a problem and deconstructing it need a significant level of expertise. John R. Hayes, for instance, found that great composers typically need to be trained for at least ten years before they create their first masterpiece [50], a rule that applies to creative achievements in many fields. However, expertise is only one of the factors that influence creativity and hardly ensures it. The advocates of the problem-finding view criticize exactly this and argue that the problem-solving view does not explain how creative persons really construct their problems. Cs´ıkszentmih´ alyi and Getzels, for instance, observed how more-creative individuals spent more time with exploratory behavior lacking clearly defined goals, which, however, typically lead to more success in their activities. The problem-finding view is more oriented toward describing the subjective experience of the creative individual and manages to explain instances of creativity independent of expertise. However, some scholars refute the problem-finding view by arguing that the subjects’s exploratory behavior might well be described with standard subconscious problem-solving routines. Cognitive psychology has contributed a lot to theories concerned with the creative process. There, scholars often deal with one of the stages or components and go slightly more in depth with the mechanisms. Many studies from the past decade have shown that conceptual combination, associating disparate sets of information, play a great role in ideation. Such sets are often only com-
144
18 Present Approaches
binable on a highly abstract level and only intelligible in a so-called metaphoric logical rather than literal way [62, p. 32]. Galenson suggests that in art there are two different types of creative personalities, the creative processes of which differ significantly: the “seeker” and the “finder” [45]. The former typically struggle and experiment guided by a mostly aesthetic motivation and no clear goals, and develop rather steadily. Finders, in turn, make detailed concepts and clearly define their goals before starting to work and are more prone to making radical conceptual innovations throughout their lifetime. Systems theories, such as Cs´ıkszentmih´alyi’s, describe the creative individual embedded in a large and complex social system. Seen from this perspective, the individual creative process loses its significance and is extended to a process where several individuals and groups interact. Evaluation, for instance, is taken over by a group of experts, and problem finding can be an indeterminate interaction between several creators. In other words, the main creative process does not merely take place on the level of a person, but also on the level of the place (the environment). Cs´ıkszentmih´alyi does not ask “What is creativity?” but “Where is creativity?” [31, 33]. He sees creative ideas as the product of a system with three components: a domain or culture with symbolic rules, a person that brings new ideas into a symbolic domain, and a field of experts that validate these ideas. None of the components can be missing, even though there might be variations. The field of experts, for instance, has a different meaning in everyday creativity than in eminent, so-called big C, creativity, the acts of which are significant to all mankind. Anyone might be able to understand the originality of an everyday joke and would thus be part of the field of experts, while it takes a lot of expertise to understand the inventiveness of a symphonic work. Another major contribution of Cs´ıkszentmih´ alyi’s to our notion of the creative process is his concept of flow. Flow is the state of mind in which a person is equally challenged and successful when performing a specific task. The person loses both his/her sense of time and self-consciousness and is completely immersed in his/her activity, experiencing pure enjoyment [30]. Cs´ıkszentmih´alyi discusses each of the factors necessary to reach the state of flow during creative activity, most notably the clarity of one’s goal, a good amount of self-judgment, the urge to face challenges, and the ability to avoid distraction [33, p. 113ff]. It turns out that these are the same factors that generally describe creative personalities now and in the long term. Generally, flow seems to accompany the creative process, and the more creative a person, is the more she experiences it in her activities. Finally, Margaret Boden, who has ideas very similar to the ones of the authors of this book, finds three different types of creative processes, which she bases on the three ways in which one can be surprised [12, p. 3]. The first type, combinational, is closely related to the associationist view and comprises unfamiliar combinations of familiar ideas. The exploratory type consists of the exploration of a conceptual space, i.e. a certain thinking style such as a theory,
18.2 Musical Creativity
145
a fashion style, or a musical genre. This exploration results in a new idea within the same space, which can nevertheless be of an unexpected nature. The third type, transformational, means the extension of a conceptual space to include a previously impossible concept or idea [13, p. 72].2
18.2 Musical Creativity For the final part of our short investigation of previous work on creativity, we now turn to musical creativity. There is hardly a domain where achievements are mystified as strongly as in music. This attitude makes the fields of music composition, improvisation, performance, and even listening distinctly hard to study. Composers who refuse to speak about the making of their works, performers who enact an artificial personality, and listeners who merely pretend to understand are omnipresent. The study of musical creativity suffers under these circumstances and is rather underrepresented in creativity studies.3 Nevertheless, many of the findings from general creativity studies and theories can be applied to the domain of music. In this section, we will give a short overview of studies specifically dealing with musical creativity. First of all, what do we mean by “musical creativity”? Generally nothing more than being creative in one of the various fields and activities in music. Or reconsidering Sternberg and Lubart’s definition of creativity given above, it is the ability to produce work that is both novel and appropriate in the domain of music. Again, this work can be a composition or improvisation; an interpretation, cover version, or remix; a recording or production, an instrument with a certain conception of sound, or even a way of listening to a specific work. In our book, we typically deal with creativity in the fields of composition and improvisation, but we also provide examples from other fields. In Western music, such a work or product indeed has to be novel in a certain way in order to be valued by an audience, and it is straightforward what this means. It should incorporate unheard melodies or old ones in an unheard context or realization, a new conception of sound, an innovative form, new catchy rhythms, etc. But what does it mean for a musical work to be appropriate? Bj¨ orn Merker explains this as the necessity of a “command of craft and grounding in a musical tradition” [90, p. 25]. Similarly, Simonton found in his research that compositions that are generally perceived as creative do depart from prevailing norms, but not as much as innovative compositions that are not widely acclaimed do [109]. Even though creativity itself was not of much interest until recently, as seen in the previous sections, the domain of music was connected to it from the beginnings of theoretical investigations in creativity. In 1931, for instance, Julius Bahle wrote a letter to thirty-two composers, including Luigi Dallapic2 3
This is analogous to the “opening of walls” in our model. The only area where musical creativity is a crucial topic is music education, which is not subject to this chapter.
146
18 Present Approaches
cola, Ernst Krenek, Arthur Honegger, and Arnold Schoenberg, with the intention to find out more about how they approach the process of composing a new work [8]. His evaluation of their answers was based on the work of the German psychoanalysts, especially Freud and Kris. He assessed how much the composers’ choice of material, their productive experience, their affective and emotional life, and their obligation to work affected the composition process. Especially worth mentioning is a question about how easily dreams could influence musical composition, again inspired by Freud. Many, especially new music composers, answered that a lot of their inspiration would come from dreams. Much like Bahle’s work based on psychoanalysis, every direction of creativity research has had its application in musical creativity. Carl E. Seashore’s investigations, for instance, are closely connected to the historiographic studies of Terman and Cox. He investigated biographies, diaries, and letters of famous and prodigious composers to find out how they proceeded in music composition. For example, he found out that Mozart used to actively retain musical ideas he liked, which then more or less automatically transformed into a whole composition [105]. Of course, this creates more questions than it answers and it merely describes Mozart’s subjective experience of his activity, which appears to be of a highly passive nature. The majority of the compositional process seems to take place subconsciously. Many exceptional composers describe it this way. Paul Hindemith, for instance, said that the imagination of musical ideas, i.e. a short melody, is the basis of the process of composition. The remainder is fulfilled by the ability to clearly envision a finished composition. In Hindemith’s opinion, this ability is what makes the ‘real’ composer, and the highest goal for a composer is the convergence of this vision and the final materialization [99, p. 42-3]. Karlheinz Stockhausen describes his compositional activity as a conscious prolongation of such flash-like visionary moments [99, p. 56].4 In their studies, both Bahle and Seashore clearly focus on the creative process. This applies to most research in musical creativity. The general type of question is almost always: How do composers compose, or how do performers perform? As the examples show, such questions are exceptionally difficult to answer, especially when looking at the musician’s subjective experience. Interest in the process of music creation is constantly growing, especially in connection with specialized theories of creativity. David Cope, for instance, presents computational models of the creative process. His software Emmy emulates the styles of composers such as Beethoven, Mozart, Mahler, and Prokofiev by recombining fragments of original compositions saved in a database [28]. Cope does not consider its results as original, but nevertheless as creative, since they originate from a creative process [29, p. 33]. Now, the creative process of Emmy cannot, however, be regarded as actually creative, since it merely applies the compositional rules provided by Cope [53]. As is often the case in computer 4
Nicholas Cook creates an interesting connection between these flash-like visions of genius composers and Schenkerian analysis in [26].
18.2 Musical Creativity
147
modeling of creativity, there seems to be a confusion between processes that create something new and real creative processes in our sense, where the result is essentially creative. Starting in the mid-twentieth century, scholars increasingly dealt with the creative personality question as well as the psychometric assessment of musical creativity, again influenced by major trends in creativity research. Some applied the findings of Guilford and Torrance and designed psychometric tests, such as the Musical Aptitude Test [36] or the Seashore Test of Musical Ability [20]. Others published detailed studies describing the personality traits of gifted musicians, such as [46] or [110], which do not differ significantly from the ones described in Section 17.2. A distinct case is Sawyer’s theory of group creativity. There, person is not a single person, but a group of interacting musicians. In an improvised jazz performance, for instance, for Sawyer “the whole is greater than the sum of the parts” [104, p. 73]. Sawyer notes that the only product of an improvisation is the creative process itself. He names this kind of creativity improvisational creativity as opposed to compositional creativity, where there is a product distinct from the process [103]. Furthermore, Sawyer says that improvisation is generally based on problem finding rather than problem solving [104, p. 73]. One of the most important questions when looking at a specific domain of creativity, such as music, is in what respect the product differs from products in other domains. The fact that music is a performing art makes it significantly different from many other domains. Musicians create in real time in front of an audience. The musical product can range from a faithful rendering of a work, to an embellished interpretation, to an entirely unplanned free improvisation. Scholars have analyzed and compared such products, e.g. alternate takes of jazz solos, and come to the conclusion that even improvisation is to a large degree built on “smoothly and innovatively combining or sequencing phrases or motifs from memory while conforming to structural constraints” [90, p. 27]. Charlie Parker, for instance, is regarded as a formulaic improviser, which means that he acquires countless patterns and formulas for different harmonic situations and applies them spontaneously. At the speed at which Parker played, it would have been impossible to compose new music from scratch [94].5 For performative musicians, Merker proposed four different kinds of products differing in novelty and preparation, as shown in Figure 18.2. When asking for the role of place in musical creativity, we come back to Hayes, who coined the ten-year window of activity of composers until they write their first masterpiece (see section 18.1.2). Hayes, for example, pointed out that Mozart’s first seven piano concertos did not contain any original music, but consisted of gathered and rearranged material from works of other composers [50]. This is not as strictly the case for early works in other categories, but the composer still closely followed the models of earlier composers. 5
The concept of formulaic improvisation was used in improvising software, e.g. in [59].
148
18 Present Approaches
Fig. 18.2. Merker’s space of musical performance products.
Mozart’s first ten years of musical experience thus consisted of immersion in the works of others by means of composition and performance. This is what Howard Gardner calls “creative mastery,” one of his four forms of extraordinariness (or creative intelligence6 ) [46]. Ericsson et al. come to the same conclusion for expert performance in classical music [40, p. 233]. The same ten-year rule also applies to jazz performers, as Robert W. Weisberg shows. Even the greatest improvising musicians say they have learned from older musicians by playing back their solos from records note for note [123, p. 236-7]. And it applies to musicians and songwriters in popular music, such as The Beatles. In the band’s early history (1957-62), 90 percent of the songs that entered its repertoire were cover versions [123, p. 239]7 . We should however note that the ten-year rule is nothing else but the necessary condition to get acquainted with a certain cultural context of the art that is at stake. If you want to write a Chinese poem, you first have to learn Chinese. Every higher culture needs this type of basic education. But this is far from describing sufficient conditions for creativity. In fact, a considerable number of those who have the necessary education in a determined field of knowledge or art never produce creative works. With respect to the ten-year rule, we refer to our discussion of a creative pedagogy (chapter 20). It is a pedagogy where the student’s creative attitude is a central concern, while traditional education often casts students into a rigid framework that prevents creativity. 6
7
“Kreative Intelligenz,” as adapted in the German translation of the book Extraordinary Minds. Another question in connection with place is the importance of a supportive family. Several studies found it to be extremely rare that a composer reaches high standards without early support and encouragement [56, p. 435].
19 Our Approach
This chapter presents two versions of our approach to creativity. First (section 19.1) we discuss this approach from a semiotic point of view. This is also the more accessible presentation since it does not rely on mathematical formalism. It is however connected to the second version (section 19.2) which relies on category theory. This means that both versions have corresponding components, but the mathematical one shows them as processes that are formalized in terms of functors.
19.1 Approach to Creativity: A Semiotic Presentation We shall now discuss the compound creativity process. At the end of this chapter, section 19.2, we shall present a processual list summarizing all characteristic steps in this process. 19.1.1 The Open Question’s Context in Creativity Our approach to creativity starts with a context, where an open question to be answered takes place. This means that creativity is not an absolute action but must be related to a specific context. For example, if a monkey discovers a new way to grasp a banana in a difficult place, this is creative for that animal, but very probably not for humans. Or if somebody reinvents something that has already been invented, but without knowledge of this inventor, then this is creative in this person’s “context.” We need to specify such contexts before identifying creativity. We propose that such a context be a semiotic, i.e. a system of signs with their syntactics, semantics, and pragmatics. This approach guarantees that the creation adds meaning to a given context—it is not only a new abstract element that is created, but it means something new in that system. Let us make this clear on the creation of the Appassionata Sonata, op. 57, by Beethoven. Mathematically speaking, or, more precisely, in the language of deG. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 19, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
149
150
19 Our Approach
notators and forms1 , all sonatas in a given notational score system are simply points (elements) in a big powerset of denotators. So in this mathematical system, a sonata is nothing new: All sonatas are already given in that abstract mathematical realm. Evidently, this is not the argument that one would accept when looking at this sonata as a musical creation. What is creative here is not the identification of op. 57 as a point in a mathematical space, but rather it is the added meaning to the understanding of what is a sonata, among others, that counts here. It is also the historical moment of this creation, that counts. It refers to the state of the music as a semiotic system in that very moment (1804-1806) of the first Viennese period, where it changed a number of insights in to what music-theoretical structure, process, and (above all) gesture could be. In particular, this contextual setup is not related to finiteness or combinatorial conditions. Even if the total range of possible sonatas within a given score notation system is finite, the semiotic extension of the sonata concept is the relevant criterion for creativity here, i.e. creativity requires the introduction of a new sign to be added to a given semiotic. However, it is not characterized by this condition only; the extension of a semiotic is a necessary but not sufficient condition for creativity. We now add the following specifications. 19.1.2 Motivation for a Semiotic Extension The second specification of the concept of creativity is that the added sign is introduced with a specific purpose, not just for any old reason. It matters why this new sign is added. And it matters how this is accomplished. Let us first focus on the reason why a sign is added. Our approach to this criterion is that the new sign should provide the solution to a given open question or problem2 that has been identified within that given semiotical context introduced above in section 19.1.1. Let us look at a typical example of this situation. Albert Einstein, when dealing with the special relativity theory, could answer open questions of physics at the beginning of the twentieth century by the extension of the concept of time. The essentially singular Newtonian time was extended to a multiplicity of times in inertia systems that are related to one another by the Lorentz transformation. The creation of Einstein’s new time concept was an extension of the semiotics of physics by a new sign: the multiplicity of times in inertia systems, together with their Lorentz relation. It might seem too restrictive to impose the answering of an open question upon the semiotic extension in creativity. In the typical context of musical composition or improvisation, why should there be any question to be answered, when acting in a creative way? Isn’t this a condition that hampers artistic freedom in creativity? If it is understood that this freedom means that anything 1 2
See section 21.3.6 for these concepts. Stravinsky [113] conceived musical creativity as a type of problem solving.
19.1 Approach to Creativity: A Semiotic Presentation
151
goes, then yes, it hampers it, and rightly so. In fact, artistic creation should occur with a consciousness of a certain necessity to conceive and realize this work of art. If freedom then means that the artist comes to an insight of such a necessity, we might agree. Although one cannot prove such a position, it is however a strong criterion for quality in artistic creation. Evidently, this point of view is quite standard in scientific contexts, but we contend that it is equally advantageous to apply it to the artistic creativity. In the theory of group flow as conceived by Keith Sawyer [104], flow is defined as an equilibrium between two components: shared structures and specific goals. Sawyer describes free improvisation in music as being in flow if there are few shared structures and there is only an intrinsic goal, i.e. no extrinsic goal to be achieved as it may happen in a group of computer programmers that has to solve a specific problem. Sawyer then comments that in free improvisation the first half of performance time might be spent inventing a problem that may be solved in the second half. Although this setup seems to relate to our approach of starting from an open question in a creative activity, it is fundamentally different. Let us explain this. To begin with, in our approach to creativity, one does not have to invent a problem to be solved, because there is already a given open question. So at least from the creativity point of view, we are only dealing with this action when Sawyer’s problem has been introduced. And we do not agree with Sawyer that this invention of a problem is what group flow in free improvisation achieves, but see [85] for details. The most important difference in Sawyer’s approach is his idea that half of the performance time would be driven not by any creativity but just finding a problem. Such music would be bare of any aesthetical quality. In reality, the open questions that we address here are present from the beginning and need not be invented or found. If Coltrane gets off the ground with “My Favorite Things,” the first task is to unfold the main theme into a manifold of variations. The question then is to conceive the main theme as a critical concept/sign of Coltrane’s context, and to open its walls to unfold its potential in rhythm, harmony, and motivic neighborhoods. One could also say that the basic question is to explore the initial data (theme, rhythm, whatever is thrown into the staging dynamics) with respect to their walls in the sense of what has not been played yet in the neighborhood of this initial data. So there is no problem to be invented; the open question is given from the very beginning. 19.1.3 The Critical Sign Once we are given the semiotic context (section 19.1.1) and have identified the open question backing the creative action (section 19.1.2), we may proceed to the first operational action upon this context, namely identifying the concept(s) that is (are) responsible for the present open question. This is a sign in our semiotics, but it may not be a singular one. It might be that there is a series of such critical concepts (signs). In this sense we just select a first critical concept
152
19 Our Approach
to start the creative process. Let us make an example. In the discovery of the three Kepler laws (first law: planet orbits are ellipses, the sun being in one of their foci; second law: the surface covered by the connecting line from the sun to a planet in a time unit is constant for that planet; third law: the orbit time t and the semi-major axis a of a planetary ellipsis define a number t2 /a3 which is constant for all planets), the open question Kepler was confronted with was the failure to model planet trajectories as perfect circles, i.e. having constant distance from the sun. Here, the critical concept is the distance of a planet to the sun. Once this concept is questioned, it must be replaced by some other “distance” concept. But even then (supposing this problem has been solved), the shape of the trajectory—that now is no longer a circle—can be quite arbitrary. The second law replaces the geometric distance with the surface covered per time unit, i.e. with a more abstract “distance.” The first law then replaces the concept of a perfect circle with the more general elliptic trajectory shape. 19.1.4 Identifying a Concept’s Walls To this point, the procedure was not very specific. This is what one would always do to answer an open question: Locate it in a reasonable context and identify the critical concepts. We now present the step that we believe is more specific for creativity. It deals with the question of how the critical concept may be investigated. It is assumed that the concept is not working well, and that it should be—in some way—replaced by another concept. A concept is defined by some of its components and by the way, it refers to these components. For example, in Einstein’s time problem, the time concept is that of a real number, plus some other properties. Or for Kepler’s laws, the distance is a geometric length in an Euclidean space. So it seems obvious what the concept’s anatomy is. In the case of Einstein’s problem, one could question the properties given by a real number, or in Kepler’s situation, one could question the Euclidean distance and try to replace it with another metrical distance construction. In fact, in the case of time, the astrophysicist Stephen Hawking has questioned the real number quality of time and replaced it with a complex number to get rid of mathematical singularities for the cosmic Big Bang 14 billion years ago. But the problem of those properties is that they might be quite hidden to the normal understanding. We therefore call such subtle properties that one might easily overlook the concept’s walls. They are properties that are so evident that one would not even become aware of them in the first naive approach. Let us look how this happens in Einstein’s problem. In Einstein’s situation, time was the Newtonian time that, except for trivial gauging and origin transformations, was one and the same for every point of the universe. It was just the divine time that was shared by all beings of this world.
19.1 Approach to Creativity: A Semiotic Presentation
153
In the description of time, there is one property that one would not even think of in the first moment: the fact that time is a singular concept. There are no two times, at least not besides the above trivial gauging and origin transformations. So what is critical here? The point is that the singularity of time is a very deep assumption: We all have the one and only time. Of course, one would answer, I also have only one weight, only one shoe size. It would be absurd to assume I have more than one weight. And this is exactly the critical point: The wall character of singularity of time is that it is identified with the time concept in such a way that putting it into question would look like putting into question the very essence of the concept. Let us look at the example of the Post-It adhesive by 3M’s Spencer Silver in 1968. He was in search of a super adhesive and never succeeded, but instead synthesized an adhesive that did not glue but could be removed easily. In 1974, a friend of Silver, Art Fry, discovered the advantage of having such a weak adhesive when adding small notes to musical scores in church. Here the critical concept is “adhesive.” It seems mandatory to have the characteristic attribute of the concept, which is “glueing.” That this might be a wall seems impossible. However, it is exactly this characteristic that turned out to be a wall against the introduction of a new class of adhesives! Here the opening of the wall meant that we question the “glueing” property. This is a binary property: either it glues or it doesn’t. But this binary logic turned out to be too restrictive in Silver’s situation. Could glueing be extended to a broader spectrum of logical possibilities? Why not think of the property in terms of a fuzzy logic: glueing by x percent? In fact, this extension solved the open question and opened the success story behind 3M’s Post-It. Before we investigate singularity of time, we should stress the perhaps deepest problem in the creative process: The identification of walls, supposing that they are not even given in any explicit definition and understanding of the critical concept(s). We may have to invent such a wall property before investigating its possible role in the given open question. It is as if we were looking at the concept of a number and all of a sudden had to think about a number’s color. Of course, the chance to invent an absurd/useless wall property is very high. So the real art would consist in finding walls that are hidden at first sight, but open up an essential new perspective on a given concept. This art could be misunderstood as a combinatorial task of just going through a list of possible properties and checking their chance of being a wall to the given critical concept. However, it would not help to go through any such list since its size would be far too large to answer the open question. But the approach of using a list is also not what the solution could offer. It is not about formal properties, but about semantics: What is the signification of a determined property for the given concept and its problematic position. For the time being, we cannot make this process more explicit, but want to have it named and memorized. Let us look at the property “time in singular.” What could one question here? The straightforward action would be the logical one: to negate the wall
154
19 Our Approach
property. So the negation of “time in singular” would be either “no time at all,” “time in plural.” We would have to ask whether it makes sense to have not one but several times. Time would then be a plural concept. But how might this be? Would we have a masculine and a feminine time? Or ten times, or none, or what? We learn here that it is not easy to act on an identified wall. Brutally breaking down the wall of a singular time is not the answer of the open question since the logical method does not take care of the specific ‘anatomy’ of the critical concept. So let us look at this more carefully. 19.1.5 Opening a Wall and Displaying Its New Perspectives After the first properly creative action of identifying a concept’s wall property, the second creative action consists of creating the open space that can be conceived once the wall is broken. Logically speaking, the breakdown of a wall simply reads as its negation: In Einstein’s situation, it reads like “there are not only one but several times” (even none is possible. . . ). This is of no use so far. The problem is not the brute negation but an extension, which ideally includes the old situation (which was after all not totally useless!). And here lies a further subtlety of creation, since the negation must be refined to a constructive extension of a conceptual landscape. It is the same situation as with Kepler’s second law: If the distance is not the right one, what kind of distance do we need? It is not about negating the distance concept all together, but about extending it in a constructive way. Perhaps could one think of another kind of “distance.” Not the usual one, but one that is of a different nature yet is still some kind of distance. In the Keplerian situation, it turns out that, yes, the distance in terms of the surface covered by the vector from the sun to a planet in a time unit is the wall’s extension. It generalizes the same quantity as the previously conceived circle-shaped trajectory of planets moving at constant velocity. It unites the connecting vector from sun to planet and the velocity the planet has when displacing that vector. Let us look at another example taken from musical creativity. In his first years as a jazz pianist, Cecil Taylor, now recognized as the leading pioneer in free jazz piano music, used to perform in his individual way. His thoroughly percussive attack of keys shocked jazz and classically oriented experts. They agreed that Taylor was obviously incapable of playing the piano in an acceptable way. This acceptable way was defined by the great tradition of piano music, spanning from Mozart’s “oily” fingering realizing the cantabile paradigm, to Liszt’s style that was described by his pupil Valerie Boissier as: “M. Liszt’s playing contains abandonment, a liberated feeling, but even when it becomes impetuous and energetic in his fortissimo, it is still without harshness and dryness. (. . . ) He draws from the piano tones that are purer, mellower and stronger than anyone has been able to do; his touch has an indescribable charm.” From this normative perspective, Taylor’s approach to the piano was unacceptable. You cannot play the piano in this way. In classical music education, it is still believed that there is an ideal way of playing the piano aesthetically.
19.1 Approach to Creativity: A Semiotic Presentation
155
The critical concept here is “playing the piano.” And its wall could be called “cantabile paradigm.” Its negation by Taylor is, of course, not of any use if we simply view it as a logical negation since anything could work in the generic negation. The wall can only be opened if we consider the “cantabile paradigm” as a variant of a multitude of paradigms applied to the way of attacking the piano keys. In this multitude, the percussive paradigm, which opposes the cantabile norm, answers the question raised by Taylor’s piano playing. It is not about connecting discrete pitches to a fluid melody, but about shaping onsets as points in a rhythmical space, where pitch reduces to a secondary parameter. This change of perspective might have been the most difficult one in the given wall configuration: European music tradition had defined pitch as being the most important singular parameter of sound, whereas onset was only used to organize the order of appearance of pitch. Onset was just a logical parameter, something like a tick to position pitch for a melodic contour. This change of perspective is a very powerful technique of wall opening. Let us state its backing principle in intuitive words here. We shall come back to it in detail in chapter 24 under the title of the “Escher Theorem.” What we are dealing with here is a kind of hierarchy of compound attributes. In our case, it is the hierarchy of primary versus secondary sound parameters. Pitch is primary, onset or loudness are secondary. This means that when dealing with a sound event, it is a pitch that has onset, loudness, duration, and possibly also a sound color. But it is above all a pitch. The Escher Theorem deals with hypergestures, which are, in a very intuitive description, “gestures of gestures.” The Escher Theorem then allows us to permute the order of gestural components in hypergestures. So, for example, if the hypergesture is a circle of line movements, the permuted hypergesture would be a line of circle movements. So the circle perspective “circle of. . . ” would be replaced by the line perspective “line of. . . ” This change can also be applied to sound parameters. A “pitch with onset. . . ” can be viewed as an “onset with pitch. . . ” So the Escher Theorem enables us to change the perspective of a compound attribute. This is much finer than the simple logical negation because it takes care of the given anatomy of conceptual walls. It does not destroy them all together, but handles them in a different way. 19.1.6 Visual Representation of the Wall Paradigm The idea of conceptual walls as described above uses the wall concept in a purely abstract way. Although we spoke about opening a wall, for example, there has been no substantial use of this metaphor qua metaphor. When applying the wall paradigm, we should try also to offer a visual representation of these ideas that might help manage such abstract concepts in a manner that enables objects to represent concepts in a reliable way. The delicate point here is that the context, where concepts and their walls live, are quite general semiotics, where any kind of connotational, metatheoretic, and motivational imbrication (the Baboushka principle) might apply.
156
19 Our Approach
Such a complex configuration does not allow for simple, say 3D, spatial representation of concepts.
Fig. 19.1. Walls that limit rooms can be used for visual representation of creativity process steps. The semantics of a concept may be represented by stepping from one room to a neighboring room.
We nevertheless suggest a simple visualization of concepts, namely as rooms within a complex building. The building might not be representable, but a single room representing a concept might help (see Figure 19.1). In this visualization, a wall might be represented by a wall of that room, and the wall’s opening might be visualized as a door in that wall. The advantage here is that opening a wall might lead you into another room, so that the semantics of a concept will look like navigation through a configuration of connected rooms. It is also advantageous to think of such conceptual configurations as spatial ones and to imagine the elimination of a wall as an opening of that room to new spatial perspectives defining larger rooms. This visualization strategy also fits into the description of concepts in the denotator formalism since denotators have components that are also denotators and could be visualized by walls pointing to denotator components as adjacent rooms. This room visualization is, however, not representative of the underlying semiotic structures, because a room does not decompose into a sign-theoretical three-component object with expression, signification, and content. The only representation of such semiotic linkage can be realized when stepping from a room into an adjacent room that represents a property of the former room and thereby helps access hidden contents (or semantics). The room metaphor is mainly efficient when thinking of concepts as limited spatial configurations whose limits are given by defining properties, namely the room walls and what lies on the other side of such walls. So the visualization strongly suggests that a concept is limited as a space of thoughts and that those limitations could be questioned and possibly eliminated.
19.2 Approach to Creativity: A Mathematical Model
157
19.1.7 Evaluating the Extended Walls Once we have constructed an extended wall concept, the creative procedure is clear: The extended wall is applied to the given open question. If the question is answered, we are done; otherwise we go back to the wall search stage described in section 19.1.4 and start over. In the successful case, the given semiotic context has been extended and is ready for a further creative investigation or practical application. Despite having technically achieved closure, one should always stop the creative cycle at this point and reflect on the deeper lesson about why this extension was successful and how one might apply the insights to a future question that asks for creative solutions.
19.2 Approach to Creativity: A Mathematical Model In the following discourse we shall relate the previous theoretical model of creativity to a less generic context, namely mathematical category theory. A similar model can be exhibited, but it is one that has obtained a deep significance in the development of mathematics since category theory began to influence algebraic geometry, eventually leading to topos theory, which now is the foundation of geometry, logic, computer science, and physics. This model is based upon the core construction that led to topos theory: namely, the famous Yoneda lemma. This lemma is an easy mathematical proposition, its proof is just two lines of mathematical arguments. But its consequences are huge and deep. Let us first state the lemma in its technical form. If X, Y are two objects in a category C, then there is a map that associates with X, Y their set-valued functors @X, @Y , i.e. contravariant functors C → Ens with values in the category Ens of sets. And it associates with every morphism f : X → Y a natural transformation @ : @X → @Y . The Yoneda lemma states that this map ∼
Hom(X, Y ) → N at(@X, @Y ) from the set Hom(X, Y ) of morphisms from X to Y to the set N at(@X, @Y ) of natural transformations from @X to @Y is always a bijection. This means in particular that X and Y are isomorphic if and only if @X and @Y are so. This implies that one may look at the functors @X instead of the objects X of a category. This looks quite abstract and harmless, but it has deep implications. The lemma first of all implies that one may look at the functor @X in order to fully understand X since the functor’s isomorphism class reflects the class of X. But looking at the functor means this: We replace the abstract object X with a system of sets, namely one set A@X = Hom(A, X) for each object A of the category C. We call A also an address of the functor. Why? Because A@X is the set of all perspectives (= morphisms) looking at X, so one intuitively
158
19 Our Approach
stands on the address object A and looks at X. The address A is where one stands when looking at X. Yoneda’s overall statement is then that X is fully understood (that is, its isomorphism class is known) if one knows what X looks like from all possible addresses. So the first step toward understanding X is to select all addresses A and to look at X. Of course these addresses are not independent but also have address change morphisms g : B → A that connect them. For such an address change g, we then have a set map g@X : A@X → B@X that sends the perspective f : A → X to the perspective f ◦ g : B → X. In most cases it is not necessary to inspect all addresses to understand X. For example, if C = Ens, then the singleton address A = 1 = {∅} is sufficient to obtain the isomorphism class of X since the set 1@X is in bijection with X, so the cardinality of X is the same as 1@X, the set of perspectives of X viewed from the singleton address 1. The inspection of addresses A to help understand X is a major effort in category theory. For example, in algebraic geometry, the points of a scheme X are often chosen to be algebraically closed fields, the C-valued points being the most prominent address selection. Suppose we have exhibited a system of characteristic addresses (sufficient for characterizing X up to isomorphism). Suppose that this system also specifies transitional address changes. This is formally described by (1) a diagram D in C that contains address changes gijk : Ai → Aj with (2) the perspectives fi : Ai → X from these addresses to X (compatible with the address changes). Then if the category has colimits (in particular if it is a topos), we may step over to the colimit colim(D) of the diagram and its canonical morphism f : colim(D) → X induced by the perspectives fi . Clearly, this latter morphism in some sense “summarizes” the characteristic perspectives fi and represents the understading of X in a single perspective from the “big” address colim(D). Since the colimit address is so powerful, the next step would be investigating its own functor @colim(D). This means that our process starting from X is now completed and may restart from the big colimit address. This procedure looks very formal, but it is completely analogous to the general semiotic creativity process described above3 . Let us trace this analogy. To begin with, the open question must be defined. In the categorical setup, this would be the question of understanding the behavior of X. For example, if X = R, the problem would be that all squares of real numbers are not negative, x2 ≥ 0. This is also equivalent to the fact that there are quadratic polynomials without real roots, such as x2 + 2. Next, we would identify the semiotic context of the question. Here, we would exhibit a category C, and then identify X as the critical object in C. The next procedure is the inspection of the critical concept’s walls. This means to inspect the general behavior of the critical concept and to look for its characteristics. In the mathematical context, this means to investigate the object’s functor @X, namely to look at X from all the addresses as explained above. In the case of X = R, we would look at a polynomial 3
And it in fact inspired the construction semiotic variant.
19.3 The List of the Creativity Process
159
ring R[x], and its quotients R[x]/P by irreducible polynomials P . The perspectives4 would be just the embeddings R → R[x], R → R[x]/P . The address changes would be the quotient morphisms R[x] → R[x]/P . If the wall inspection leads to a repertory of critical properties, these are represented by our diagram D of characteristic addresses. They allow us to understand the critical concept/object X. The opening of X by this diagram D enables an extended understanding of X, and this is what is represented by the big address and its arrow f : colim(D) → X to X. So we would have extended the naive context X by this big new colimit object. We should stress that the question heres is not to have an object X, or any other being a member of the given category, but to have a technical access to understanding this object’s behavior.
19.3 The List of the Creativity Process To conclude this chapter, we give a summary of the creativity process in the form of a list to which we refer in this book: 1. Exhibiting the open question 2. Identifying the semiotic context 3. Finding the question’s critical sign or concept in the semiotic context 4. Identifying the concept’s walls 5. Opening the walls 6. Displaying extended wall perspectives 7. Evaluating the extended walls
4
Arrows are reversed here, but in algebraic geometry, this is canonical via the prime spectra of these rings.
20 Principles of Creative Pedagogy
The concept of a creative pedagogy as an approach to creative teaching was introduced by Andrei Aleinikov in 1989 [4]. We summarize its theoretical and practical aspects and discuss its realization when introducing our concept of creativity. We conclude with the special situation of creative pedagogy in musical education, where not only the methodological aspect of this pedagogy relates to creativity (which would be the case in general education in chemistry or physics, for example), but also the creative activity of a composer or improviser.
20.1 Origins of Creative Pedagogy Following Andrei Aleinikov’s definition [4], creative pedagogy is defined as: Creative pedagogy that includes educational influence on the learner for acquisition of certain study material (subject) [as pedagogy in general] and differing from the above by the fact that in order to achieve higher efficiency of learning, the pedagogical influence is provided on the background of centrifugal above-the-criticism mutual activity in which the learner is raised from the object of [pedagogical] influence to the rank of a creative person, while the traditional (basic) study material is transformed from the subject to learn into the means of achieving some creative goal, and the extra study material includes the description and demonstration of the heuristic methods and techniques. This is an educational methodology, not education to become creative. The educational field can be any science or art. Learning is meant as achieving a creative goal. The learning process is different from the traditional one, and this new approach to shaping classes is called “creative transformation.” The learner is no longer an “object” of pedagogy, but becomes a creator in the field being taught. G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 20, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
161
162
20 Principles of Creative Pedagogy
This methodology is the one that is needed in the twenty-first century for the development of a new social class, the Creative Class [43]. This class fulfills the growing need for experts in the continuous renewal and extension of our knowledge society. A variant of creative pedagogy has been implemented in a science called TRIZ (a Russian acronym), and translated to “Theory of Inventive Problem Solving.” Boris Zlotin and Alla Susman [128] describe TRIZ as being invented in Russia by Genrich Altshuller in the 1940s. It is based on the study of evolutionary patterns in various systems of technology, science, and organization. Methods for creative solutions of problems were developed and have been summarized as follows [128]: 1. The logical analysis of a given system and its problems. This enables users of TRIZ to understand the essence of a problem and to reveal the nonobvious contradictions that hinder problem solving. 2. The application of a special knowledge base that includes the most effective methods of problem solving, along with examples of how these methods are used. 3. The means to overcome psychological inertia in the process of problem solving. It is remarkable that this list resembles our concept of creativity in the following sense: Similar to our setup, the list starts with a problem, together with a system where the problem is located, corresponding to our semiotic where the problem is situated. In the list, the essence of the problem has to be found. We would see this as corresponding to our critical concept. Further, they have to reveal the non-obvious contradictions that hinder problem solving. In our setup this would be the inspection of the concept’s walls. Next, they apply special knowledge bases for effectively solving the problem. In our setup this would mean to open the walls and to find conceptual extensions that eventually would solve the problem. The last item in their list is of a psychological nature, and we would attribute it to the problem of finding walls since becoming aware of critical walls also depends upon the sensitivity to the concept’s hidden limits. An important point in this TRIZ approach is its relation to language. It is rightly remarked that children are naturally creative, but that the infusion of language with its normative logical nature builds a strong obstruction to creativity, since creativity is “paralogic” (wording by the TRIZ authors). In our approach, we do not specify the language but the semiotics, which is an extended representation of what the TRIZ authors think about language. In our approach, the effect of a successful creative action is always an extension of the given semiotics, which in terms of language means extension of the language. Clearly this is a big effort against the language’s normative power. The inability to imagine an extended language (or: The inability to conceive that a language can be extended) is due to this normative framework, and it
20.2 Applying Our Concept of Creativity to Creative Pedagogy
163
is clear also that children1 who are not yet casted by the language’s norms can be more creative and will often lose this ability as they become immersed in the language’s rigid status quo. The TRIZ authors then also criticize the inevitable battle that characterizes the relationship of teachers and students—the battle of rigid norms against creative extensions. They propose replacing this battle relationship with one where a teacher assists students in their quest for self-perfection.
20.2 Applying Our Concept of Creativity to Creative Pedagogy Our concept of creativity is built as a multistep process as described in chapter 19. Summarizing, its steps are: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6.
Exhibiting the open question Identifying the semiotic context Finding the question’s critical sign or concept in the semiotic context Identifying the concept’s walls Opening the walls and displaying its new perspectives Evaluating the extended walls
Essentially, we are dealing with an extension procedure that starts in a given semiotic system and adds extended conceptual perspectives so that we obtain an extended semiotic context. If successful, this creation solves the original problem. This process is very akin to what is constructed in algebraic Galois theory, which starts with a polynomial phrasing of an open question and then finds the answers by an extension of the original field. To make this more understandable from an elementary point of view, we want to show how complex numbers C are “discovered” in a creative process, starting from the very beginning with natural numbers N. So let us start with the natural numbers N and seek to solve the equation a + x = b, a, b ∈ N. The answer to this question around the critical concept of the linear equation a + x = b is the group of integers Z. In this domain, a new critical concept is given by the equation ax = b, a, b ∈ Z, a = 0. The extension of Z that answers this question is the field of rationals Q. In this domain, the critical concept is that of a Cauchy sequence (ai )i∈N , which in general does not converge to a rational number. In order to obtain numbers to which all Cauchy sequences converge, we construct the field of real numbers R. Finally, in R the critical concept is a polynomial equation a0 + a1 X + . . . an X n = 0, which may have no solution in R. The 1
We should be aware that children usually do not create masterworks. This is due to the fact that they have neither the maturity of a professional instrumental performer nor are they competent in the complex knowledge about music theory and notation. They simply live in a context where such creations are out of reach.
164
20 Principles of Creative Pedagogy
extension of R to the field of complex numbers C answers this question. And it is remarkable that each extension is found by taking the critical concept as a type of new element of a larger structure; in other words, the very concept that is responsible for the problem also yields the solution! For example, R is obtained from a structure whose elements are the Cauchy sequences over the rationals! And C is obtained from R by considering all the polynomials with real coefficients. This means that the walls provide the doors that offer the solution. Teaching along the idea of creative pedagogy means that we teach a field of knowledge by successively extending a given semiotic context around a critical concept. Learning then means to create a solution following our six-element process of creativity. The pedagogical work consists of presenting the problem, working out critical concepts, searching and inspecting their walls, inventing wall extensions, and finally investigating the potential of such extensions as solutions of the given problem. This procedure puts the students into a situation of being creative, building their knowledge through creative activities. Whether these are successes or failures doesn’t matter, because it is important that the students experience these evolutionary dynamics in the building of a knowledge architecture. The minor miracle in such a work of conceptual extension is that very often the solution is found directly from a precise and clever restatement of the walls, like in arithmetic as explained above! It must be stressed that all these extensions are not purely formal (without content), we really add signs to the given semiotic context, i.e. expressions and contents. This must be taken into account when working out the detailed operations. It is also important to understand the operational character of this type of creative work. We do not rely on psychological categories in the identification of creative activity; creation can be checked without psychology, merely by following the thread of those six steps described above. Of course, it is also true that such an activity may be difficult or even fail because of psychological obstructions. But the explicit “flow chart” of creativity should be of great advantage when asking ourselves where we are located in the adventure of such creative work.
20.3 Creative Pedagogy for Musical Creativity As already recognized by its inventor, creative pedagogy can be applied to any field of knowledge—it is a teaching methodology, not a field of knowledge to be taught. However, when special fields are at stake, the general methodology may be difficult to apply if not problematic. The field of musical invention is such a delicate situation since composition and improvisation are creative activities. When it comes to teaching these fields by creative pedagogy, the tension between methodology and teaching object arises: Teaching creatively
20.3 Creative Pedagogy for Musical Creativity
165
musical creation looks somehow circular. So let us investigate what kind of tension we are dealing with in this case. In the tutorial of the practical part of this book, we have given a number of examples for creative pedagogy (see chapter 3). To begin with, we should think about how to teach musical creativity creatively. Musical creations always have two components: a set of material, such as a set of notes, motives, chords, instruments, etc., and a set of operators that act upon this material, such as Boolean operators, permutations, harmonization, contrapuntal rules, ways to play an instrument, etc. Teaching musical creativity then means to teach creatively how to generate or select material and how to generate or apply operators upon selected material. Both activities, relating to material or operators, can be taught creatively in the sense of applying the creativity “flow chart” to a critical instance of material or operators. For instance, one may question the concept of an instrument and add new instruments by extension of defining properties. The history of the keyboards and of the violin family are excellent examples of such a case. Or one may question the way of playing the piano. The addition of the thumb to piano-playing techniques or the percussive style of piano technique added by Cecil Taylor to the Mozart-Liszt tradition are examples. But also a new way to compose a sonata2 might emerge from a creative questioning of the sonata concept. This means that composing with given rules and materials without any creative process is not what we would like to teach in such a class. Such uncreative processes are just rule-based mechanical activities and not proper compositions. It is evident that such mechanical activities play an important role in the music industry, and there might be a computer program for such algorithmic applications, but this is not what would be taught under the title of creative activities in a composition class. Observe however that the writing of such a program might very well be a creative action, but the produced samples are not, at least not in the semiotic system of the applied rules and materials. Let us give an example. From mathematical music theory, we know that counterpoint can be composed in six so-called worlds according to the six possible dichotomies of the twelve interval pitch classes modulo octave into a “consonant” and a “dissonant” half [77]. The construction of ‘exotic’ counterpoint compositions other than those referring to the classical Fuxian dichotomy of classical consonances—prime, thirds, fifth, and sixths—have been implemented in the RUBATO Composer software by Julien Junod [60]. In this system, an exotic counterpoint would just be a sample of the computer’s program. But if a composer came up with such a composition by questioning the classical Fuxian dichotomy and extending the concept of consonances/dissonances and counterpoint rules, this would define a creative action. In Junod’s program, the creative work had been achieved by the extended counterpoint theory from 2
As Beethoven did with his late sonatas.
166
20 Principles of Creative Pedagogy
[77] and by Junod’s creative writing of such a sophisticated program, applying creatively sophisticated techniques of graph theory. So far we have focused only on composition, but we should also consider improvisation in a creative pedagogy for musical creativity. In the compositional context it is clear how to apply the process of creativity, since one has plenty of time to think about walls and their extensions. When improvising, the process seems to become impossible because improvisation takes place without any time to reflect in a quiet atmosphere. However it is possible to anticipate certain musical constructions, such as motives, chords, or rhythms, and to call them up while improvising. But there is another creative strategy, namely to grasp a critical concept in the making, i.e. to focus on a musical structure being played and to call up its walls in the making. This boils down to focus on typical gestures being performed to realize such a musical structure—a rhythm, a motif, etc. In this moment one would recall Jean Cavaill`es’ insight that “understanding is catching the gesture and being able to continue.” One would take the given gesture and continue it with a new gesture, and, most important, not just mimic it but continue with another gesture that resonates from the first one. The conceptual extension of walls here is realized as a resonance of gestures, quite in the spirit of cultural evolution built upon the psychological DNA paradigm of mirror neurons as suggested by Vilayanur S. Ramachandran [98]. This type of real-time process will enable an improviser to be creative without having to step back for a meditative reflexion. 20.3.1 Conceiving Our Tutorial in Creative Pedagogy for Musical Creativity In the practical part II of this book, we have developed a tutorial applying creative pedagogy to teach musical creativity. The idea behind the tutorial is to implement the above techniques and strategies to educate a student to become a creative composer/improviser. We start by the most elementary situation of absolutely unshaped sonic and instrumental material. Everything that could be imagined as sound or a sound generator would be admitted at the onset. This is the totally chaotic original position. We would then successively introduce extensions of critical concepts in this manifold of sound material or devices. Critical concepts will emerge when the chaotic variety cannot present any interesting statement or utterance. In the tutorial we have organized a tree of successively enriched conceptual extensions, starting with shaping time in rhythm, or pitch in scales, etc., and thereby giving the student all the power to shape his/her compositional strategies and tools. The overall development in the tutorial would show the student how to generate a successively more sophisticated composition when applying the sequence of conceptual extension. It might seem contradictory to state that successively enriched creative activity with a sequence of conceptual extensions would generate a more and more non-chaotic, orderly composition. One would rather expect the opposite in musical creativity: the movement to increasingly
20.3 Creative Pedagogy for Musical Creativity
167
wild compositions by use of such conceptual extensions. It is a common misunderstanding that musical creativity tends to produce wild works. The famous conductor Nikolaus Harnoncourt once remarked, “The highest creation is the one which can express its thoughts in a very limited context, such as a small chamber ensemble, not a Wagner orchestra.” Creativity is about applying the finest choices to build new works, much like the existence of the human species is only possible in the extremely refined terrestrial environment of the universe. In our tutorial, the creation of a musical composition will be generating an intelligent output that expresses all the richness of the creative path of the tutorial’s logical tree. If wild compositions emerge, they will be wild only on their surfaces; the internal logic will be a richer one, but possibly difficult to see without a sophisticated culture of understanding music. Creativity is always a taming act of the chaos, never its progressive extension. We shall illustrate this fact in the case study of Beethoven’s third movement in op. 109, (chapter 26), where the wild trill surface of the finale in the sixth variation is the disciplined and precise expression of a cadential symmetry.
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
This chapter is about technological issues of music and therefore might be more interesting to those who deal with technology, for example in computer music, studio recording and postproduction, or new electronic instruments. However, this chapter is not a standard exposition of acoustics and music hardware and software as may be found in textbooks about music technology, such as [55, 81]. We shall discuss those contents but with emphasis on their potential roles as tools for musical creativity. This chapter is also conceptually demanding and may be used as a reference for those who want to apply principles of creativity to technological environments. We do in fact believe that technological tools are essential for the expansion of creative processes only if they are understood as autonomous devices and not just as realizations of given paradigms. Recall that the free jazz pioneer, saxophonist, and composer Ornette Coleman used the violin in a very creative way in his free jazz performances, but only because he completely disregarded the standard usage. And John Cage created new ways of playing classical instruments, such as the organ in his composition “ASLSP,” where a new pipe is installed every period of several years for the total duration of 639 years!
21.1 Acoustic Reality Acoustics deals with the physics of sound. Sound is generated by a sound source, typically an instrument or human voice in musical contexts (see Figure 21.1). This sound source acts on the molecules of air and makes them produce a variable air pressure (around the normal pressure of 110.130Pa, Pa = N m−2 , at sea level) that propagates through space, is redirected by walls and objects, and then reaches the human ear, which is sensitive to such pressure variations. The auditory nerves in the cochlea in the inner ear then conduct the sound input to the auditory cortex and other sensitive afferent brain centers, where G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 21, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
169
170
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.1. Sound is generated by a sound source, typically an instrument or human voice in musical contexts. This sound source acts on the molecules of air and makes them produce a variable air pressure that propagates through space, is redirected by walls and objects, and then reaches the human ear, which is sensitive to such pressure variations. The auditory nerves in the cochlea in the inner ear then conduct the sound input to the auditory cortex and other sensitive afferent brain centers, where different properties of the sound information are perceived and processed for the human cognition.
different properties of the sound information are perceived and processed for the human cognition. This basic setup can be taken as a germ for musical creativity. But what would be a problem here? There are many! To begin with, let us first blank out the instrumental source structure providing the sound, so we may focus on the complex trajectory of the sound from the source to the ear. In the realization of sounding works of art, the problem of controlling the trajectory is crucial. Historically, this relates to room acoustics: How can we shape the music halls in such a way that performed works can be heard in an optimal way? This original problem has the sound trajectory (from source to ears) as its critical concept. What are the sound trajectory’s walls? A subtle wall is the assumption that sound travels through air with the given speed and follows the room’s physical walls and other objects until it reaches the human ears. This wall specifies a given travel mode. Sound travels through air, and it does so without any further influence. It is just “given physics.” This is the hard part of this wall: What could we do against given physics? Let us see how this is feasible. To begin with, we can question the path. Why does
21.1 Acoustic Reality
171
the sound have to go through air, be reflected at walls, and enter the human ear? Couldn’t we imagine other pathways? A first opening of the wall would be to ask whether a direct pathway is mandatory. And it is not. There are a number of technologies to split the trajectory into a multistep pathway. The sound can be piped into a microphone system and then distributed to a number of loudspeakers. This has been done not only for simple reasons of acoustical quality in music halls and dance clubs, but also to redefine the output in an artistic way, for example when a multiplicity of loudspeakers is part of the composition and may enable migration of sound among several loudspeakers. Another interruption of the sound trajectory might be saving the sound on a tape or digital soundfile. This relay station can then be used to reconstruct the sound and apply any kind of sound processing before forwarding the sound to the audience. Finally, following some ideas from Venetian polychoral style of distributed choirs, one may also rethink the role of the music hall’s space, extending use of the stage to the entire hall (including audience space and even the music hall’s bar) and setting up musicians to play anywhere. 21.1.1 First Sound Anatomy The structure of musical sound waves is described in Figure 21.2. They consist of longitudinal waves, i.e. the pressure variation of air moves in the direction of sound propagation away from the sound source. If they carry the pitch, the variation of pressure is periodic, i.e. a snapshot of the pressure shows a regularly repeated pressure along the sound’s expansion in space. The time period P of this regularity, as shown in Figure 21.2, defines the sound’s frequency f = 1/P . For example, the chamber pitch a1 has frequency 440Hz. And going an octave higher means to double frequency; therefore, the octave a2 above a1 has frequency 880Hz. The wave’s pressure amplitude A (relative to the normal pressure) is perceived as loudness. For example, the minimal loudness that can be perceived by the human ear at 1000Hz is A0 = 2.105 N m−2 . Loudness for amplitude A is then defined by l(A) = 20. log10 (A/A0 )dB, where the unit dB is Decibel. What could be a creative endeavor in this elementary sound description? A sound is a wave, starting at an onset time, lasting a certain time (its duration), and during that time showing the amplitude and periodicity discussed above. Taking this kind of objects as an element of music, however is a problem. To begin with, it is not clear why these attributes should hold during the entire sound. Why should amplitude be constant? A sound may well increase its loudness. And then, why is the pitch constant? What about glissandi? And finally, where do we find access to the sound color, the instrumental characteristic? Putting all these questions together, the critical concept here is the parameters that are used to describe the sound object. They are all too simplified and incomplete to cope with musical reality. The walls in this situation are the
172
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.2. Standard parameters for sound with frequency (pitch).
parameters used to describe sound. Are these parameters inevitable—does sound has to have one pitch, one loudness, etc.? And where is sound color hidden? Isn’t periodicity for pitch too simple to catch all of the sound’s anatomy? Of course, the wall character of these parameters is supported by the correspondence with notation of sound in scores. Onset, duration, loudness, pitch, instrument name—all of this is described in classical score notation. But only when comparing these forms to the real sound events does one become aware that these walls are not necessary and that opening them can create richer musical compositions. We shall come back to such options in the discussion of sound synthesis methods, such as Fourier, FM, wavelets, and physical modeling. But one big wall has not yet even been mentioned: the fact that sounds must be fabricated. Sounds are not there by themselves; they are made by some agent. And this is the theme of the next section. 21.1.2 Making Sound It is perhaps one of the most intriguing walls in the theory of music that sounds are not abstract entities defined by mathematical parameters such as onset, duration, loudness, and pitch. They are not even defined by mathematical sound parameters but by the way the variation of sound pressure is realized as a physical process. Sound must be made, not mathematically but physically. It is not astonishing that music theory does not take care of this elementary fact since human understanding usually starts from huge abstraction. For example, numbers and their arithmetics are abstracted entities from real ob-
21.1 Acoustic Reality
173
ject assemblies. One takes five apples and adds three apples, but arithmetic yields eight apples independently of whether these objects are apples, bananas or planets. Music theory is about very strict abstraction. Usually, in harmony one disregards duration, loudness, and instrumental color and only focuses on pitch, or even pitch classes modulo octave. How then was it that making sound became a strong paradigm beyond abstraction? Until the first half of the eighteenth century, instruments were still placeholders for voices; any instrument would do if it could play the pitches required. But around 1750, also the moment when the string quartet emerged with Haydn and Boccherini, the voices were required to express increasingly complex structures. The abstract note sets were set in such a complexity that their sensual expression required more and more sophisticated sound bodies. So the complexity of abstraction enforced a corresponding complexity in expression. And vice versa: The increase in expressive power of the family of violins, and the richer color spectrum of the piano, enabled increasing complexity of compositional structures. What is this wall about? It is about the intimate relationship between abstract musical structures, of counterpoint and harmony, say, and their expression via a sounding body. This relationship has never been recognized as the central topic of orchestration, so it is a wall in the best sense of our theoretical approach: invisible at first, and impenetrable. How could abstract music structure be related to these very practical instrumental objects? Even Beethoven argued that this “stupid violinist” Schuppanzigh was not his concern if he could not play his supreme tones. The philosophy of this resonance of structure and instrumental expressivity is a creative extension of what it means to play an instrument. What is the point of this creative extension? It means that a musician’s movements on an instrument that merely cope with the required abstract note parameters limit not only the musician’s bodily richness, but also the the potential expressivity required by advanced compositions. In other words, the creation of instruments is not just a technical process for the realization of abstract tone parameters, but an activity in its own right. And the richness of instrumental interaction is a field of primary musical interest. Making music is a rich dance of the musician’s limbs on the complex interface of the music instrument. Figure 21.3 shows three methods for the production of regular sound pressure variations (inducing pitched sound), using clarinet, flute, and trumpet. Each method creates pressure variations in different ways. With the clarinet, the air vibration is generated by the vibrating reed. With the flute, the air vibration is generated by an alternating air stream moving into the flute or outside. With the trumpet, the air vibration is generated by vibration of the musician’s lips. Accordingly, the technical basis of musical expressivity varies strongly. So it is definitely not about producing the abstract pitch here.
174
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.3. Three methods for the production of regular sound pressure variations (inducing pitched sound), using clarinet, flute, and trumpet.
Although these examples are evident messages about the body’s expressivity in the making of music, the really complex case is the violin family, whose typical representative, the violin, is shown in Figure 21.4.
Fig. 21.4. The violin’s anatomy and its cross-section.
21.1 Acoustic Reality
175
The violin, as it had been developed to its ideal shape by the families of Stradivari, Amati, and Guarneri in the first decennia of the eighteenth century, is a highly complex mechanical device. Essentially, its sound is produced by drawing a bow across one or more of the five strings, whose horizontal vibration is transmitted by the bridge to make the belly plate—and, via the sound post, also the back plate—vibrate vertically. The vibrational shapes on these plates are extremely complex and can be classified following investigations of Ernst Chladni by so-called modes (basic vibrational states), which are visualized in Figure 21.5. The fabrication of the plates is a highly artistic process. For example, the quality of these plates is checked by a number of bending actions with the artisan’s hands. This gestural access to the instrument is complemented by a rich repertory of playing modes, such as plucking the strings, knocking the belly plate, etc. Also the bowing can be executed on different locations of the violin’s strings and with different movements, such as chopping, shuffle, col legno, lour´e, sautill´e, etc. In other words, the violin is a gestural universe, and it is an interface that requires intense training and sensitivity.
Fig. 21.5. Chladni’s resonance modes describe a secret of a violin’s quality.
This characterization is also valid for the other instruments of that family. And it is the basis of the dominating role of string orchestras, and especially of the string quartet. The development of the string quartet has proved that the gestural extension of the violin family’s sound production universe has become the driving creative force for a compositional approach that does not theorize, but simply applies the technical tools of the instruments as compositional methods.
176
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Summarizing, we have learned that making sound on a sophisticated instrument is not just a complicated way of letting abstract sound parameters take place in acoustical reality, but it is also a highly creative interface between structural and expressive universes. And these universes have no hierarchical relationship with each other; on the contrary, they set into action a deep resonance of extensions in structure and performative expression. Following these lines of thought, orchestration should include a theory of this resonance and answer the questions concerning adequacy of an orchestra for a given composition, and vice versa (the adequacy of a composition for a given orchestra). It should deal in a scientific way (!) with categories of questions such as why a recorder quartet cannot adequately perform a Beethoven string quartet, or why a simple song such as Happy Birthday to You should not be performed by a Wagner orchestra. 21.1.3 Fourier The instrumental extension of abstract sound parameters is complemented by descriptions of sound colors independent of the instruments that produce them. Or rather: using very simple devices that act like ‘atomic’ instruments, whose combination yields a complex sound. Among these attempts, Joseph Fourier’s theorem, discovered in research about heat conductance around 1800, provides a first model. The atomic “instruments” he uses are vibrating masses m attached to a fixed point at distance x by a spring with spring force constant k, and moving along a fixed line. Newton’s differential equation for the force acting upon m is m.d2 x/dt2 = −k.x. The solution of this vibrating system is a sinusoidal function x(t) = (k/m) sin(t). Recall that pitch of a sounding periodic air pressure vibration w(t) is proportional to the logarithm of its frequency f = 1/P eriod. Fourier’s theorem then states that w(t) can be expressed in a unique way as a sum of sinusoidal functions, or, so to speak, as a sum of those atomic instruments given by masses and springs (see Figure 21.6). Uniqueness means that for the given frequency f of w(t), the amplitudes A0 , A1 , A2 , . . . and the phases P h1 , P h2 , . . . are uniquely determined (and called amplitude and phase spectrum, respectively). The nth component function An sin(2π.nf t + P hn ) is called the nth partial or overtone of w(t). Before we delve into the creative investigation of this setup, let us describe how the Fourier theorem is related to realistic sounds. We have to see that the wave function w(t) is all but natural. In reality no such infinitely lasting regular air vibration can occur. The relationship to realistic sounds can be seen in Figure 21.7. If a singer sings “laaaa” at a determined pitch, the pressure variation around the mean pressure looks like a bundle as shown on top of Figure 21.7. The bundle can be described by its envelope, i.e. the locally maximal pressure variations (shown at the left bottom), and by a periodic excitation of pressure, limited by the envelope, and shown to the bottom right.
21.1 Acoustic Reality
177
Fig. 21.6. Joseph Fourier’s theorem, discovered in research about heat conductance around 1800, provides a first model of sound as composed of ‘atomic’ sound shapes: sinusoidal functions.
This combination of envelope and periodic function yields the realistic sound. In a systematic building process as shown in Figure 21.8, this means that the periodic wave w(t) is superimposed with the envelope H (normed to duration and maximal excitation both = 1), and then shifted and squeezed by a so-called support to yield onset, duration, and amplitude of the real sound. In technological modeling of this building process, the envelope is often represented in a very simple shape, following the so-called ADSR (Attack Decay Sustain Release) model as shown in Figure 21.9. Although this seems to describe realistic sounds quite faithfully, it turns out that instrumental sounds are more complex in that the partials are given independent amplitude envelopes that enable the sound to have variable overtones as it evolves in time. Figure 21.10 shows such a situation for a trumpet sound. The graphic displays envelopes for each partial, and we see that higher partials have lower and shorter envelopes, meaning that the amplitudes of these partials contribute only a short time and to a lower degree to the overall sound. The display of these temporally variable overtone envelopes is called chronospectrum. Fourier’s theorem and the description of sounds by overtones are firm scientific facts, as a mathematical theorem cannot be deemed false once its proof is correct. Why can such a fact be a problem for musical creativity? To begin with, its facticity seems to condemn everybody to its unrestricted acceptance. It is an eternal truth. And can an overtone-related analysis— although not precisely true [77, Appendix B.1]—in the inner ear cochlea’s Corti
178
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.7. When a singer sings the syllable “laaaa” at a determined pitch, the pressure variation around the mean pressure looks like a bundle as shown on top. The bundle can be described by its envelope, i.e. the locally maximal pressure variations (shown at the left bottom), and by a periodic excitation of pressure, limited by the envelope, and shown to the bottom right.
Fig. 21.8. This combination of envelope and periodic function yields the realistic sound.
organ be taken as a strong argument for the universal presence of the Fourier decomposition of a sound? The wall here is precisely the mathematical truth of this theorem. Nobody can even think of putting the theorem into question. This theorem is the critical concept. But the creative softening of its wall(s) can be accomplished when we think about the justification of this theorem: We are analyzing a sound, and
21.1 Acoustic Reality
179
Fig. 21.9. The envelope is often represented in a very simple shape, following the so-called ADSR (Attack Decay Sustain Release) model.
Fig. 21.10. A trumpet sound. The graphic displays envelopes for each partial, and we see that higher partials have lower and shorter envelopes, meaning that the amplitudes of these partials contribute only a short time and to a lower degree to the overall sound. The display of these temporally variable overtone envelopes is called chronospectrum.
Fourier tells us how to do so. But analysis is not synthesis. The wall softens if we question the exclusivity of analysis. After all, composers are interested in synthesis rather than in analysis. The point here is whether this formula is the end of an insight or the beginning thereof. If it is just about understanding a periodic function, it is the end, but if it is about putting together atomic instruments (the sinusoidal functions) to form a compound instrument, it is a new thing. We could construct instruments by adding sinusoidal functions, provided with their individual amplitude envelopes. And we do not have to
180
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
add sinusoidal functions with frequencies that are multiples of a fundamental frequency. This latter generalization is called inharmonic partials. Summarizing, there is no need to follow the original formula, but we can generalize it and generate compound sounds with the original building rule but more flexible. This is precisely what spectral composition discovered [47]. They were interested in composing sounds, not abstract symbols. And the synthetic interpretation of Fourier’s formula was the technical tool they used to shape the sound’s anatomy as a living body. 21.1.4 FM, Wavelets, Physical Modeling We now discuss some prominent sound synthesis methods which complement Fourier’s traditional approach. They also prove that Fourier’s decomposition is not the only one that one might conceive in the description of a sound’s ‘anatomy’. 21.1.4.1 Chowning’s FM Synthesis Fourier’s formula has not only provoked more general compositional approaches, such as spectral music, but also more realistic sound representation for the technology of sound synthesis. The first of these innovations was introduced by John Chowning in 1967 at Stanford University and was called FM for “Frequency Modulation.” His invention was patented and had a remarkable commercial success with Yamaha’s DX7 synthesizer since 1983 (see Figure 21.11). The creative idea was again to review the critical concept in Fourier’s theory. It was critical in the context of sound synthesis technology since the production of reasonable sound colors is described by a huge number of overtones and of corresponding envelopes. Whereas the spectral music creativity focused on the extension of sinusoidal components in Fourier’s formula, Chowning questioned its arithmetical construction. This was a delicate wall since addition of sinusoidal functions for the partials is hard to open. Should one just negate addition, and then how should it be replaced or embed by another operation? Should one multiply sinusoidal waves? Or apply any other operation? There are infinitely many such candidates, mostly unattractive because of mathematical properties. And the problem was not only the addition as operation but also the number of summands necessary to produce interesting sounds. Chowning’s idea was highly creative in that he succeeded in replacing addition with another operation, which also allowed him to massively reduce the number of sinusoidal components. As seen from Yamaha’s list of components used in DX7, only six components are used in this technology. How can we build complex sounds with only six overtones? The idea focuses on the meaning of the wall “addition of sinusoidal partials.” The original formula for a wave w(t) as shown in Figure 21.11 takes a fundamental wave and changes its values by the values of a second overtone,
21.1 Acoustic Reality
181
Fig. 21.11. John Chowning’s invention of “Frequency Modulation” (FM) in 1967 at Stanford University.
and then this sum has values that are in turn changed by values of a third overtone, etc. Chowning’s idea was to have the influence of higher overtones not on the values of the preceding overtones, but on their time arguments. Instead of having time in a linear expression 2π.n.f.t + P hn , Chowning allowed a nonlinear correction of the time argument, the nonlinearity being defined by the overtone function! This means that instead of adding to values, his new synthesis formula adds to arguments! The result is shown in the formula W (t) in Figure 21.11, where the second overtone value is added to the argument of the first overtone, and where the third overtone value is added to the argument of the second overtone. The overtone distortion of the time argument is called a modulator, and it in facts modulates the frequency, in the sense of a time function distortion of the frequency-related linear argument. In Chowning’s approach, it was also permitted to add several overtone distortions to the linear time argument. The resulting architecture shows a number of sinusoidal functions (called carriers) that are altered by other sinusoidal functions (called modulators). Yamaha calls such an architecture an “algorithm.” Yamaha’s DX7 displays 32 such algorithms. Some of them are even their own modulators. Of course this is possible on the technological realization since output and input values of these sinusoidal “boxes” are shifted by elementary time units.
182
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
21.1.4.2 Wavelets
Fig. 21.12. A wavelet function g(t) of time. It is a sinusoidal function cos(wt) that has been modified by the envelope function exp(−t2 /2).
Although FM synthesis was a huge step in the reduction of sinusoidal components and the richness of sound colors realized in consumer technology, the FM formula (what Yamaha calls an algorithm) is still far from realistic. Because it is infinite like Fourier’s formula, the sinusoidal components are not limited functions. There is a canonical way to correct this, namely by envelopes. And this is exactly what was done in the approach of wavelet functions. Figure 21.12 shows such a wavelet function g(t) of time. It is a sinusoidal function cos(wt) that has been modified by the envelope function exp(−t2 /2). Although this is still an infinitely extended function, its values converge fast to zero by the exponential envelope. In wavelet theory, there are many such wavelet functions, but all have the property of showing the shape of a timely short wave “package,” and this is why such functions are called wavelets. They play the role of sound atoms, much as sinusoidal waves in Fourier theory. Whereas sinusoidal waves are modulated by amplitude, frequency, and phase, wavelets are modulated by a time delay argument b and an expansion argument a to yield the deformed wavelets ga,b (t) = g((t−b)/a). Figure 21.12 shows a number of such deformations that are placed in the plane of a and b.
21.1 Acoustic Reality
183
The creative component of this theory is to take one single sinusoidal wave ‘atom’ g(t), limit it by a strong envelope, and vary its time position and duration according to a whole two-dimensional parameter set (a, b). The open question is then whether this two-dimensional variety of deformed and shifted wavelet atoms is capable of representing a given sound function s(t). The answer is positive, and it can be stated as follows: Define a coefficient function 1 S(b, a) = ( √ ) g a,b (t) · s(t)dt. a This function replaces the Fourier coefficient calculation. So we have an entire two-dimensional function, not only that discrete set of amplitudes and phases of the Fourier formula. But like with Fourier, this new function enables the reconstruction of the original sound wave by the followig formula: s(t) = Qg ga,b (t) · S(b, a)dadb, where Qg is a constant depending on the chosen wavelet type g. An example of the coefficient function is given in Figure 21.13, see [63]. Here the gray value represents the numerical value of the coefficient function. The octaves in this musical example are visible as dark coefficient values.
Fig. 21.13. An example of the coefficient function. The gray value represents the numerical value of the coefficient function. The octaves in this musical example are visible as dark coefficient values.
21.1.4.3 Physical Modeling The last example of refined sound modeling is a radical change of paradigm. In Fourier’s theorem, Chowning’s FM, and the wavelet methods, we always
184
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
dealt with sound representation. We have to recall however that instrumental technology, as discussed above for the violin family, has always been a radical answer to the question of sound synthesis. It is an answer of sound production, as opposed to the more or less abstract representation by mathematical formulas. With the development of powerful personal computers, the instrumental approach has been recreated on the level of software simulation of entire instruments. It has become realistic to not only create an “instrument” built from a series of sinusoidal waves a la Fourier, but also to simulate complex physical configurations on fast computers. This approach has three styles, namely: •
The Mass-Spring Model: The software simulates classical systems of point masses that are connected by springs and then outputs the sound wave resulting from the movement of such mechanical systems. A famous example is Chordis Anima developed by the Institute ACROE Grenoble, which was presented at the ICMC (International Computer Music Conference) in 1994. • Modal Synthesis: Modeling of different sinusoidal components that are experimentally determined, e.g. Modalys-Mosacic at IRCAM (Institut de Recherche et Coordination Acoustique/Musique) [92]. • Waveguide: It models propagation of waves in a medium, such as air or string. This is implemented, for example, at Stanford’s CCRMA (Center for Computer Research in Music and Acoustics), and a commercial version is realized on YAMAHA’s VL-1. Physical modeling is not just a simulation of physical instruments in software environments. By the generic character of such software, the parameters of the physical instruments, such as string length, diameter, material elasticity, material density, and so forth, can be chosen without any reference to realistic numbers. For example, physical modeling can simulate a violin with strings of glass and extending to several miles in length. So the critical concept being the musical instrument with its physical limitations, the software simulation in physical modeling now enables opening all the walls of realistic physical parameters. It is like a reconstruction of physical devices with fictitiuous parameters. A fascinating example of such a simulation has been implemented by Parry Cook in his singer synthesis software [25]. The software’s functional units, simulating a human singer’s physiology with throat, nose, and lips, is shown in Figure 21.14. This means that the creative action here is the opening of instrumental parameters by transferring the sound production to computer software, where the physical properties of the instrument are only used as data to calculate the output. This means that we are only interested in the sound output of the instrument, not its real physicality. This seems to be a huge extension of instrumental technology, but one should observe that physical modeling deals only with the instrument as such, not with the instrument as an interface between human gestures and sounding
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
185
Fig. 21.14. Parry Cook’s singer synthesis software.
output. In other words, the entire virtuosity of musicians on their instruments must be reconsidered when building interfaces capable of letting humans play such physically modeled sound generators. This means that creativity can, on the one hand, expand one concept—in this case, that of a musical instrument as a sound generator—but on the other hand also create new problems for the management of such expanded concepts when relating to other concepts of the given context—here the musician’s interaction with these new instrumental devices. To put it simply: It is not sufficient to create a new fancy instrument by physical modeling, but you also have to consider how to play the instrument. Moreover, to preserve the information about your creation, you would have to develop a new appropriate notation (analogous to the traditional Western notation, for example) and then also an educational system that teaches musicians how to play such notated information.
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW 21.2.1 General Picture of Analog/Digital Sound Encoding The electromagnetic encoding of music is the trace of an incredibly rich history of creative acts. We want to follow this pathway and highlight the most important milestones.
186
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.15. The general scheme of electromagnetic encoding of music. It shows that this encoding technology inhabits a physical reality and mainly realizes a movement from the poietic original code given by the music’s sound waves to a neutral niveau level of communicative transfer, where the message is encoded in either analog or digital fashion.
The general scheme of such encoding is shown in Figure 21.15. The scheme shows that this encoding technology inhabits a physical reality and mainly realizes a movement from the poietic original code given by the music’s sound waves to a neutral niveau level of communicative transfer, where the message is encoded in either analog or digital fashion. “Analog” means that the original waveform is mapped onto a similar waveform imprinted on a media, and “digital” means that the original waveform is transformed into a sequence of numbers according to a more or less refined algorithm. The neutral niveau is in the expressive layer of the semiotic system; it has no meaning as such, but needs to be decoded in order to give us back the original musical sound content. Observe that “content” here means just the sounding wave, not the deeper symbolic or psychological sound signification. Technically speaking, we have the arrangement shown in Figure 21.16. The physical content is recorded by a set of microphones (short: mics), and sent to an analog mixer that merges the mics The mix is then piped to a analog or digital encoder, which then— after potentially mixing on the digital material—outputs its analog decoded wave to a second analog mixer for voltage output to a system of loudspeakers. Although the microphone and loudspeaker technology looks marginal in the music encoding process, it has been a major concern to obtain optimal input from or output to the acoustic level. Figure 21.17 shows the three major
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
187
Fig. 21.16. The physical content is recorded by a set of microphones (short: mics), and sent to an analog mixer that merges the mics. The mix is then piped to a analog or digital encoder, which then—after potentially mixing on the digital material— outputs its analog decoded wave to a second analog mixer for voltage output to a system of loudspeakers.
Fig. 21.17. Three major mic types: moving coil dynamic, ribbon, and condenser.
mic types: moving coil dynamic, ribbon, and condenser. While the technologies defining these devices are evident, their use in music recording studios or for concert amplification is subject to sophisticated discussions that also reveal personal tastes and ‘ideological’ positions concerning the characteristic quality of the sound. It is remarkable how much effort has been invested in creating
188
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
better loudspeaker systems or better mics and marketing such systems under the title of creative technologies. Figure 21.18 shows the typical anatomy of a loudspeaker device.
Fig. 21.18. Typical anatomy of a loudspeaker device.
The concept of a microphone and loudspeaker as technological surrogates for ears and instruments has a more creative implication for the technology of sound recording and reproduction, however. The critical concept here is the ear/mic. The wall here is the singular (like with Newton’s time, see section 19.1.2). Why should we have only one recording device, or two like in the human ear configuration? The answer (confirming the wall character) is that human ears are also just one (pair), so humans do not need more than a corresponding mic (pair) to record music. This paradigm of high fidelity is also used in audio label advertising (e.g. the excellent Cadence Jazz Records): “We guarantee the most faithful real music recordings.” But the wall can be softened by asking: Where do you listen when hearing a musical performance? Are you simulating a concert hall position, and where in such a hall? The question opens a variety of answers: One can sit in an ordinary seat, also creating a variable listening according to where the seat is located, and in which hall one wants to be seated. But the variety of answers is much larger in that it is also possible to listen to the music as a musician, really near to some instrumental configuration (within the string choir, for example, or next a drum, etc.). Which is the ‘real’ listening position? In studio technology,
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
189
this is solved by a heavy intermediate process involving the installation of a large number of mics across the orchestra, recording all these tracks and then mixing them while stepping to postproduction. The multiplicity of such artificial ears is even potentiated by positioning some twelve mics across the drum set, for example. Ideally one would wish to have mics everywhere in the orchestra’s space. Of course, this would presuppose a new mic technology that is capable of tracing an infinity of mic locations and merging them to a postproductive synthesis. But it is clear that this opening of the hearing concept redefines musical reality altogether: It is no longer evident what is the audio output. The variety of local hearing inputs enables a very creative reconstruction of the typical final stereo output. On the other hand, thinking of the concept of a loudspeaker as a surrogate of instrumental output also has a wall in that it is thought in analogy to the two ears as two sources, or four in quadro setups. But similar to the theoretically infinite multiplicity of mics, there is also the option of an infinity of loudspeakers distributed in any manifold within the hall or living room of audio reproduction. This infinity might be realized as a surface mic, i.e. a surface that vibrates in a locally variable way. A technology using an infinity of hearing positions could be realized in headphones whose output depends on its position in space and a bluetooth wireless input of sounds that had been recorded and/or edited to represent spatial positions in the orchestra’s recording space.
Fig. 21.19. The overall analog and digital encoding variants.
The overall analog and digital encoding variants are shown in Figure 21.19. For analog encoding, we have the options of a mechanical LP and an analog
190
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
magnetic tape. For the digital encoding, we have three options: (1) the optical technology of a CD, where the data is engraved in a glass material (see below for the details); (2) the magnetic technology realized by DAT (Digital Audio Tape) or Hard Drive technology; (3) the electric (semiconductor-based) technology with volatile (RAM, Random Access Memory), semi-volatile (memory sticks), and non-volatile (ROM, Read Only Memory) technology. 21.2.2 LP and Tape Technologies, Some History
Fig. 21.20. The classical analog encoding and its historical highlights.
Figure 21.20 shows the classical analog encoding and its historical highlights. To graphically represent sound on discs of paper, a machine using a ´ vibrating pen (without the idea of playing it back) was built by Edouard-L´ eon Scott de Martinville in 1857. While this phonoautograph was intended solely to visualize sound, it was recently realized that this depiction could be digitally analyzed and reconstructed as an audible recording. An early such phonautogram, made in 1860 and now the earliest known audio recording, has been reproduced using computer technology. In 1877, Thomas Edison developed the phonograph, which was capable of both recording and reproducing the recorded sound. There is no evidence
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
191
that Edison’s phonograph was based on Scott de Martinville’s phonautograph. Edison originally recorded on wax-coated tape while Scott de Martinville used soot coated glass. The version Edison patented at the end of 1877 used tinfoil cylinders as the recording medium. Edison also sketched (but did not patent) recording devices using tape and disc recording medium. This phonograph cylinder dominated the recorded sound market beginning in the 1880s. Lateral-cut disc records were invented by Emile Berliner in 1888 and were used exclusively in toys until 1894, when Berliner began marketing disc records under the Berliner Grammophone label. Berliner’s records had poor sound quality; however, work by Eldridge R. Johnson improved the fidelity to a point where they were as good as cylinders. Johnson’s and Berliner’s companies merged to form the Victor Talking Machine Company, whose products would come to dominate the market for many years. In an attempt to head off the disc advantage, Edison introduced the Amberol cylinder in 1909, with a maximum playing time of 4 minutes (at 160 rpm) to be in turn superseded by the Blue Amberol Record whose playing surface was made of celluloid, an early plastic that was far less fragile than the earlier wax (in fact, it would have been more or less indestructible had it not been for the plaster of Paris core). By November 1918, the patents for the manufacture of lateral-cut disc records expired, opening the field for countless companies to produce them, causing disc records to overtake cylinders in popularity. Edison ceased production of cylinders in 1929. Disc records would dominate the market until they were supplanted by the compact disc, starting from the early 1980s. 21.2.3 The Digital Approach, Sampling Philips and Sony have used digital encoding since 1982 upon recommendation by Herbert von Karajan. It is remarkable that his acceptance of the CD quality (characterized by a 20 kHz upper frequency limit in the Fourier spectrum) was decisive for these companies, although Karajan’s age (around 50 then) was not ideal as a reference for faithful sound perception. The hardware display of a CD is shown in Figure 21.21. The CD’s laser reads the land and pit levels engraved upon the polycarbonate carrier as bit sequence of zeros and ones. The transformation from the analog soundwave to the digital representation on the CD is explained in Figure 21.22. The wave is quantized in two ways: First, the sound’s amplitude is quantized by 16 Bits1 . This means that we are given 216 = 65, 536 values (0, 1, 2, . . . 65, 535) defined by the binary integer representation b15 215 + b14 214 + . . . b1 21 + b0 20 , bi = 0, 1. Second, the (quantized) values of the wave are only taken every 1/44, 100th of a second, i.e. the sample rate is 44, 100 samples per second. In total, this gives 635 MByte, 1 Byte = 8 Bit CD capacity for one hour stereo recording. We shall see in the next subsection that this allows for partials up to frequency 44, 100/2 = 22.05 kHz. The human ear is known to perceive up to 20 kHz. 1
A one-Bit quantization would allow for just two values, 0 or 1.
192
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.21. The hardware display of a CD. The CD’s laser reads the land and pit levels engrained upon the polycarbonate carrier as a bit sequence of zeros and ones.
Karajan, in his fifties, could very probably not hear more than 15 kHz, so for him the quality of the CD was perfect. A young human however would have asked for higher resolution. In recent technology, a sample rate of 96 kHz with amplitude quantization of 24 Bit is being envisaged. This looks like the endpoint of a long development of sound conservation and transfer, for which the 200 billion CDs sold by 2007 is a good argument. However, the creative argument comes from the critical concept: the container unit of music, the CD. What is a wall thereof? First, its material part, this disc, why should this be the container? And second, why should music be transferred using such a hardware container? Because the Internet has defined the global reality of information transfer since the early 1990s, the answer to the above questions has become straightforward: Of course music data transfer can be accomplished via Internet. This transfer would use the electromagnetic digital technology that we display in Figure 21.23. And then the unit of transfer would no longer be a collection, such as those 635 MByte containing a small number of musical compositions. This answer is, however, only theoretically valid because those 635 MByte are far too much to be transferred in reasonable time by the present Internet performance. We shall see in the following sections that the solution of this performance problem has been an odyssey from rejection of patents and disinterest of industry to the celebrated integration of new ideas in the now commonly known MP3 format.
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
193
Fig. 21.22. The transformation from the analog soundwave to the digital representation on the CD.
21.2.4 Finite Fourier Analysis So let us first recall the Fourier formula for a sound function w(t) of frequency f and look at its structure: An sin(2π.nf t + P hn ). w(t) = A0 + n≥1
It has two drawbacks: 1. In real life, a (non-zero) function is never strictly periodic. In particular, it cannot last forever, and we cannot know it except for a finite time interval. 2. It is not possible to recognize the function’s value at every time; this would be an infinite task. In real life we deal with functions that have a finite interval of definition, and we can measure only values for a finite number of times. This is, of course, not what must be offered to a Fourier setup. The solution of this situation is as follows. We are given a function w(t) that is only defined in a finite interval of length P . No periodicity is presupposed for this function—it could be a short sound recording of 0.5 seconds (see Figure 21.24). To turn this data into a Fourier situation, we have to create a periodic function from w(t). This is done by continuing the function by copying it infinitely to intervals of same length P to the left and to the right of the original interval such that the period of
194
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.23. Transfer modes of analogue sound using the electromagnetic digital technology.
Fig. 21.24. To turn general sound data into a Fourier situation, we have to create a periodic function. This is done by copying the function infinitely to the left and to the right of the original interval such that the period of this continuation is P by definition.
this continuation is P by definition. This creative solution starts by opening the wall of nonperiodicity of the given function. It is not periodic, yes, but we are not interested in anything else but the representation of this function in its original domain of definition. So whatever we have outside does not matter. And the solution is to take the continuation of the function by shifted copies,
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
195
so the result is periodic and coincides with the given function in its original domain. The second problem is dealt with by measuring only finitely many values of w(t) in the original interval (see Figure 21.25). It is related to a technically reasonable procedure where the function values are measured in regular time periods ∆. This ∆ is called the sample period. The frequency 1/∆ is called the sample frequency. The total sample period P is a multiple of the sample period, P = N ∆ = 2n∆, which means that we assume the multiplicity of the sampling action is even, N = 2n. This will be important later in section 21.2.5, when we discuss Fast Fourier calculation.
Fig. 21.25. Measuring only finitely many values of w(t) in the original interval.
So the situation is this: We have fabricated a periodic function with frequency f = 1/P , and we have to find a Fourier representation that coincides with all the values measured in the 2n sample times. This is a mathematical problem relating to a Fourier formula that satisfies the preceding conditions. To solve this problem, we use the goniometric equation a. cos(x) + b. sin(x) = A. sin(x + arccos(b/A)), where A = a2 + b2 . Using this equation in the Fourier equation for the overtone expression Am sin(2.πmf t + P hm ), we can write the Fourier equation at time t = r∆: w(r∆) = a0 + am cos(2π.mf.r∆) + bm sin(2π.mf.r∆) + m=1,2,3,...n−1
bn sin(2π.nf.r∆). The 2n equations for r = −n, . . . n − 1 are linear in the 2n unknown coefficients a0 , am , bm , bn . It can be shown, using the so-called orthogonality relations
196
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
of sinusoidal functions [80, section 38.8], that these equations have exactly one solution. This mean that we can find exactly one Fourier formula that solves these conditions. The formula has its maximal overtone at frequency nf = N f /2 = 1/(2∆), which is half the sampling frequency. This result is known as: Theorem 1 (Nyquist’s Sampling Theorem) Given a wave w(t) defined in a period P of time as above, if we measure its values every ∆ sample period, dividing the period P into N = 2n intervals, then there is exactly one set of coefficients a0 , am , bm , bn in the above finite Fourier expression for all sample times r∆, r = −n, . . . n − 1. The maximal overtone of this expression has index n = N/2, half the sample index N . Its frequency is half the sample frequency nf = N f /2 = 1/(2∆); it is called the Nyquist frequency. This result applies to the CD sampling at 44.1 kHz. The Nyquist frequency is half of it, 22.050 kHz, as already announced above. Let us make another simple example: Suppose we have a wave of period P = 20 seconds and a sample frequency of 80 Hz. This means that ∆ = 1/80 seconds and N = 80 × 20 = 1, 600. The fundamental frequency is f = 1/P = 0.05 Hz. How many overtones do we have in the finite Fourier analysis? We start with the fundamental at f , and go to the overtone with index 1, 600/2 = 800, having frequency 800 × 0.05 = 40 Hz. The Nyquist theorem is the connection between general mathematical Fourier theory using infinite sums and infinite information about the waves, and the practical theory that is based upon finite information about the limited extension of the not-periodic wave function in time and the finite number of practically possible samples of this function. This finite Fourier theory does solve the conflict addressed in the beginning of this section. But it does not solve the question about the time needed to calculate the Fourier coefficients if the sample number N is large. For example, if we are given the CD sampling rate of 44, 100 per second, and if we have a period of P = 10 minutes, we get 44, 100 × 600 = 2.6460 × 106 equations, and the calculation of its solution involves an order of the square 7.001316 × 1012 of arithmetical operations. This is beyond reasonable calculation power. In the next section, we shall solve this major problem. 21.2.5 Fast Fourier Analysis (FFT) Fast Fourier Transform (FFT) is an algorithm that enables faster calculation of Fourier coefficients in the finite Fourier theory described above. This approach however is not easily accessible by the classical description of Fourier’s formula using sinusoidal functions. We have to prepend a short discussion of using complex numbers to restate the formula. Then we shall be able to understand the beauty of FFT.
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
197
21.2.5.1 Fourier via Complex Numbers
Fig. 21.26. The complex representation of sinusoidal functions.
In the discussion of the Nyquist theorem, we have restated the Fourier repesentation of the periodic wave function w(t) in the shape w(t) = a0 + a1 cos(2π.f t) + b1 sin(2π.f t) + a2 cos(2π.2f t) + b2 sin(2π.2f t) + . . . This representation must be replaced by a much more elegant representation involving complex numbers. Recall that a complex number is just a vector 2 x = a + i.b √ in the plane R of real numbers (with coordinates a, b ∈ R), where i = −1, and besides the usual coordinate-wise addition, we have a multiplication defined by (a + i.b) · (u + i.v) = (au − bv) + i(av + bu), using i2 = −1. This enables a complex representation of sinusoidal functions as shown in Figure 21.26. The idea is to represent the sinusoidal values as the two coordinates of an arrow of length one rotating around the origin, and where time is parametrized b the angle of the arrow with the x axis. The deeper advantage of this reduction of sinusoidal functions to rotating arrows is that this arrow’s head satisfies Leonhard Euler’s famous equation cos(x) + i. sin(x) = ei.x n where ez = n≥0 zn! is the exponential function. The advantage of this exponential representation is that the exponential function has a beautiful property: namely, it transforms addition of arguments into the product of values: ez+w = ez · ew . This is the basis of all apparently complicated formulas for sinusoidal functions. The creative idea behind this Eulerian result is to (1)
198
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
connect cos(x) to sin(x) in the complex vector, and (2) to use the complex arithmetic for the combination of such complex vectors. The relationship between sinusoidal functions and the exponential is this: cos(x) = (eix + e−ix )/2 sin(x) = (eix − e−ix )/2i. This is used to restate the Fourier formula in terms of exponential expressions as follows: w(t) = cn ei2π.nf t n=0,±1,±2,±3,...
with the new coefficients cn relating to the old ones by a0 = c 0 , and for n > 0, an = cn + c−n bn = i(cn − c−n ). With this data, the above finite Fourier equation for w(r∆) looks as follows: In order to keep ideas transparent, we only look at the special case of a sound sample of period P = 1 from t = 0 to t = 1 , such that ∆ = 1/N and r∆ = r/N for r = 0, 1, . . . N − 1. We may then write cm ei2π.mr/N . wr = w(r∆) = w(r/N ) = m=0,1,2,3,...N −1
Why are the negative indices gone here? They are not, but they are hidden in the equation ei2π.mr/N .ei2π.m(N −r)/N = ei2π.mr/N +i2π.m(N −r)/N = e0 = 1, which means ei2π.m(N −r)/N = ei2π.(−m)r/N , where −m is a negative index! Also, cN −m is the complex conjugate to cm since am , bm are all real numbers. Therefore we have a total of N/2 independent complex coefficients, i.e. N real coefficients as required from the original formula. This enables us to represent the sample sequence with the vector w = (w0 , w1 , . . . wN −1 ) ∈ CN in the N -dimensional complex vector space CN . In this space, we have a canonical scalar product of such vectors u, v (similar to the high school formula) u, v =
N −1 1 ur v r . N r=0
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
199
We have exponential functions em = (em (r) = ei2π.mr/N )r=0,1,2,...N −1 and their scalar product is em , em = 1, em , eq = 0, m = q, which means that they define an orthonormal basis of CN (see Figure 21.27). These relationships are the orthogonality relations mentioned above. These functions replace the sinusoidal functions in the complex representation. Every sound sample vector w = (w0 , w1 , . . . wN −1 ) can be written as a unique linear combination (see Figure 21.27) cm em , w= m=0,1,2,3,...N −1
and the coefficients cm are determined by the formula cm = w, em =
1 N
wr e−i2π.mr/N .
r=0,1,2,3,...N −1
This writing in the complex vector space, using the exponential basis is the
Fig. 21.27. An orthonormal basis of CN .
Fourier theorem for such finite sums. It is much more elegant than the original one using sinusoidal waves, and the calculation of the Fourier coefficients (essentially the amplitude and phase spectra) is very easy. We hope that the reader can appreciate this beautiful simplification of the theory through the step to the complex numbers.
200
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.28. The FFT trick: To split the vector w = (w0 , w1 , . . . w2N −1 ) ∈ C2N into its even and odd parts w+ , w− .
21.2.5.2 The FFT Algorithm The FFT algorithm was invented to calculate the Fourier coefficients cm faster than in the quadratic growth algorithm that is given by the solution of the above orthogonality relations. The FFT was discovered by James W. Cooley (IBM T.J. Watson Research Center) and John W. Tuckey (Princeton University and AT&T Bell labs) and published in 1965 in a five-page (!) paper, “An Algorithm for the Machine Calculation of Complex Series” [27]. It has become one of the most cited papers of all times. It is remarkable that the algorithm was already discovered by the great German mathematician Carl Friedrich Gauss in 1805 for astronomical calculation, but it was not recognized because he wrote the paper in Latin. (This might be amusing, but it also teaches us to share creations in languages that are communicative. It is interesting that many great creators do not care about this and even avoid any straightforward communication of their findings. The psychology of such hidden creativity has not been written to this date.) Compared to the quadratic growth N 2 defined by the orthogonality relations, this FFT algorithm grows with N. log(N ). The idea is very simple but ingenious. The trick consists of taking the sample vector w = (w0 , w1 , . . . w2N −1 ) ∈ C2N and splitting it into its even and odd parts w+ , w− as shown in Figure 21.28. Supposing that we have calculated + + + − − − − = (c− the coefficient vectors c+ = (c+ 0 , c1 , c2 , . . . cN −1 ), c 0 , c1 , c2 , . . . cN −1 ) with a growth F ourier(N ), we can calculate the coefficient vector c of w using r − the formula cr = (c+ r + e(N ) .cr )/2. This latter formula permits a calculation F ourier(2N ) ≤ 3 × 2N + 2N + 2.F ourier(N ) = 2.F ourier(N ) + 8N . This is a recursive formula that is used to show that the growth can be set to N. log(N ). The detailed mathematics here is not so important; the question is rather how this problem could be solved in such a simple way. What was the critical concept, what was the wall? The critical concept is clearly the formula for the calculation of the coefficients cm . Nothing suggests that this formula consists of sub-information that can be calculated separately and yield the desired values. Once we are told that such a procedure is possible, the solution is not difficult. The solution is just the splitting of the wave w into its even and odd parts.
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
201
Then, once the even and odd coefficients have been calculated, the connecting r − formula cr = (c+ r + e(N ) .cr )/2 yields immediately the required result. So the creative part of this work is not the mathematics, but the unbelievable fact that everything can be solved recursively from even and odd parts. 21.2.6 Compression In order to appreciate the quality of MP3 compression, we have to briefly discuss the concept of compression in computer file formats for digitized audio data. Such formats contain not only the audio-related data, but additional technical information about the encoding method of the raw data, and data concerning the composer and other poietic information. This additional information can be complex according to the actual method. We shall see for MP3 that the encoded data stream is in itself a virtuosic achievement invented to enable playing a piece starting at any time moment of the piece2 . The additional data strongly depend on compression methods invented to reduce the saved data with respect to the original audio data. By definition, compression for a determined file format is the ratio of two quantities: original data/file data. For example, if the original data is a 10-minute CD and the file needs to be 10 MB, what is the compression? Answer: 44.1 × 103 Hz × 16 Bit × 2 channels × 10 min × 60 sec/107 × 8 Bit ≈ 10.58. There are two types of compression: •
Lossless compression. This means that the original data can be completely reconstructed from the compressed ones. • Lossy compression. This means that the original data cannot be completely reconstructed from the compressed ones. Here are two lossless compression methods also used in MP3: •
RLE = Run Length Encoding. It consists of replacing a Bit sequence (such as black and white pixels in a black-white TV screen) with the sequence of numbers of uninterrupted occurrences of a determined Bit. • Huffman. This method is described in Figure 21.29. We start with a number of values, here six (step A), and list their frequencies. Label the two least frequent values 0,1 (step B), then add the frequencies of the two least frequent values and define a new value * (step C). Start over with the new values and frequencies, append the 0.1 to 12:* at the end of the algorithm (step D). And here are two examples of lossy compression: • 2
Analog to Digital Conversion (ADC). From analog to CD with 44,100 Hz and 16 Bit amplitude digitization. This has an infinite rate. Remember that Fourier’s coefficient calculation needs all time moments!
202
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.29. An example of Huffman compression.
•
Quantization. In the 16-Bit representation of amplitude, the five last Bits are neglected. So, for example, 1011 1100 0101 1110 is transformed to 1011 1100 0100 0000 and then shortened to the 11 relevant Bits left, 1011 1100 010.
21.2.7 MP3, MP4, AIFF Figure 21.30 shows the best-known digital audio file formats, together with their compression types. Let us discuss MP3, the most sucessful format. MPEG (Moving Pictures Experts Group) is the code name for the standardization group ISO/IEC JTC1/SC29/WG11 (Int. Organization for Standardization/International Electrotechnical Commission). It was created in 1988 to generate generic standards for encoding digital video and audio data. MPEG-1 is the result of the first work phase of the group and has been established in 1992 as standard ISO/IEC IS 11172. It contains Layer-1, Layer-2, and Layer-3, which means three operation modes with increasing complexity. By MP3 one denotes Layer-3 of MPEG-1. MPEG-2 Advanced Audio Coding (AAC) is the result of the second work phase. In enhances Layer-3 in many details. We are not going to discuss this phase here. The development of these compressed audio formats goes back to research by Dieter Seitzer since 1960, who at that time worked at IBM, and his student Karlheinz Brandenburg, who is above all responsible for the psychoacoustical compression methods. It is remarkable that Seitzer’s patent was rejected in 1977; however it was awarded in 1983 but was then suspended because of lack of interest from the industry! MP3 is above all based on research and development
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
203
Fig. 21.30. The best known digital audio file formats, together with their compression types.
by Brandenburg at the Fraunhofer Institut f¨ ur Integrierte Schaltungen (IIS) in Erlangen. It is an open standard, but it is protected by many patents (more than 13 US patents, and more than 16 German patents). We shall discuss legal aspects at the end of this topic. MP3 includes these options: •
Mono and stereo, in particular joint stereo encoding for efficient combined encoding of both stereo channels. • Sampling frequencies include 32 kHz, 44.1 kHz, 48 kHz; for MPEG-2 also 16 kHz, 22.5 kHz, 24 kHz; and for MPEG-2.5 (Fraunhofer-internal extension) also 8 kHz, 11.5 kHz, and 12 kHz. • The compression’s bitrate (= the Bits traversing the audio file per second) goes from 32 kBits/sec (MPEG-1) or 8 kBits/sec (MPEG-2) up to 320 kBits/sec. For MP3 the bitrate can even vary from frame to frame (a frame is the unit package in MP3, we come back to it later) and, together with the so-called bit-reservoir technology, allows a variable as well as constant bitrate.
Besides compression MP3 has the advantage of being platform-independent. This is also a strong reason for its popularity. Let us now look at the MP3 encoder chain (the decoder works symmetrically, we don’t discuss it for this reason). Figure 21.31 shows the original overall flowchart of audio information. 1. From the left, the digital datastream defines
204
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.31. The MP3 encoder chain with its core Perceptual-Audio-Coding device.
the system’s input; the quantity is given by 768 kBit/sec ≈ 48, 000×16 Bit/sec. In the region 2, a FFT processing of the digital signal is applied, yielding a number of Fourier coefficient banks (filter banks—we discuss below what is a filter, but essentially it just selects a range of Fourier coefficients). We cut the spectrum 0 − 20 kHz into 32 subbands of 625 Hz each (32 × 625 = 20, 000) for 1/40 sec. windows. We then use MDCT (Modified Discrete Cosine Transformation, a variant of FFT) to split each 625 Hz band into 18 subbands with variable widths, according to psychoacoustical criteria. We then get 576 = 18 × 32 “lines.” Region 3 is the heart of the MP3 compression, covering 60 percent of the compression. It operates by elimination of physiologically superfluous information following the so-called Perceptual-Audio-Coding Model (PAC). PAC has three components: PAC 1—hearing thresholds; PAC 2—auditory masking; PAC 3—temporary masking. PAC 1, hearing thresholds, uses the fact that there is a loudness threshold under which the human ear does not hear sounds. The curve is shown in Figure 21.32. Therefore we may eliminate Fourier components (overtones) with amplitudes below these thresholds. PAC 2, auditory masking, uses the fact that for a frequency component there is a curve under which no other component can be heard. Figure 21.33 shows the situation for 2, 4, and 8 kHz components. PAC 3, temporary masking, uses the fact that for every sinusoidal frequency component of frequency f and loudness l, another subsequent component cannot be heard below the given curve of loudness in time, because the
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
205
Fig. 21.32. Hearing thresholds: One uses the fact that there is a loudness threshold under which the human ear does not hear sounds.
ear needs some time to “recover” from that first component’s perception. This is even true before (!) the given one, because the perception needs to be built up. Figure 21.34 shows the curve. In point 4 and 5 of the flowchart, we have the lossy quantization and lossless Huffman compressions discussed above—they make up the remaining 40 percent of compression. The final output is shown in region 6, where the MP3 frames are also built. We discuss them now. To begin with, the MP3 file is headed by a MP3 file identifier, the ID3 tag. It has 128 Bytes and its information is shown in Figure 21.35. After this header, a number of frames is added. Here is the concept: A frame is an autonomous information package. This means that all encoding data is provided within every frame to enable playing a file from any given time onset. A frame’s duration is 1/38.28125 ≈ 1/40 sec. This enables virtually continuous playing for humans. Each frame has these parts: • •
a 32-Bit header indicating the layer number (1-3), the bitrate, and the sample frequency; the Cycle Redundancy Check (CRC) with 16 Bits for error detection (without correction option) but frame repetition until correct frame appears;
206
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.33. Auditory masking uses the fact that for a frequency component, there is a curve under which no other component can be heard.
Fig. 21.34. Temporary masking uses the fact that for every sinusoidal frequency component of frequency f and loudness l, another subsequent component cannot be heard below the given curve of loudness in time, because the ear needs some time to “recover” from that first component’s perception.
• •
12 Bits for additional information for Huffman trees and quatization info; a main data sample block of 3,344 Bits for Huffman-encoded data.
Each frame has a 32-Bit header containing the information shown in Figure 21.36. The frame structure is given as shown in Figure 21.37. Each frame has a header and a reservoir of 3,344 Bits. However, the reservoir technique allows information to be placed in reservoirs that are not filled up yet. So data for block n might be saved in block n + 1. This is called the reservoir technique.
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
207
Fig. 21.35. The MP3 file identifier, the ID3 tag, has 128 Bytes.
Fig. 21.36. Each frame has a 32-Bit header containing the information shown here.
There are two important formulas regarding frame capacities for MP3. The fixed data is this: 1. number of frames/sec = 38.28125 2. maximal audio data capacity per frame = 3,344 Bit/frame 3. number of frequency bands = 32 The first formula is this: The maximal bitrate 3,344 Bit/frame × 38.28125 frame/sec = 128 kBit/sec guarantees CD quality. And the second one is this: (44,100 time-sample/sec)/(38.28125 frame/sec) = 1,152 frequency-samples/frame guarantees CD quality. And this yields 1,152/32 = 36 frequency-samples/band. Observe: 625 Hz/band/38.28125 Hz = 16.3265 frequency-samples/band. We have overlapping info, but this is OK to minimize measurement errors.
208
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.37. The MP3 frame structure.
Some performance values are shown in Figure 21.38. Let us add some remarks regarding the joint stereo encoding: MP3 implements the Joint Stereo Coding compression method, which is based on these two principles: •
Mid/Side Stereo Coding (MSSC), where instead of taking the left and right channels (L, R), we use the equivalent data (L + R, L − R)—since L and R are usually strongly corrupted, the difference is quite ‘tame’. • Intensity Stereo Coding (ISC), where the sum L + R and the direction of the signal are encoded (replacing the L − R information). This coding method also uses the fact that the human ear is weak in localizing deep frequencies. Since the direction is detected by phase differences that are difficult to retrieve for deep frequencies, they are encoded mono! Let us end the discussion with some commercial information: The license rights of Fraunhofer IIS are represented by the French company Technicolor SA, formerly Thomson Multimedia. Here are the figures: • • •
0.50 USD per decoder 5.- USD per encoder 15,000.- USD annual lump sum
This means that an enterprise that sells 25,000 copies annually of the encoder software, pays 25,000 × 5.- + 15,000.- = 140,000.- for the first year and then 15,000.- in annual fees for every successive year.
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
209
Fig. 21.38. Some MP3 performance values.
21.2.8 Filters and EQ In our discussion of finite Fourier methods, we had encountered that clever trick that transforms a non-periodic function in a time interval of length P (the period) into a periodic function by simply juxtaposing the shifted function to the left and right of the original function. This might be clever if we have a finite time interval of this function. But what happens to the function if it is extended to infinity and is not periodic? Then that method fails.
Fig. 21.39. Letting a finite frequency go to zero without losing the formal power of the original theory.
Mathematicians have however been able to solve this problem by a very adventurous idea: Why do we have to suppose a finite period for our theory? Is Fourier only feasible for finite periods? In other words, why couldn’t we try to extend the theory to infinite periods? This is a typical situation of a mathematical problem of creativity. The critical concept is the Fourier sum given from a P -periodic function w(t). The wall is the index of the partials, which is a discrete quantity. The problem here is to ask for a Fourier formula whose overtones are not only reasonable for finite, but also for infinite periods. This means that we are looking for a Fourier formula for frequency f → 0. This is a very mathematical situation! It is about reshaping a given expression or concept until its shape is such that a seemingly indispensable limitation is absorbed in a more general setup.
210
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
In our context we are fighting against the problem of letting a finite frequency go to zero without losing the formal power of the original theory (see Figure 21.39).
Fig. 21.40. The correspondence between the product of frequency functions and the convolution of their corresponding time functions.
The solution of this limit problem, the transition for a finite frequency to the vanishing frequency, works because the limit of a sum is, if mathematically correctly worked out, the integral, and the finite frequency converges in an infinitesimal frequency. Evidently, under this transformation, there will no longer be a discrete multiplicity of a fundamental frequency, but an entire continuous variety of frequencies that describe the Fourier formula. And here is the result. We use also the usual symbol f (t) for the function (instead of w(t)), and ν for the frequency (instead of f ): ∞ 1 f (t)e−iνt dt. F(f )(ν) = √ 2π −∞ This function F(ν) of frequency ν is called the Fourier transform of f . It is a function of frequency instead of time. Figure 21.40 gives an overview of the power of this new Fourier transform formula.
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
211
Fig. 21.41. A filter is a function that alters an audio signal on the basis of its Fourier transform.
Here are the properties: F defines a linear isomorphism from the space of all time functions (right) (with some technical properties that are not interesting in our context) onto the space of all frequency functions (left). The inverse of F is denoted by F ∗ . For example, the sinusoidal function sin(ωt) is transformed into the function that is 0 except at frequency ν = ω, where it is 1. So the sum of sinodial functions is transformed into a sum of such spike functions, which symbolize the Fourier overtones with their amplitudes. Furthermore, by the inverse F ∗ , the pointwise product F · G of two frequency functions F,G ((F · G)(ν) = F (ν) · G(ν)) is transformed into the convolution (f ∗ g)(t) = ±∞ f (x)g(t − x)dx.
Fig. 21.42. The filtering process in the frequency domain for a time function f (t).
This means that we can use pointwise products in the frequency domain to cut functions. This is precisely the fact we need to understand filters! A filter
212
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
is a function that alters an audio signal on the basis of its Fourier transform (see Figure 21.41). The filtering process for a time function f (t) consists first in a Fourier transform F = F(f ) of f , and then we are given a filter function G(ν) in the frequency domain. It is shaped in such a way as to eliminate a number of frequencies from F(f ) by pointwise multiplication, yielding F · G, and then to transform the result F · G back to the time domain, yielding fG = F ∗ (F · G) = f ∗ F ∗ (G) (see also Figure 21.42).
Fig. 21.43. Frequent filter types.
In audio technology there are a number of special filters that are given standard names: low pass, high pass, low shelf, high shelf, band pass, notch. Their filter function is shown in Figure 21.43. The meaning of “low pass” is that only low frequencies, below a determined cutoff frequency, can “pass” higher frequencies are cut off. A low shelf filter passes all frequencies above a cutoff frequency, but increases or reduces frequencies below the cutoff frequency by a determined quantity. Etc. In audio technology, the representation and management of filters is realized in two ways: as a graphical EQ and as a parametric EQ, EQ stands for “equalization” and just means filtering using complex filter functions. Figure 21.44 shows these two types in commercial software. Let us conclude this filter topic with a practical remark. Filters are not only used as abstract devices, but also occur in very practical contexts. Two
21.2 Electromagnetic Encoding of Music: Audio HW and SW
213
Fig. 21.44. Two types of equalizers, graphic and parametric, in commercial software
simple examples are walls and electrical circuits (see Figure 21.45). If a sound is produced in a room, it propagates to the room’s walls. There, it is reflected but also travels through the walls. The sound that arrives in the rooms adjacent to the room where the sound is produced is (hopefully) very different from the original one. The walls usually act as low pass filters. This means that the sound in the adjacent room(s) contains a certain amount of only low frequencies. This is made clear when we think of the bass sound in a commercial music sound. In the adjacent rooms, you will (have to) hear the bass, an effect that can be very disturbing at times. The second example, a special electrical circuit shown in the lower part of Figure 21.45, is capable of realizing the low pass filter in an electrical setup. It takes the input as a voltage Vin and “filters” it by a resistance R and a capacity C. The capacity induces a low pass filter in that it only transmits high frequencies, and therefore the low frequencies pass at Vout . The cutoff frequency is 1/2πRC. It should be remarked that the use of electrical circuits to simulate acoustical configurations is a powerful standard method in acoustics, especially acoustics of musical instruments. It serves as a methodology of representation in acoustics, but also as a means for the construction of acoustical effects on the level of electrical sound hardware technology.
214
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.45. A special electrical circuit shown in the lower part of the figure is capable of realizing the low pass filter in an electrical setup.
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators It is not true that musical objects are just acoustical and that anything that is used to notate music refers to these acoustical objects. This misunderstanding was virulent in the middle of the twentieth century when the electronic musicians discovered the precise structure of acoustical sounds, above all in the German school centered around the Studio f¨ ur elektronische Musik where Herbert Eimert tried to downsize all musical notation to the acoustical one, arguing that its precision would make all other notations superfluous. Thinking in symbols that are not just short writings for acoustical data has a long tradition in musical thought. The difference between symbols and acoustics is described by performance transformations. Scores are symbolic data; they are not acoustical. For example, a quarter note can have any physical duration, depending on the tempo chosen for that performance. In John Cage’s famous composition “ASLSP” (as slow as possible) [21], the total duration is 639 years, so the physical duration of notes in a score is totally relative. Notes live in a symbolic space, which is independent of the physical performative realization. In the following sections, we shall discuss a number of relevant symbolic notations: Western notation and the performance problem, then the main technological format, MIDI (Musical Instrument Digital Interface), and denotators, our own universal format implemented in the RUBATO software [74]. 21.3.1 Western Notation and Performance We do not have to recapitulate the history or the elementary properties of Western notation, but we should observe some of its symbolic prerequisites. To
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators
215
begin with, the staff system allowing for positioning note heads on or between the five lines (and lower or higher ledger lines) is encoding the diatonic scale from C and the third distances (between lines and line interspaces). This diatonic scale can be used to define alterations several semitones downward by ♭s, or upward by ♯s. It is however not clear from this notation what is the basic tuning of such pitch information. The diatonic scale as well as the alterations can relate to 12-tempered, just, or any other tuning. Also, the alteration is not simply an indication of the resulting lowered of heightened pitch, but also of the movement (vector) from the original pitch to the altered one. Relating to the time dimension, the notation of onset and duration is somewhat ambiguous because the onset is only fixed by the bar lines and, more relatively, for notes pertaining to chords. The other onsets must be determined from pauses and relative positions. While onset and duration are independent parameters, they are symbolic, and thus their physical values are quite difficult to be determined. One information in this regard is the tempo, which encodes the inverse derivative of physical time as a function of symbolic time, see [89, chapter 6] for details. However the tempo only encodes the onset of the beginning of a note, not its end, the offset. This can be encoded using the formula offset = onset + duration. But this is only valid if there is no articulation to be performed, articulation is a thoroughly symbolic information that has to interpreted by the performer in order to obtain a physical representation—or if the tempo curve is well defined between the onset and the offset in the score. Other symbolic time information might be ambiguous, such as the fermata. Its tempo-related information is not well defined; it is a symbolic sign much as the pitch position of notes is. If we look at dynamical information, absolute and relative, then we have the same situation, but even more dramatic since there is little agreement about what an mf should mean in terms of dB. Also are these symbols not precise in the sense that they designate one determined physical value as pitch would be. Dynamical signs are more like intervals of dynamics, and even overlapping ones, as there are situations where some parts in mf could have the same loudness as parts in f. All these score symbols are parts of a symbolic language where sound parameters are expressing more or less huge abstractions from physical reality. The music theory dealing with the relationships between these symbols and their physical (instrumental) realization is called performance theory and has been an intense research topic in traditional investigations as well as in contemporary research involving quantitative methods and specifically computer-aided models, see [89] for a recent documentation. The creative aspect of this symbolism is a very sophisticated one, and it has evolved in the course of the historical development of notation. What is the general problem leading to the development of such a notational sign system? Writing score symbols has never meant to represent all of the music; it was always understood that musical notation is an abstraction. So the problem was to find symbols of abstraction from the sounding reality of music. It is interesting that the Western culture of music has converged to the concept of
216
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
a composition by means of its trace in notated form. A composition is written, but it is not the entire music. Notation does not pretend to represent the sounding music but only certain aspects that either have a theoretical relevance or are meant to be reproducible. Therefore the creative wall inspection here for the critical concept of “notation” is about the parametric representation of the sound to be symbolized. The original solution of this problem was to encode the sound by gestural signs, the (cheironomic) neumes (see Figure 21.46).
Fig. 21.46. Neumes above text from Gregorian chant.
The function of a score to grasp the gestural rendition was then more and more reduced to the essence that could be reproduced and was thought to be essential in its memorization. The invention of neumes was a first-order creative act since these symbols could be deformed ad libitum (gestures are elastic!) until their substance was cast in the graphical shape needed to express the thought’s essence. The subtlety of neumatically driven abstraction, leading to the present notation, is that even after this huge geometrization, notes are still representing gestures. Following a modern insight by the author, and also confirmed by Theodor W. Adorno’s writings about performance [1], they are “frozen gestures.” Performers know that playing a composition from a score means to thaw these frozen gestures until they recover their original “temperature.” This means that whenever we deal with a Western score, we implicitely think about its gestural kernel. This is the creative solution of the notational problem: The notational symbols always represent compact gestures. Although they look like symbols, they can and must be opened to show their gestural essence in a successful performance. In the course of the history of notation in musical composition, the successive enrichment of notation is a known developmental path. Viewed superficially, it reflects a successive integration of performative commands into symbolic representation. This surface, however, is only functional for the performer, because in reality, it drives toward the completion of the gestural essence of notation, i.e. notation is always a vector toward performance by gestures— nothing more, nothing less. This also means that the direction of this vector
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators
217
shapes what is not written, namely the performative action, which we will identify with improvisation in chapter 22—namely all that is not preconceived (and fixed in notation) when sounding music is played. Summarizing, Western notation is not symbolism for its own sake, but a wrapping and compactification of performative gestures. However, understood as a surface of forms, it can be taken as a playground for composers, who manipulate the notational symbols as if they were without performative substance. This is definitely a creative usage because the performative substance can also act as a wall against formal manipulation. And it is also historically relevant that notation was first motivated by theory, not only as a mnemonic device. The symbolism for theory is essential for the compositional strategies when they are driven by knowledge bases. Obviously, we have a schism here between a theory that is built upon abstraction, such as parameter spaces and transformations dealt with in mathematically structured theories, and performative gestuality. Only in the last decade has it become possible to think about music theory as a coherent body of forms that treat abstraction and gestuality using the same basic formalism, see [84, 87]. 21.3.2 MIDI: What It Is About, Short History MIDI was officially introduced in January 1983 at the NAMM (National Association of Music Merchants) with its “MIDI 1.0 Specification”3 . It replaced the first sketches of a “Universal Synthesizer Interface” from 1981, which had been presented by Dave Smith and Chet Wood at the 70th Convention of the Audio Engineering Society. It is interesting that it was no longer the academic Audio Engineering Society but the thoroughly pragmatic community of music merchants who remained at the wheel. Also, no music-theoretical community was involved in this development, but of course they later complained about the MIDI’s deficiencies. Standardization of music formats had never been a topic of music theory before mathematical and computational music theory started developing universal standards, see [77, 124, 125, 126]. It is important—and we have stated this already in section 21.2.5.2 regarding the FFT algorithm already discovered by Gauss, but only communicated in Latin—that creative actions be communicative. It is not reasonable to hide creativity or to abstain from participation in highly active specialized communities. In the following sections we describe MIDI communication and the structure of MIDI messages. These messages are exchanged between any two: computers and/or synthesizers. The general functionality of MIDI is shown in Figure 21.47. Making music is a threefold communication: We usually have a (1) score whose frozen gestures are being “thawed” to (2) gestures, which act on an instrumental interface and thereby produce (3) sound events. The map from score to sound events is the objective of performance research. The gestural 3
The MIDI Specifications are accessible through the MIDI Manufacturer’s Association at http://www.midi.org.
218
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.47. Making music is a threefold communication: We usually have a (1) score whose frozen gestures are being “thawed” to (2) gestures, which act on an instrumental interface and thereby produce (3) sound events.
interaction with an instrument (process from the left top position to the right top position in Figure 21.47) is where MIDI has its main functionality. The movements of the human limbs (hands for keyboard players) are encoded and then communicated to a synthesizer that produces corresponding sound events. MIDI is therefore essentially a simplified code for human gestures interfacing with an instrument. A second functionality of MIDI is the transformation of instrumental gestures to a Standard MIDI File such that the performance can be replayed later. Standard MIDI files can also be transformed to (electronic files for) Western scores, and vice versa. But the essence of MIDI is that it encodes commands of gestural nature, although in a very simple setup as we shall see in the following discussion. It is nota coincidence that machines that understand the MIDI messages are called slaves in MIDI jargon. MIDI just tells an agent (mimicking a musician) to do simple gestures at a defined time and with a specific key and instrument. It was probably the most ingenious creation in the MIDI code to refrain from abstract symbols and to encode the simple gestural music-playing action instead. The music industry was not interested in higher symbols but in a communication code that would help musicians play electronic instruments
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators
219
when performing onstage or in a studio. Again, we see here the schism between codes and thoughts in theory vs. performance. 21.3.3 MIDI Networks: MIDI Devices, Ports, and Cables
Fig. 21.48. MIDI messages are Bit sequences, and the ports connecting MIDI devices have three types: IN, THRU, OUT.
MIDI communication is done via MIDI cables. They accept MIDI messages at a Out port and pipe them either to an In port, where a machine uses the message, or to a Thru port, which makes the message available to an Out port of the same machine for further messaging to other machines. The three port types are shown in the lower center of Figure 21.48. The MIDI messages are Bit sequences sent at a frequency of 31, 250 Bits per second (= Bauds) with a current of 5mA. Equivalently, this is 1/32 of a MegaBaud. This means that the transfer of one Bit needs 32 μsec. Originally, such transfer was strictly serial (one Bit after the other), but nowadays there is also parallel data transfer. MIDI is a semiotic, and the MIDI Specification connects the expressions given by Bit sequences to their symbolic signification (see Figure 21.49). But we should be precise here: The contents of the MIDI messages are not directly musical. They just decipher the Bit sequences and yield information that a synthesizer could understand, but it is the synthesizer’s semiotic (!) that must transform the message contents to musically meaningful information. We will clarify this when looking at the message structure.
220
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.49. The semiotic role of MIDI Specification.
21.3.4 MIDI Messages: Hierarchy and Anatomy A MIDI message consists of a sequence of words, each having a length of 10 Bits (see Figure 21.50). These words are delimited by a zero startbit and a zero stopbit, and it takes 320 μsec per word, which means roughly a third of a millisecond. MIDI messages are sequences of a few words with a fixed content anatomy. The first word is the status word, and the status character of the word is initiated by the first Bit: the statusbit one. The word encodes two
Fig. 21.50. The MIDI message anatomy.
information units: (1) what is being played, encoded in three Bits; and (2) who is playing, encoded in four Bits. We will come back to these contents later. The second portion of the message is composed of a number of words.
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators
221
They are all—on the Byte (= 8 Bits) inside their start- and stopbits—initiated by the databit zero. These words encode information about how the actions, as defined by the status word, are played.
Fig. 21.51. The MIDI message types.
Let us first make the example shown in Figure 21.50. Here the first three Bits 001 encode the action of pressing down a key (Note-ON, the note’s onset action). The following four Bits 0101 tell us which “musician,” called channel in the MIDI code, is playing the Note-ON action; here it is channel 5, written in its binary representation 0101. With this information, the data words tell the musician which key to press down: The seven Bits in the first data word, namely 0111100, correspond to 60, the middle C on the piano. The second data word shows the seven-Bit binary number 1111001, corresponding to 61, and meaning “velocity.” Here we see the gestural approach: “Velocity” means the velocity with which a keyboard player hits key number 60, and this is a parameter for loudness. The data words can specify any number in the interval 0 − 127, so the velocity value is a middle loudness. The total time for such a message is three times 320 μsec, roughly one millisecond. This is not very short, and it can in fact happen that complex musical information flow can be heard in its serial structure. As announced above, these numbers are still quite symbolic. The pitch associated with a key number is not given in the MIDI code, so it is up to the synthesizer to interpret a key number in terms of pitch. And velocity must also be specified by the synthesizer in order to become a loudness value. This is a typical situation of a connotative semiotic system (see chapter 2): The MIDI Specification only decodes the Bit sequence, and then this result is taken as an expressive unit pointing to the acoustical contents via the synthesizer’s signification engine. The messages are divided into different categories (which are then encoded in the statusbyte). These categories are shown in Figure 21.51. There are two big categories of messages: channel and system messages. The former relate to single voices or their collaborative action, where the latter concern the entire system and are encoded by the statusbyte starting with 111 after the
222
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.52. Some channel voice messages.
initial status index 1. Channel messages of voice type relate to single musicians (channels), while channel mode messages relate to the channels’ collaboration. Figure 21.52 shows some channel voice messages. You recognize the 1 as the initial Bit of the statusbyte. The action type is 1000 for Note Off, the databyte starts with the mandatory zero and then has the 128 possible values indicated by kkkkkkk. The two databytes define Key number and Velocity, as in our example above. Program Change, for example, describes the instrument that is going to be played. This is a typical situation where the meaning depends upon the synthesizer’s settings. For the so-called General MIDI standard, these numbers have a fixed meaning, 0 being reserved for acoustic grand piano and 127 being assigned to gunshot. The system messages are of three types: System Exclusive for messages that are reserved for specific information used by the industrial producer, like Yamaha, Casio, etc.; System common messages for general system information, such as the time position in an ongoing piece; and Real Time messages for time information (e.g. the timing clock that produces the ticks, see below about ticks). 21.3.5 Time in MIDI, Standard MIDI Files MIDI has a special treatment of time. It is not a physical time format, but counts time in multiples of ticks. The value of a tick is variable. Usually a tick means a 24th of a quarter note. But the physical duration of a tick must be defined on a special header. In the Standard MIDI Files, this header is called meta information and it tells us about the tempo that relates ticks to physical durations. Standard MIDI Files save MIDI informations in order to play a recording back on a MIDI device. The Standard MIDI File Formats define the syntax of such files. Let us look at a typical Standard MIDI Files to see what this syntax looks like in a concrete piece of music (see Figure 21.53).
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators
223
Fig. 21.53. A typical MIDI standard file to see how this syntax looks in a concrete piece of music.
In the first column of the file’s table, we see the delta time, which indicates in multiples of ticks the time delay between successive messages. The second column indicates the status byte in hexadecimal (base 16) numbers. The action is Note On, encoded by 1001, and the player is 0000 (first channel 0), yielding the hexadecimal pair 90. The next number is the hexadecimal key number 34, i.e. decimal key number 52 = 3 × 16 + 4—the e, first note in the score on top of the figure. Then we have the hexadecimal velocity value 53, i.e. the decimal velocity 53, medium loud. The next event is 120 ticks later and represents to play the end of the first note. Here we have a very economical convention, namely the “running status” command, which means not to change the status. This means that we again play that e but now with velocity 0! We play the note again but mute it. This is a creative use of the Note On message! When done with this note, we start the second note, g, without any time delay, i.e. the delta time is zero after the end of the first note, and so on.
224
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.54. Jean le Rond D’Alembert and Denis Diderot, the fathers of the famous French Encyclop´edie published first in 1751.
21.3.6 Short Introduction to Denotators Denotators were introduced to music informatics in 1994 [74] as a data format of the RUBATO software to cover representations of all possible musical objects. The denotator system was the product of a quite creative process. We encountered the problem while designing the data format for a software that would do everything from analysis to composition and performance. We started with an approach that resembled the well-known database management systems. We tried to be flexible on the parameters that represent musical objects. We set up lists of sufficient length to cover onset, duration, loudness, glissando, crescendo, instrumental voice, etc., so every such object would live in a big module, and most objects would only need a fraction of the available parameters. For example, a pause would have vanishing loudness, a fictitious pitch, and only onset and duration and voice as reasonable parameters. On the one hand, this looked artificial—why wouldn’t we just take the parameters that were really used? On the other hand, we were also questioned by ethnomusicologists who made it clear that we would never get to a universal representation; every day they find new instruments, techniques and parameters that had not been considered in the past. We therefore had the problem and the critical concept: find a universal data format for music in an encyclopedic environment with an ever-growing repertory. The wall of this concept was the singular! Universality suggests a single format, and more precisely a single big space where every instance would be positioned. This evidently contradicts the extensibility requirement and also the problem of economy: Why work in an enormous space for tiny objects? The creative solution of this dilemma was the negation of the requirement of a single top space. We needed a data format that could add new object types at any time without having to revise the entire format, as would be the case
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators
225
Fig. 21.55. The architecture of conceptual construction as suggested by the French encyclopedia.
in database management systems. It became clear that this means creating a multiplicity of spaces, one for each object type. This would however be the end of universality since no systematic construction would be at hand. We found the solution from two sources: (1) The semiotic theory of French encyclopedists Jean le Rond D’Alembert and Denis Diderot, the authors of the famous Encyclop´edie, published in 1751. (2) The universal constructions in modern mathematics—limits, colimits, and powerobjects—as universally present in a topos, the most powerful single mathematical structure of the last 50 years, in fact the basic structure of geometry and logic, of theoretial physics, and of music theory.
Fig. 21.56. The recursive ramification principle.
The semiotics of the French encyclopedists is based upon three principles:
226
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
• unit´e (unity) - grammar of synthetic discourse - philosophy • int´egralit´e (completeness) - all facts - dictionary • discours (discourse) - encyclopedic ordering - representation From the mathematical source, it became clear that concepts are built according to the French principles by a quite explicit methodology, which means that the multiplicity of spaces postulated when opening that wall of a unique space could be built following a unifying method. The three French principles would offer an architecture of conceptual construction, illustrated in Figure 21.55. The idea is that every concept type refers to other concepts. This is what we understand as being unity. Next, the reference is given by a comprehensive ramification variety, the ways to refer to previous concepts (see Figure 21.56). This means completeness: There is no other way to build concepts. And third, these types can be ordered in some linear ordering and thereby shape the discoursive display of conceptual architectures.
Fig. 21.57. Our concept architecture of denotators and forms.
These principles now apply to define concretely what are our concept architectures (see Figure 21.57). According to the encyclopedic approach, the basic building principles are recurrence, ramification, and linear ordering. Let us first start with what is being described. We have to define concepts that are of a specific type (its “house”). We shall no longer suppose a big universal house, but, like snails carrying around their own houses, for each concept a special house. In geometric terms (and also referring to the object-oriented programming paradigm), we shall view concepts as being points in a given geometric space. We call these points denotators and their spaces forms, similar
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators
227
to the Aristotelian distinction between form and substance, denotators being substance. A form must have a name (a sequence of ASCII symbols), the form name. Also a denotator must have a name, denotator name. This is necessary because not only values count but also their signification. For example, a real number might be an onset or a duration. This is taken care of when specifying the form name as being “Onset” or “Duration.” Next, the ramification type, i.e. the way the form refers to other, already given forms, must be indicated. We shall see in a moment what types are available. The type being given, the collection of referred forms, is called coordinator. It will in general be a sequence F1 , . . . Fn of forms. The denotator shows its form in the entry for form name. According to this form, the denotator has a collection of coordinates, which are also denotators, usually a sequence D1 . . . Ds−1 , Ds of denotators. In our form architecture, there is a recursive basis, namely the simple forms. They are those spaces that reside on purely mathematical information. In this case, the coordinator is a mathematical space A. Let us look at a
Fig. 21.58. Simple forms referring to STRG
concrete such space (see Figure 21.58). The form name is “Loudness,” the type is “Simple,” the coordinator is the set A = ST RG of strings from a given alphabet, usually ASCII. A denotator may have the name “mezzoforte,” the form’s name being “Loudness,” and the coordinates are a string of letters from ST RG, in our case mf, the symbol used in scores for a medium loudness. We may vary the mathematical space; here are some simple first examples:
228
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
•
form = , denotator = • form = , denotator = (b-flat) • form = , denotator = • form = , denotator = The most general simple space scheme is to take any module M over a commutative ring R and to select the coordinates of denotators as being elements c ∈ M . Examples are pitch classes with module Z12 or a module M = Z× Z365 ×Z24 ×Z60 ×Z60 ×Z28 for time in years:days:hours:minutes:seconds:frames. Why only modules? This has no deeper reason; it is just the straightforward mathematical basis from the examples of classical theories and practice. But one is now also envisaging topological contexts, in particular for mathematical gesture theory [87]. The recursive construction is the part that relies on the universal operations covered by the topos structure. We call such forms compound, and it here is where the ramification must be specified: How do I refer to given forms? The
Fig. 21.59. Limit forms.
first compound type is called limit, and it generalizes the Cartesian product
21.3 Symbolic Formats: Notes, MIDI, Denotators
229
known from set theory. An example is shown in Figure 21.59. This example has form name “Interval.” Its coordinator is a diagram of already given forms; here we have n forms F1 , . . . Fi , . . . Fn . These forms are connected by arrows that designate transformations between the forms’ denotators. These transformations generalize the affine transformations we have in the case of modules of simple forms. In our example we three forms: two named “Note,” and one named “Onset”. The example shows two transformations from the Note form to the Onset form, namely projecting a note denotator to its onset denotator. A denotator here called “myInterval” contains two Note denotators plus one Onset denotator, and the transformations guarantee that the onset denotator is identical to the onset of both notes. This simply means that we have a couple of notes at the same onset, i.e. a simultaneous interval. Limit denotators generalize what in American music theory following David Lewin’s transformational ideas has been called a Klumpenhouwer-network [83].
Fig. 21.60. Colimit forms.
The second universal construction of compound forms relies on the “dual” of limits, namely colimits, which generalize the union of sets. In our example in Figure 21.60, we are describing a colimit form defined by the same diagram of forms as above for the colimit construction. The denotators are the elements of the union of the denotators of all forms F1 , . . . Fi , . . . Fn modulo the identification of any two such denotators that are connected by a chain of the transformations of the diagram. In the example here, we take just one form F1 = Chord parameterizing chords of pitch classes (see the next construction for details of this form), with one transformation, the transposition by n semitones. The colimit consists of the chord classes modulo n-fold transposition.
230
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
Fig. 21.61. Powerset forms.
A third universal construction of compound forms is called Powerset. Its coordinator is a single form F , and the denotators are just sets of denotators of form F . In our example in Figure 21.61, the “Chord” form is defined, and its denotators are sets of denotators of form F = PitchClass. This fourfold typology: simple, limit, colimit, and powerset is everything one needs to perform any known conceptualization in mathematics and also in music theory. The system has also been used to model GIS (Geographic Information Systems). The creative point here is the very small construction methodology for a variety of spaces. And we should add that these techniques have also been implemented in a Java-based program RUBATO Composer [91], where forms and denotators can be constructed on the fly, whenever one needs a new form or denotator. However, there is a detail that is astonishing when such a creative extension of the space concept is at hand: We did not exclude circularity, which means that in the reference tree of a form, it may happen that the same form reappears. At first, this seems pathological, but it turns out that an important set of forms are effectively using this circularity, e.g. forms for Fourier analysis or forms for FM sound representation. More than this: It turns out that essentially all interesting formats for notes are circular. For example, notes that have satellites for ornamentation or Schenker analysis are circular, see [91]. Therefore the creative act not only solves the original problem of the multiplicity of spaces, but it even enables space constructions that were not anticipated by the classical understanding of what a space can be.
21.4 Creativity in Electronic Music: Languages and Theories
231
21.4 Creativity in Electronic Music: Languages and Theories We have now examined music technology, but it is also important to remind composers of electronic music that technology does not guarantee successful compositions. We therefore should not conclude this chapter without questioning the fascination with electronic music composition for many composers (young and old). The explosion of music technology—in fact one of the first applications of general computer technology in the middle of the last century (Max Mathews stands as a central creator of computer-aided music, and the music software Max testifies to this pioneering work, see Figure 21.62)—has created an
Fig. 21.62. A rare meeting in Zurich 2005 of leading computer music pioneers (from left) Jean-Claude Risset, Max Mathews, and John Chowning.
enthusiasm for the invention of sound synthesis programs. In this atmosphere, the first twenty years of Boulez’s famous Paris-based IRCAM were characterized by a breathtaking extension of sound worlds, of the capability to compose sound, and not just with sounds. This shift of compositional paradigms followed Marshall McLuhan’s claim, “The media is the message.” One believed that the technological medium of the computer could take over the creative capacity of humans. It was a kind of belief that is widespread in Artificial Intelligence, a belief that intelligent machine assemblies would eventually produce emergent properties, i.e. intelligent output that was not implanted in the system and that would be created ex nihilo by those machines. It was believed in musical creation that composition could be creative when delegated to computer synthesis of sound. Spectral composition is such an example, where the Fourier
232
21 Acoustics, Instruments, Music Software, and Creativity
synthesis was believed to carry a magical meaning of music that, say, serial formalisms could not generate. The overwhelming variety of computer-generated sounds had two drawbacks, however. First, those compositions could not be described in an adequate language. Every composition was a singular event without being ‘backed’ by a communicative notation. Many computer-music compositions were improvisational in the sense that their creation was a spontaneous action without any reproducible trace. The score did not exist anymore for those creations. It is still a major problem that many electronic compositions, created with Max MSP, say, are made by slaves of this technology without tracing the detailed construction process in a reliable language. This is not only a consequence of the emergent property mysticism, but it also follows from a deficiency that became virulent at the IRCAM in the last decade of the last century: They learned that you cannot compose music— and even less electronic music, with its overwhelming repertory of sounds and sound-generating processes—without thinking about theory. The composers with those infinitely variable sounds could simply not organize their music anymore without higher guidance. Guerino Mazzola asked Jean-Claude Risset in 1982 (he was a leading computer musician at IRCAM at that time) about a theory controlling those huge sound manifolds, and he answered that there simply was none. We were confronted with a zoo of new ‘sound animals’ whose variety had turned wild. It was positive, but it was chaotic. Later, research was initiated at IRCAM (and elsewhere) that led, for example, to the composition software OpenMusic, which took care of theoretical and associated language issues for computer-aided musical composition. The insight was that you cannot delegate extensions of semiotic content to machines. Musical creation must be taken care of by humans, who are the only creators that can add meaning—machines cannot. Computer-aided composition cannot make sense (or meaning) alone; it is the human composer who has to cover meaning and sense of music.
22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation
Composition and improvisation are two forms of musical creation. Although they are different, they share a number of characteristic features. We are not going to claim their equivalence or even essential identity. But we shall focus on the aspect of creativity they share, and we shall try to prove that this aspect is—albeit complementary—essentially of equal weight in the creation of musical works. We shall more precisely make clear that composition and improvisation turn out to be two ramifications of one and the same creative strategy: There is always composition in the genesis of improvisation, and vice versa.
22.1 Defining Composition and Improvisation Musical composition is an activity leading to a result that enables us to objectivize and conserve data about musical objects. In Western music tradition, following the first neumatic attempts in the ninth century, the standard result of composition is a score, consisting of a number of note events or pauses that are inserted into a system of reference pitch, onset, duration, and loudness, together with a set of special signs to indicate articulation, loudness variations, and performance commands such as tempo and fingering. The classical score may be replaced by a set of symbols that encode other approaches to notes— they can be of a more graphical nature or else expressions of computer language tokens, such as MIDI, denotators, or other symbols. The compositional activity then consists of the creation of such a result. It is a remarkable fact, and we shall come back to it later in this chapter, that the original usage of notation was to generate a written trace of musical works and to describe theoretical reflections, but not to give birth to musical creations. Score writing, however, commuted from the documentation task to the creation of music, and it is significant that in a conservative understanding of Western music, the score is even identified with the musical work, the creation of the score being the core musical activity, while performance of a score is reduced to a service similar to G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 22, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
233
234
22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation
what MIDI slavery (slave is, in fact, the name for a MIDI-driven device) would provide for present music technology. The essence of composition is that it does not generate musical sounds but commands that enable the production of sounds when applied to an instrumental interface. A composition is not sounding music, but a command structure for the production of sounding music. This does not mean that a composition is not music, but that its reality resides on a symbolic level. It is something akin to a culinary recipe, not the dish itself. Although a composition is made to generate sounding music, it is, in most cases, not explicit enough to comprise all determinants of the intended sounding music. For example, Bach’s compositions did not indicate loudness, let alone tempi. And even in a standard composition of Western music, many determinants of sound are not defined. For example, a piano score by Beethoven does not specify the tuning, and the detailed agogics is far from explicit. Dynamics and articulation are also factors that have to be shaped by the performer. This is the topic of performance theory: the transformation of a symbolic score into sounding music. It is not written on the score, except for some gross and often quantitatively poor indications of tempo, articulation, or dynamics. The only case where a composition is complete is where its specification generates a unique sounding corpus. For example, this is the case for the digital representation of a piece of music on a CD, or for the MIDI representation of a piece, where the meaning of all MIDI parameters is precisely connected to a sound generator. So a composition usually requires a set of additional actions in order to define a complete sounding musical body. This “difference set” is the improvisational part of the created music. Improvisation is all that is not encoded in a preconceived symbolic system of commands leading to a sounding musical body. Although this definition looks like a negative one in that improvisation is all that is not written in those symbols, we could also have defined composition as all that is not improvisation, where improvisation is understood positively as being the totality of all actions performed while playing the sounding music. We shall analyze this approach when dealing in more detail with improvisation. And we shall see that this alternative is somehow more complex than the chosen one. It is easier to exhibit the symbols backing a sounding musical work than to describe precisely the actions of the performing artists, hence our choice. Although this looks like a clear conceptual setup, which could be summarized by a formula composition + improvisation = sounding music, the details are less evident. Let us look at some basic situations. First, if the composition allows for a selection of a set of variants, then what is the status of this choice? For example, if we have a lead sheet composition with defined chord symbols, the performer would have to select one of the chords subsumed under the given symbol. Is this part of the composition or is
22.1 Defining Composition and Improvisation
235
this an improvisational action? If the chord symbol is Cm7 , then each sounding realization thereof will be improvisational because it transcends the symbolic information. The composition only specifies the set of chords subsumed under Cm7 , but every concrete choice (of pitches, onsets, durations, and loudnesses and of instrument) will be improvisational. Even if it seems clear that a preconceived part of the performance is not improvisational, the question of what is preconceived remains critical. It may happen that in the situation above, the set of chord representatives for Cm7 is not further specified in the lead sheet, but that nonetheless, in the performer’s mind, there is a set of rules that narrow the possible selection, and then the improvisation would be narrowed by this additional set of preconceived rules. A neuroscientist or psychoanalyst might argue that every choice is predetermined by some subconscious rule, and therefore no improvisation will take place in this case. The critical point in this argument is that the compositional part is not well defined. If we define the composition once and for all, then the improvisational part is all but the composition, whatever composition is chosen. Of course, this may be done in many ways. But then, the improvisational part is improvisational with respect to the chosen composition, and this may be put into question as a critical or even artificial choice. There is also another extremal, where the CD recording of a Beethoven sonata has virtually no improvisational part at all, but this is acceptable because the digital data determine everything here (except the loudness, which can be changed by the user of the CD player). In other words, the equation composition + improvisation = sounding music may be accepted in any case, provided the meaning of the parts is understood and interpreted in an adequate way. We should add that the above definition would conceive the performative part of sounding music as an improvisational instance. This is however not the usual understanding of performance. It transforms symbolic events of the composition to a sounding event, but it is not agreed that this transformation would be an improvisational action. Why not? Because the shaping of symbols in the performative action is not free from predetermined symbolic contents. For example, the shaping of a tempo curve might be defined by a well-defined tempo operator which deforms the score’s given constant tempo, see [89, chapter 17] for details. In fact, this case would then be subsumed under the compositional part of that performance since it follows predefined symbolic data for the construction of sounding events. This means that in performance one would assign all such symbolic rules to the compositional part, and not to the improvisational one. Observe that the previous definitions do not make any statements about the poietic nature of composition or improvisation. We did not describe which mechanisms are used to realize either creation. Our next discourse will therefore focus on the creative processes giving rise to the compositional and improvisational productions.
236
22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation
22.2 Creativity in Composition It is a first characteristic of composition that its time is threefold: It is first of all the time that signifies the material parameter of symbolic events to be defined for the composition, i.e. the symbolic time, in units of quarter notes, say. A second time is then added by the performance transformation that maps symbolic parameters to acoustic parameters. This physical time, measured in seconds, say, is defined by the tempo curve in elementary performance contexts. As such, it becomes concrete when the composition is performed. The third time is the time in which the composition is being constructed. It is the time wherein the thoughts are deployed. Schoenberg has related this to a kind of slow-motion improvisation. The thought process of the composer constructs the composition in a mental realm that usually is much slower than the time of performance.1 The third time where the creative compositional process unfolds could be called the logical time. In this process, the composer gets off the ground with two ingredients: the material of the composition and the rules that allow the material to be shaped and arranged in the parameter space of the symbolic events. 22.2.1 Composition by Objectivation Although in composition the processual configuration, defined by the flow chart between material and transformational rules, looks natural, it is a very specific construction that would not work for improvisation as a real-time activity. In fact, the separation of “material boxes” from transformation rules would not work in real-time: A gesture requires total unification in the making. It is also remarkable that the real-time activity has been relativized with respect to compositional strategies in its creative potential. Evidently, composing looks more reliable, computational, and controllable than improvising. If you can think about a material component or a rule to be or not to be applied, life is safer. The composer can think about the consequences of his/her decisions. The entire creation is never really risky, at least never in terms of improvisational decisions. But it is mysterious why composers believe that this strategy of creativity is producing better results. Why is the fast improvisational decision something whose cultivation would not enable better quality results without high risk to fail? Why has this compositional strategy been so successful (in Western music culture) against improvisational strategies? First of all, the possibility to delay a decision when time is relatively extended is an attractive alternative. Making an error by spontaneous action becomes virtually impossible. This also means that one’s decisions become more and more immutable since they 1
Observe, however, that John Cage’s composition “ASLSP” [21] has a performance time (639 years) that by far exceeds the composer’s construction time.
22.2 Creativity in Composition
237
are issued from a reflected shaping of musical symbols. In improvisation, such error correction would be impossible. It is as if the improvisers would run for their life. Perhaps this is a serious drawback of improvisation. It expresses the belief that thinking cannot be of such a high quality if it occurs as a real-time gesture. The creative act in this thoughtful “offline mode” has been referred to under an interesting perspective by Michael Cherlin [24]. He classifies three types of musical memory: (1) the internal reference of a work, which one would associate with David Lewin’s transformational theory; for example, the construction of an inverted series deduced from the original series that would be played in the beginning of a piece, (2) the reference between musical works as a style-critical and tradition-oriented memory; for example, the sonata form of a piece connecting it to another earlier sonata, and (3) the reference pointing to extra-musical memory; for example, the near-death experience of Schoenberg whose trace we can discover in his String Trio, op. 45. The idea behind this setup is that composition essentially is a memory process. The local and global logic of composition is based upon a referential system of memory-based delays. This type of thought process is organized through a network of pipelines that transfer information from past to present. This paradigm suggests that the seriousness of composition relates to its memory delay. Opposed to such memory work, improvisation would appear as memory-less blind activity. Memory appears as the motor of thoughtfulness. Thinking is always looking back, or “down,” onto a distant thing that objectivizes experience. Objectivization here affirms the thought action par excellence in Western scientific methodology. Another aspect of compositional objectivization is that every category of commercial value is based upon objects that can be stored and exchanged under corresponding value conditions. It is not only the memory argument, and the media for compositional creativity, that justifies score writing, but also the commercial disposability. A score is a commercial entity, improvisation is much less so. We come back to this topic in the next section. 22.2.2 Creativity in Composition with Symbolic Objects In the semiotic context of symbolic objects as made available in score-driven composition, creativity occurs in a very specific way. The available signs/concepts are time-independent abstract entities. They can be reconsidered ad libitum in the logical space of compositional construction. The symbolic time (the first one in our list above) they convey is a material parameter like density of a material for artistic sculpture. It does not unfold in the compositional process, but only when the potential performance takes place. The semiotic context of composition is extra-temporal. Composition takes place in a logical space-time, and its narrativity is shaped by the syntagm of this topos and by the rules that describe the structure of such syntagm. The performance then only appears as a projection of the logical syntagm, and its narrativity in physical time may be radically different from the logical time organization. For example, the logical narrativity may show an implication “A implies B” in
238
22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation
the following example. Suppose that we are in tonality F-major and want to modulate to tonality G♭-major. Then what is given logically first is the target tonality G♭-major = A. We then have to construct its logical implication B— namely, B = the modulation structure from F-major to G♭-major. So B follows A in the logical narrativity, whereas the composition would show first B and then A in the score’s timeline. Creatively solving a problem in this context therefore looks very different from an improvisational situation. Suppose the problem is as follows: You have composed a tonal and rhythmical structure A and want to connect it to a second successive tonal and rhythmical structure B. Then you focus on the concept of a transitional structure connecting those tonalities and rhythms following a given rule set. It might happen that such a transition is impossible for the given rule set (e.g. if the tonalities have a distance not allowing modulation in your modulatory theory). You would then take these rules as walls and open them to a more powerful transformational toolset. This may take hours, or days, until the critical walls are opened and then connected to a wider context that solves the transitional problem. For example, the modulations in the Allegro movement of Beethoven’s Hammerklavier Sonata, op. 106, show such a situation. The so-called “catastrophe” modulation in measures 189-197 from E♭ (major) to b (minor), as discussed in [77, 28.2] and in [87] with regard to the gestural dissolution of the fanfare, shows that Beethoven’s rule set would not allow him to modulate in a standard way here (E♭ and b being in different “worlds” in that context). The creative solution of this impossibility refers to the rhythmical construction of the fanfare. This one has two parts: The first exhibits the repetition of a halting movement, and the second then exhibits the halting of a repetitive movement, i.e. a symmetric construction exchanging onset and duration. Beethoven’s catastrophe modulation solves his obstructional situation by two devices: He does not modulate using a standard modulatory chord assembly, but instead shows the structural background for the obstruction, namely the diminished seventh chord. And he shapes the impossibility to modulate in a repeated halting from the fanfare’s first part, eventually freezing the rhythm in the fanfare’s initial halting gesture. The modulating section of the piece has been creatively finished here by making the obstructions evident by repeating a halting movement and also creating the perception of a halting in the logical standard situation: “Rien ne va plus.” This creative action is based on a complex extra-temporal logic of modulatory tools and obstructions, and on the reuse of the fanfare’s halting rhythm, and on the decision to compose those structures that are responsible for the modulatory obstruction. Such a communicative performance could not have happened in a real-time environment because it is built on a global perspective of the tonal topography and its logical coherence. Abstraction of this type characterizes composition. It is creative in a semiotic architecture that manipulates musical objects and concepts on a high level of meta-theoretical symbols.
22.3 Creativity in Improvisation
239
Remark 11 Often, compositional structures are taken from a preliminary improvisational action. So is this a compositional or an improvisational part of the music? Insofar as it is a set of symbols to be inserted and/or processed to the score’s material, it is a compositional object. Previous actions leading to the present material are not part of this perspective. We are strictly considering the compositional level of manipulating symbols, not the history of available symbols. To be clear, the history of compositional or improvisational actions might involve both compositional and improvisational creativity; this pertains to the recursive nature of musical creativity. But our perspective in this chapter is a synchronic one, focusing on given materials and rules, not the diachronic dimension that involves historical developments, another important perspective that lies orthogonally to the synchronic one. How could the creativity process in composition be characterized? 1. It strongly relies on the availability of symbolic musical objects as elements of a semiotic context whose syntagm unfolds in a logical time as opposed to the symbolic and eventually physical material time. 2. The creative management of such symbols heavily relies on the basic semiotic architecture, as typically described by Louis Hjelmslev [89, chapter 4.5] in terms of meta-theory, connotation, and motivation. This architecture manipulates symbols in a referential network, whose narrativity is independent of material time. Accordingly, the creative core manipulation of wall inspection and extension involves all of Hjelmslev’s constructions. 3. The network of these symbols allows for a separation of material boxes from the connecting transformational arrows. The compositional narrativity is reflected in these networks’ structure. See Figure 22.1 for the example of a dodecaphonic row (material box on left upper corner), together with three transformed rows (material boxes) that are connected by the transformations of retrograde and inversion. Therefore, it is a major problem of compositional creativity to construct transformational networks in such a way that their projection to the performative realization reveals their compositional logic in the aesthesis of performance and perception. However, the double reality in composition does not dispense the composer from communicating the symbolic realm to the physical embodiment in sound and gesture. Composers, especially in contemporary composition, should become aware of the necessity to make this double reality presentable and audible to the addressed public.
22.3 Creativity in Improvisation Following the above characterization of compositional creativity, improvisational creativity must look dramatically different since improvisation is strictly separated from those symbolic objects created in composition.
240
22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation
Fig. 22.1. Schoenberg’s first dodecaphonic row and its three transformed versions define four material boxes. They are connected by the transformations of inversion and retrograde.
To begin with, contextual reality for improvisational creativity looks different from the compositional one. According to [89, chapter 4.12], the performing artist defines and lives an artistic reality that relates to three basic dimensions: presence, dance, and balance. So let us look more carefully at this reality, and compare Figure 22.2. Within the three dimensions of musical oniontology to which the communicative artistic dimension refers—realities, embodiment, and semiotics—the performer realizes a crossing of a very special type. In what follows, we stress the characteristic features. The most characteristic feature on the axis of realities is the interaction of two bodies: the musician’s body and the body of physical sounds. Their interaction is generated on the interface of the musical instrument, whose bodily manipulation produces the music’s sounds. For an acting performer, this coupling of bodies is the core neutral niveau. All other levels of neutrality might be implied or subsumed, but this one is the manifest neutral building block. On the axis of embodiment, corresponding to the reality of instrumentally interacting bodies, the performer’s focus is on gestures. It is these gestures that are communicating musical formulas and processes. It is the highest quality of musical expressivity to expand compact musical formulas into gestures. Gestural embodiment does not populate given spaces but creates them, defines their
22.3 Creativity in Improvisation
241
Fig. 22.2. The performing artist defines and lives an artistic reality that relates to three basic dimensions: presence, dance, and balance.
extension and thereby enables fellow musicians’ gestures to resonate with one’s gestures in these shared spaces. “Understanding is catching the gesture and being able to continue.” This deep insight by French philosopher and mathematician Jean Cavaill`es [22] is what happens in the gestural interaction among performers: Their gesturally spaced vibration is what drives their bodies to move and to shape the “body of time.” On the axis of semiotics, the (successful) performer organizes the future of the music being performed with reference to the music’s past. The meaning of the music played to this present moment is connected to the shaping of the meaning of the next musical signification in a flow of thoughts. This creative transfer is performed by the body’s gestural utterance. In order to achieve this in a coherent and persuasive way, we have to identify an environment where such a strong shaping activity is executed. On the level of physical events, we cannot realize such a program, since physical time presence reduces to a single time point, and nothing can really happen in such an instantaneous moment. 22.3.1 Improvisational Creativity in the Imaginary Time-Space Recall that compositional creativity uses threefold time. In improvisational creativity, we shall also recognize several types of time. The first being the physical time where performance takes place, there is a second type that is quite remarkable because it is of a totally different nature. Let us explain this. We argue that the concept of presence in time-critical arts requires an addi-
242
22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation
tional “imaginary” time and space2 . It is in this realm that the transitional processing of past music to future music, the planning of gestural strategies, and the body-instrument-sound interface are all displayed and organized. It is a quite dramatic change of understanding of what happens in the artistic presence, because it eliminates the mystification of spontaneity and unpredictability in creative performance. These attributes have had a great influence on the failure to understand creative performance, from classical music to free jazz. Improvisation, creative performance—all of that has been boiled down to these negative concepts: Spontaneity and unpredictability are just negations of any sort of positively defined artistic shaping; they are the “emergent properties” of creativity mysticism, creativity by negation. Telling a musician to be spontaneous is of no help whatsoever: It is just a recommendation to rely on nothing that could be conceived of in the artistic-shaping activity. However, offering to the artist the concept of imaginary time-space is a completely different affair: It opens a huge environment where the artist’s consciousness can evolve and construe complex architectures and highways of shaping musical structures. The gestural complex is driven in this time-space; the flow from past to future music that is being played is driven and lived in this imaginary realm. Let us focus on the semiotic flow process connecting past music instances to the shaping of future ones, which can take place in very different ways. First, the performers may conceive of different extensions of the music’s structure that is played immediately before presence. An improviser might then only listen to one other fellow musician or he/she might listen to many of them when shaping the next sounds. For example, a pianist may take over the rhythmical gesture of a drummer and play a similar rhythm with chords immediately after the drummer’s rendition. Second, these future sounds might also be shaped by a more or less strong reference to pre-conceived structures, independent of the actual performance, such as the reference to a given score that tells me which notes to play next independently of how and what has been played to the moment. This might happen if the improvisation relates to a lead sheet, where a given harmony might be played following the present position in that lead sheet and not what other musicians might have played immediately before. In the previous discussion, this second type of reference evidently pertains to what had been identified as a compositional part of the sounding performance. These factors in the shaping of future sounds are more or less distributed processes: They define an identity of the performed piece of music that is distributed among a number of agents. This is why we call this process one of a distributed identity. And why we would define the quality of the present 2
It is known that modern physics—in the research of Stephen Hawking [51] in Big Bang cosmology, and also in contributions of Itzhak Bars [9] to the unification of gravitation and quantum mechanics—has introduced a second time dimension.
22.3 Creativity in Improvisation
243
performance as being defined by the coherence and strength of this flow as a distributed identity. Putting the three components of performance together, we see that the pairing of body-instrument-body and gestural space vibration could be conceived as the aspect of dance. In short, dance would be viewed as a synthesis of body and gesture. A second pairing, body-instrument-body and the flow of structural unfolding, would then be seen as the balance in a bodily realm, a concept that is akin to what classical Greek aesthetics called “kairos”—the perfect balance in the body’s dynamics of presence. And finally, the pairing of gesture and structural flow would be understood as a shaping of the body of time, the dynamics within the imaginary time-space that defines our imaginary body of time; we might call this the presence in performance. Putting these three pairings together, one could then conceive musical performance as being the balanced dancing of presence, an existential intensity in three directions of communicative activity. In view of these preliminary remarks on the performer’s ontology, improvisation is localized in a space of gestures on interfacing bodies that meet in the kairos of an imaginary presence. The latter might refer to compositional preconceived symbols, but it is only the imaginary presence of improvisation that can shift such remote entities from the compositional abstraction to embodied gestural presence. 22.3.2 Improvisational Creativity with Gestural Embodiment The radical difference to compositional objectivization in improvisation is that there is no referentiality to given objects and that, a fortiori, no transformation of objects is at stake. Improvisatory creation is an affair of pure gestuality. Gestures are not just nice rewordings of transformations, but replace those material objects and maps from compositional networks. Gestural creativity does not refer to things; it gives life to embodied action, and it is in the making where we have to think this aspect. We should stress that this type of creativity is not restricted to free jazz, but includes contemporary music or any other style of improvisation. Although gesture can be taken as the constituent of improvisational creation, we still need to conceive connectivity among gestures, namely that structure that must replace networking in compositional creativity. There are two strategies for such connectivity: On the one hand, gestures may be connected by morphism of gestures. Such morphisms have been identified in the flow responsible for the group collaboration in free improvisation; they have been described in [85, chapter 9.2]. There is a second strategy that might be even more substantial as a gestural utterance, and this is the hypergesture concept: Hypergestures are gestures of gestures, and in particular continuous curves connecting gestures. This is an excellent device for connecting systems of gestures without being forced to exit the conceptual framework of gestures. The world of gestures (mathematically speaking: the category of gestures) is closed
244
22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation
under the construction of networks of gestures, also known as hypergestures. This is the remarkable difference to the compositional situation: Gestures are a complete self-referential system. With these general observations on the improviser’s realm, we want to investigate the improvisational shape of creativity. We have to first identify the contextual system and an open question. The contextual system is the semiotics of gestures. But here we have to pay attention to the generative role of gestures relating to semiotics. Gestures are not simple signs referring to a given semantic content; they generate meaning, they are semantic generators, not carriers. With this in mind, a critical concept would be a determined gesture that is responsible for the given problem. What can then be a wall of that gesture? Let us offer an example. We have to exhibit a critical gesture for a problem while performing in improvisation. Suppose the group is performing a free improvisation and gets stuck in a groove (e.g. a blues groove). The critical gesture here could be a pianist playing the groove by a steadily repeated blues motif. So the task would be to exhibit the walls of this motivic gesture and to open them in such a way that the motive can be “dissolved” and the band may move out of that bluesy prison. Of course, one could just break with the blues and blow it up playing instantly some other groove or any other gesture. The creative solution and a solution that is musically interesting would however consist of an exit from that groove, which is organically organized. Why is this musically more interesting than simply blowing it up? Because the latter would express a brutal disconnection from the blues and an introduction of a new musical structure without any motivation. The coherence of music is one of the most important signs of quality. Schoenberg has strongly stressed this characteristic in his theory of tonal modulation [107]. The quality of a modulation is how it shapes the transition between two neighboring tonalities. Blowing up the blues by any other groove would correspond to an unmediated shift in tonality, an unfortunate ‘trick’ of bad commercial music. Here is how a wall may be exhibited: It is known from collaborative free jazz theory [85, chapter 9.2] that exchange of gestures is responsible for distributed identity in the flow. So in our case, the walls of that piano blues groove would consist in “catching the gesture and continue” in the spirit of Cavaill`es. This means that the other members of the group would project their understanding of the groove by playing its aspects, such as rhythm or melodic or harmonic gestural projections. For example, the drummer may play that groove’s rhythm. Or the saxophonist may play the groove’s melodic contour. This is in fact an inspection of the groove’s anatomy. Not by detached analytical activity, but by gestural resonance. Such caught gestures then may be taken by the fellow musician(s) and replayed through the gesture’s limbs. Musicians might play the rhythm, identifying its parts and articulatory profile, and then open it by altering those constituents, over-stressing them, replaying them with
22.4 Instant Composition and Slow-Motion Improvisation
245
different accents—in other words, taking that body, “riding that horse,” and moving it, deforming it. This is nothing else but a hypergesture acting on the given gestural aspect and deforming it in different directions. This may then introduce a new profile to the groove, a profile that can be received and understood and applied by the other group members. It might not, however, lead to a resolution of the groove’s deadlocking force, but it can be taken as a dynamic action in the right direction. This example gives us the general strategy for creativity in the improvisational gesture context. One exhibits a critical gesture, one then project from that gesture to other gestures using gesture morphisms as described in [85, chapter 9.2]. The walls are exactly those projected gestures that reflect the critical gesture’s anatomy. The walls are then opened by their hypergestural deformations. The resulting new gestures, endpoints of the hypergestural ramifications, then would be candidates for the restatement of the critical gesture. But this time it is the improvisational presence that takes these new aspects and integrates them into the playing, there is no analytical detachment where such things may be “pre-cooked.” How could the creativity process in improvisation be characterized? 1. It strongly relies on the system of gesture and hypergestures that does not allow for abstract symbols and does also not enable logical time as opposed to material (physical) time. Time in improvisation is an existential dimension where gestures are living; it only exists once within gestures. 2. The creative management of gestures relies on the projection of gestures by gestural morphisms and, even more substantially, on the connectivity of gestures within hypergestures. 3. The network of gestures is always a hypergesture. There is no separation of material from transformation, and there is no way to objectivize such gestural networks. They only live in presence. They also have no history: When the music is over, they are gone, and “you can never catch them again.” (Eric Dolphy)
22.4 Instant Composition and Slow-Motion Improvisation After having investigated creativity in composition and improvisation, we should thematize the famous sayings that improvisation is instant composition while composition is slow-motion improvisation. This confrontation is substantial because sounding music is not only split into the independent components of composition and improvisation, but beyond this disjunction also unites these two styles of creativity in a deep interaction. This is what these sayings are about. To be clear, the following discussion does not contradict the above splitting but introduces a more generative aspect, namely about how composition and improvisation are generated from anterior movements of musical creativity. So we are not claiming that composition and improvisation in sounding
246
22 Creativity in Composition and Improvisation
music are each other’s background, but that in every composition there is an improvisational genealogy, and vice versa: Each improvisational action is also driven by a compositional attitude. Let us discuss how this can occur. We first look at the compositional creativity and its possibly improvisational gestuality. But before we get started, we should mention that there is an obvious way to use improvisation in the compositional process, namely to create ‘raw’ material for the composition by improvisation. This can be done, for example, by making a MIDI recording of a piano improvisation and then taking the MIDI file, transforming it to score symbols by a standard sequencer software, and using this data as material for one’s composition. Lots of composers use this technique. However, this is not the creativity within the compositional work; it only makes available compositional material by a specific improvisational technique. The real compositional process lives in the realm of a transformational formalism and shares different time dimensions, most importantly the logical time where thought processes are executed. This level of creativity realizes the abstract construction of transformational networks. But if we focus on this level as such, and if we investigate this level’s generative background and motivation, we will find a germinal layer where ideas are growing according to mental movements that are not logical anymore, but express a gestuality of thoughts. This might be the insight that led Schoenberg to call composition “slow motion improvisation”: The generative forces of the compositional logic are not necessarily logical, but they may very well be nourished by gestures of memory, dreams, and yearnings. These types of background forces will also be responsible for what in compositional creativity is identified as the initial problem. Why should it be a problem to connect two structures in a score with a coherent bridge? Because the composer wants to lay a bridge, a connecting gesture between the structural endpoints. This gestural motivation might lead to a logical construction on the level of transformational networks, but the background is of another nature. And it is also remarkable that Schoenberg’s slow motion metaphor seems to contradict the very nature of improvisation, namely that it takes place in real time. As such it cannot be slow motion. The answer to this apparent contradiction is that the time where composition is driven by improvisatory gestures is the logical time, not the symbolic or physical time. In this logical realm, the composer effectively lives in real time, but the reality is another. Let us next look at improvisational creativity and its possibly compositional background. Again, like for composition, the statement that improvisation is instant composition appears to be a contradiction since composition by definition relies on preconceived structures. Therefore, it seems problematic to identify the preconceived with the instant. As with composition, the solution to this apparent contradiction lies in the concept of time. In composition, the improvisational presence was hosted in the logical space-time, while in improvisation, we have to exhibit a time dimension that simultaneously al-
22.4 Instant Composition and Slow-Motion Improvisation
247
lows for the expanded process of composition and the instantaneous presence of improvisation. This space-time can be related to what we earlier called the imaginary space-time. This dimension enables a big environment for creative activity, occurring in one single physical moment. You can think in compositional terms here without moving in physical time at all. Gestures, the core structures of improvisation, engage this imaginary time in their parametrization. The curve parameter of a gesture curve system is a time parameter in imaginary time. Hypergestures can only exist in this imaginary time because their curves are curves of gestures, so they are moving other movements (and so forth recursively for higher hypergestures). The unfolding of a (hyper)gesture is an event in imaginary (space-)time. Therefore, composition in the sense of a display of preconceived objects is possible if the word’s prefix “pre-” is understood in imaginary (space-)time. The imaginary space-time of improvisation is in itself a kernel structure for a compositional approach to improvisation since it creates a space for musical construction as if we were working out a compositional preconception. The dynamics of (hyper)gestures in the creative work of improvisation evokes a presence that is best described by Mihaly Cs´ıkszentmih´alyi’s flow concept [32] and Keith Sawyer’s extension to group flow [104]. Flow transforms you in what they call “the zone.” It is a presence that is atemporal, and we argue that this is precisely what needs imaginary space-time as localization. The improviser then lives a trancelike presence beyond physical space-time, a dreamlike state of inner balance. This higher level of consciouness is where so-called instant composition takes place. On this level, one recognizes an organizational activity upon gestures as if they were symbolic objects of a hidden dream-like reality. This level of gesture-generated symbols can be made precise in that gestures are the germs of symbols. This has been explained in detail in [85, chapter 11]. Without delving into technicalities here, we may recall that gestures are the generators of abstract mathematical groups (in more technical terms: all groups can be represented by fundamental groups [111]). In other words, this dream-like reality evokes higher symbols of abstract mathematics, and it is in this vein that improvisation is embedded in what they call instant composition. In this state of consciousness, it is not a composition that you are making (like in the normal compositional action), but a composition that drives you, the musician—it is the moment where music plays you and not you the music, but see [85, chapter 11.3] for a thorough discussion. And yes, it is also the audience that will be entranced by such a flowing intensity, if it takes over the music’s vibrating expressivity.
Part IV
Case Studies
23 The CD Passionate Message
This chapter is about a shared creative production of a CD, entitled Passionate Message, by two pianists, Joomi Park and Guerino Mazzola. It is a work that was prepared during five months, January to May 2011. We planned to record four series, and each series has three layers: A compositional component by Joomi, a corresponding ‘comment’ by Guerino, and an improvisation on two pianos by Joomi and Guerino. The last series is a bit different. It starts with an improvisation (not a composition) by Joomi, a further comment by Guerino, and again a shared piano duo improvisation. The idea was to set up a profound dialogue of two completely different styles—Joomi’s contemporary music approach to composition and improvisation, versus Guerino’s free jazz improvisation with previously prepared basic materials—and then synthesizing these styles in a shared improvisation on two pianos. The present discourse intends to analyze this collaboration’s creative processes. We include it because these processes are our own activities and we therefore are able to describe all we know about them without uncertainties about what we have being creating. This does not mean, however, that we have total control of this work. We know all that has come to our consciousness and can therefore give a faithful analysis of this creation.
23.1 The General Background of This Production We shall describe Joomi’s compositional approach via improvisation, Guerino’s improvisational approach via given materials, and the collective improvisation, all based on the overall strategy in the production of the CD. 23.1.1 The Overall Strategy The overall strategy of this CD, recorded on June 4 and June 11, 2011, at the Wild Sound Studio in Minneapolis by Matt Zimmerman, was designed as a G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 23, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
251
252
23 The CD Passionate Message
collaborative project between pianist and contemporary art music composer Joomi Park and free jazz pianist Guerino Mazzola. The encounter was set up to initiate and perform a dialogue between compositional and improvisational perspectives, and also between contemporary music and free jazz. The compositional component was initiated by Joomi’s compositions Black Summer, American Carnival and a re-working of The Beatles song Yesterday, and by Guerino’s composition Verino qu’es. Black Summer is the counter title of White Christmas, as the piece took the melodic materials from it, but the piece sounds completely unrecognizable unless the information is given. Joomi ironically transformed the elegance of the original song into the excitement of people getting busy for their Christmas. The basic inspiration of American Carnival is Joomi’s positive and passionate response to the American festive culture. Joomi’s two compositions were ‘commented on’ by an improvisational free jazz approach by Guerino. The Beatles song was recomposed by Joomi. These three compositional groups were then reflected in improvisations by Joomi and Guerino on two pianos. A fourth piece was the improvisation Joomi’s Dance by Joomi. It was commented on by an improvisation by Guerino and also by a duo improvisation, including a reference to Guerino’s jazz composition Verino qu’es. The general strategy was to investigate composition by improvisation and also to integrate composition in the improvisational approach. So it was not general free jazz, but the integration of compositional material in improvisation by Guerino and also then a synthesis of Joomi’s and Guerino’s soli in a shared improvisation. Here the new music and the free jazz idioms were confronted and merged. Joomi’s and Guerino’s contributions were developed in a prolific discussion in the construction of these musics, meaning that none was an isolated creation but resulted from an intense musical exchange of ideas and performances. 23.1.2 Joomi’s Compositional Approach Joomi earned a PhD in composition from the School of Music at the University of Minnesota. She was professionally educated as a classical pianist in the paradigm of classical and contemporary Western art music. She is a composer who is thoroughly acquainted with this approach to musical creation and has won international prizes. She had composed in the style of the prominent contemporary composing constructions such as serialism, Fibonacci-type schemes, electronic, and aleatoric music for the formal principles of sound parameter selection. But her preferred approach to composition typically starts from improvisational germs played at the piano. In so doing, she wants to rely on the concrete sounding performance as opposed to abstract constructions. An essential point of creative compositional action, however, became more evident to her when she started to get acquainted with improvisation as it is cultivated in the tradition of free jazz, and in particular Cecil Taylor’s approach
23.1 The General Background of This Production
253
to improvisation as an utterance of “dancing hands.” But what was the problem here in terms of the first agenda of creativity in our general scheme? She was improvising already before encountering the free jazz perspective, but it was just to try out the sound for tracing her improvisation to write the score. But the visualization of her imagination, the score, was casting her into a time frame that limited musical invention. This prison even acted on her (but was more subtle) when she was not restricted in her music by any time signature or measure line. By writing the score, her original imagination was reduced to the notation, and tracing the score for the next sound gradually distorted the originality. She trapped herself in the notation by ‘counting’ it. The critical concept here is that of time. The time is a given parameter of a score that tells her when pitches, dynamics, and articulations have to take place. There was no choice for onset time. Let us investigate the walls in the time concept. How do we determine time? It is usually determined by quarter notes, time signature, or measure lines as the given space of the score’s parameter. Where could this be a problem? In the compositional process, the musical creator clearly is urged to make, to construct music. But to what extent does he or she make the musical objects, notes, pauses, etc.? For Joomi it is no problem to record the pitches for piano or another pitch-specifying instrument because the pitches could be shown with the exact information on the staff. What happens with the time parameters, onset, duration, tempo, and agogics? Is there any difference in their making? If they have to be selected in analogy to pitch selection, this means that time points are given and must be imagined on the time space defined by the score. Joomi reports that adding time attributes to the score imprisoned her creativity in the sense that referring to time limited her to counting. She did not experience time except in that mathematical abstraction of counting. Time was reduced to a parameter of mathematical detachment. However, time in music is not a computer trigger slot; it is the essential access to existence of music when performed. The anchoring of notes in real time transforms symbolic objects into physically and psychologically expressed and perceived realities. Counting trigger slots prevents the composer and even more the performer from accessing this existential dimension of time. Joomi always believed that classical education as a composer had framed her creation of time to the abstraction of counting. Again, she had composed in various contemporary styles including many pieces using no certain rhythmic patterns. But, the counting habits still exist when a composer writes and traces the score, and this obviously has its effect when the composer creates what comes next. It was only in the context of free jazz improvisation that this wall against creativity became the core concern of her compositional power. So what then can be the opening of this wall of counting time in the compositional construction? The critical wall character here was to understand what “making” time slots means. In Western art music, it is reduced to that selection as discussed above. But in the free jazz paradigm that she was taught by
254
23 The CD Passionate Message
Fig. 23.1. First page of the sketch of the composition American Carnival.
Guerino, the making is more embodied: The dancing hands are not following an abstract score parameter but take the full responsibility of making time— and other musical attributes. Time is not given here, but we invent it, point to it, and define it by our whole body’s gestural utterance bringing the music to existence. For example, the movement of the hands plays an important role in shaping time. They do not have to follow a time-line or given patterns, but they could determine time like a clock’s pointer does. It is remarkable that Albert Einstein answered the question, what is time: “It is the movement of
23.1 The General Background of This Production
255
the clock’s pointer.” In free jazz improvisation, our hands and their fingers are the pointers of time. Joomi learned that the constraint of counting time could
Fig. 23.2. First page of the score of the composition American Carnival.
256
23 The CD Passionate Message
be overcome by replacing the selection of time points in the score by gestural utterance that, instead of selecting, shapes time. Her hands learned to shape the body of time. This also means that her improvisation now was extended to this shaping activity, to the very sensitive making of musical existence instead of triggering given slots of an imposed time prison. As an audible consequence, Joomi’s composition is now brought to a maturity, where she has freely and sensibly shaped the body of the composition’s time. Only then is it inscripted into a score format—see Figure 23.1 for a first sketch of the composition American Carnival, and Figure 23.2 for the score’s first page. In a first understanding of this change of strategy, one would argue that Joomi’s approach is that of somebody who improvises and records this performance with a MIDI piano system to produce a score from the MIDI file. This is a wrong conclusion. In fact, this composer uses sketches of melodic and harmonic structures, as written down on score paper, and also involves many compositional techniques such as forms, limited number of repetitions, returning materials, and systematic developing themes. But these traces are not meant to determine their implantation in time-critical dimensions. These dimensions are added later in the time-shaping making of fully existing music. What she wrote down on the paper are constituents of a composition standing as the ingredients of a culinary recipe, and then the action of cooking is taking place on another level of compositional realization. 23.1.3 Guerino’s Improvisational Approach Guerino is a free jazz improviser who developed his art after an initial training from jazz schools in Zurich. He then developed his own approach within the tradition of Cecil Taylor, stressing the pianistic techniques of two-handed clusterings and the dancing paradigm of gestural construction of the body of time. In this project, he decided to perform in a somewhat more specific setup. Before joining in a duo improvisation with Joomi, to be discussed later in this chapter, Guerino would take Joomi’s compositions and give his musical comments in his language. He therefore analyzed her compositional structures and inserted them into his improvisation as reference points and germs for his own unfolding gestures. Here we want to focus on the question concerning creative strategies followed by Guerino in his meditation on Joomi’s musical germs. What are the creative problems here? The starting point for Guerino is that he usually does not want to rely on any given material. The creativity of a free jazz musician is exactly what can be done without any composed material. So the problem is clearly this: How can one improvise with the full responsibility of a free jazz musician, but referring to a compositional material? This is evidently a conflictual setup and should not work at all. So let us inspect the walls surrounding this critical concept of free jazz improvisation based upon
23.1 The General Background of This Production
257
given compositional material. Recall that Joomi’s solution of the time problem was to make time, to shape it instead of selecting time slots in a counting action. Can we do the same here? With time, the solution was somehow straightforward in that Joomi had to throw away the given score time and had to make time from scratch—she had no “time material” to refer to. This is true, but also somehow too simple to be realized since she, in fact, had to shape time of something. Her ideas, pitch, dynamics, and articulation were given, and she had to create the time for these objects. So yes, she had something to which time would be associated. Could Guerino use this approach to insert Joomi’s compositional material into his free jazz shaping? Well, Guerino not only had to shape time of given material, but he also had to shape the material as such and not simply copy Joomi’s material. So shaping the material is the critical concept here. And the wall that would be decisive would be the question of how to open this material to the free jazz approach. Can we take a given material and transform it into free jazz? This reminds us of a remarkable scene in the documentary movie All the Notes on Cecil Taylor [41]. Taylor explains his way of giving existence to musical structures. He first plays one octave of a C-major scale mechanically upward, stressing that he now “copies” the abstract note data defining such a scale. In a second run, he replays the scale, but now hits the key of every note with great insistence and passion. He identifies himself with the keys he is hitting: He no longer “cites” some abstract material but “rides the horse,” as free jazz musicians say. This time he plays his music, the external reference is abolished and replaced by the full responsibility Taylor takes for what he is doing. So what is the difference between these two approaches to the C-major scale? Isn’t it a matter of psychology without audible trace? No, the difference is that from the moment when you turn those notes into your property, which you may place how you want, you are free to shape whatever you wish to do. But then, is it still that given material? Couldn’t you have taken anything? The point is that “riding the horse” is not “inventing the horse.” Although you shape the horse, you are not acting in an empty space. The horse is there, and riding it also depends upon what it is. And what it is not. Playing the C-major scale in Taylor’s approach means to sit on each note you play and to look around: What other notes can you find, what other order of the scale notes can you find and play, or look at notes outside the scale, investigating all what is not part of the scale, the conceptual skin of this material, treating it as if it were a body, looking at this body’s surface: alterate one note, varying the notes’ durations, investigating this material’s position in the infinite variety of possible other musical objects. This is, of course, not independent of the given material, but it does not simply replicate its formal definition. It appropriates it, deforms it, and explores its anatomy as if it were a horse. The concrete action to be taken to perform such appropriation is to embody the “inherited” material in a gestural utterance and to replace the ob-
258
23 The CD Passionate Message
jective data by their gestural making, the responsible making of those sounds. Now, such making then pertains to an elastic paradigm, and Joomi’s material is embedded in a gestural variety and can as such be deformed according to gestural dynamics. Those notes are now endpoints of dancing fingers, and it is this dance that, although initiated by the material data, takes control over what is going to be played. The pianist’s hands may now hesitate to hit the next key, they may resonate on a local gesture, they may reshape a gesture in its peak energy, and so on. The gestural vocabulary may also be infused by another dynamic paradigm, such as a stylistic coloring. It is important to distinguish this process from the classical method of citation or variation. Citation is not about riding the horse, but a method that takes the animal (or rather: its dead body), and places it into one’s musical context without any further interaction, like a touristic objet trouv´e. And variation is using citation in different colors and different techniques, so to speak. It is not meant to step outside the given material, to investigate the neighborhood beyond its skin.
23.2 Softening One’s Boundaries in Creativity Composition is a lonesome activity. The composer usually is not communicating his/her creative activity to others. It is a dialogue with oneself for two reasons: First, creativity in this domain follows a search for solutions of problems that cannot be communicated, or open questions that cannot be answered, and second, it is not clear whether any such communication could help solve the creative action as such. This is very different from creativity in an improvisational approach, where inspiration is shared with fellow musicians and creation is done in the incessant exchange of ideas in the making. This is also true for the improvisational solo, which can be understood as a dialogue with oneself1 . But it is different from the compositional auto-dialogue (not to be confused with a monologue) because it is one in the making of the music while playing, whereas the compositional situation resembles improvisation in slow motion2 . But the difference is significant, qualitative—composition is not merely slowing down improvisational processes. The compositional process usually does not happen in the performative presence, but “offline” in a mental layer where strategies and knowledge bases can be activated, which are inaccessible in improvisational presence. In Pierre Boulez’s Structures pour deux pianos [17, 18], for example, we see a huge calculation, also traced on tables for basic structures, chords, etc., and we know from Gy¨ orgy Ligeti’s analysis [67, 88] that these calculations also include auxiliary serial calculations not directly involving musical objects. The critical concept of this problem is the dialogue with oneself mentioned above. What are the walls here that should be opened? To begin with, the 1 2
Cecil Taylor shares this view. Arnold Schoenberg shares this view.
23.2 Softening One’s Boundaries in Creativity
259
“self” of such dialogue might be reviewed as a space of mental activity whose extension and function mode could be opened. Second, the nature of the inner dialogue has the potential for limited efficiency in that lonely endeavor. Let us first look at the wall of “self.” This is the identifier of a person, and is conceived as being an encapsulated entity that for Descartes defines one’s being: “cogito ergo sum.” I think therefore I am. The “I” is constituted by this thinking activity. And this thinking “I” is a closed internal space: It distinguishes one from all that is not one’s self, so there is a strict dichotomy: self versus non-self. The thinking “I” creates what is in myself and what is outside. This dichotomy is thought to be a strong characteristic for the constitution of the self. It is, however, not evident why an opening of one’s self should be a weakening. It could be that softening one’s boundaries expresses an even stronger self that would be able to integrate and absorb external determinants. The second wall, the inner dialogue’s efficiency, looks non-critical. Why should an inner dialogue be limited in its efficiency? The composer evidently has full access to his/her own knowledge, and it takes no time to communicate with oneself in this internal communication. But this seemingly positive characteristic of quasi-zero distance is not automatically advantageous. One can also be too near to oneself. So we are asked to rethink the effect of inner dialogue on the depth of compositional construction. When comparing the inner dialogue of a composer to the dialogue of an improviser with him/herself when performing, we detect that the latter has the sounding music in front of him/her, i.e. the musical dialogue is externalized and can be ‘observed.’ Although it is a dialogue with the self, the improviser’s object lives out there and can be looked at (well, rather: “heard at”) with due distance. This gives the object the possibility to resonate in its ambient space, to expand before it hits the self. This effect is not automatically achieved when thinking about one’s composition in a quiet inner cave without letting it resonate in itself before reaching the inner ear. The inner dialogue of the quiet composer simply lacks the space for its objects to unfold their musical body. They cannot be heard in the infinitesimal vicinity of the composer’s inner cave. One could compare this deficiency with the absence of a resonance body for a violin or a piano: The vibrating string needs resonance in space-time to unfold the sound’s body. 23.2.1 Embodied Creation and the Crisis of Contemporary Composition The concept of creativity is not a priori conditioned by the paradigm of embodiment, neither in the arts nor in the sciences. But musical creativity is related to the acoustical realization of whatever ideas and strategies—music is not complete without its performance. This is, however, not a proof that musical creativity is necessarily related to its performative embodiment. And this is the delicate point: Can musical creativity be disjoint from its embodied perspective?
260
23 The CD Passionate Message
Whereas it is a fact that the adjective “musical” must include the embodiment of an acoustical realization by musicians in performance, it is not clear whether the creative aspect of music necessarily relies on embodiment. Referring to our discussion of composition and improvisation in section 22.1, composition + improvisation = sounding music. Therefore creativity in music must rely on either composition or improvisation (or both), the latter including performance by definition. It is clear from our discussion in section 22.1 that creativity in improvisation must be embodied. So our question must focus on composition: Can musical creativity in composition be detached from embodiment? Of course, there are many ideas in composition that pertain to non-embodied categories, such as using Fibonacci’s sequence or dodecaphonic series, or the simple (but creative) setting of a cadence or modulation scheme. But we would hesitate to call them musical. Why? The question here is about the ontology of music, the modality of being in music. Let us first discuss a similar situation in physics, since this case is much simpler and also scientifically reflected. Physics is described by mathematical forms, but physical reality need not coincide with the reality of its formal description. The crucial example is Einstein’s concept of the velocity c of light. The characteristic statement of special relativity is that c is the highest possible velocity in physics. More precisely: It is the highest possible velocity for transfer of physical information. There are velocities in physics, e.g. the group velocity, that can be higher than c, but no physical information can be transferred at this speed. It is a mathematical velocity beyond physical reality. When looking at music, a similar situation can occur: Musical reality can be described by mathematical forms of whatever complexity. But these forms are not by themselves musical in their existence. For example, in Karlheinz Stockhausen’s Klavierst¨ uck IX, the initial four-note chord Q = {c♯, f ♯, g, c} is a musical fact, but the origin of this chord, being pitches number 2, 3, 10, 11 of the dodecaphonic series used in this composition, is not a musical fact when only this chord is played. The statement, “There exists a dodecaphonic series such that Q is the chord built from its pitches number 2, 3, 10, 11,” is not a musical but a (however simple) mathematical fact. Or if a musical motif has an inversion symmetry, this is not a musical fact until the inversion is evidenced and rendered as a musical process. We have discussed this topic in detail when describing the tonal modulations in Beethoven’s Hammerklavier Sonata [77, chapter 28.2, in particular chapter 28.2.5]. In other words, the thoughts behind a compositional result need not be obvious at all from this result. Coming back to the question of embodiment in musical creativity, this means that a creative construction need not be evident on the level of musical objects, processes, or gestures. It can boil down to invisibility when projected onto musical objects. This discussion implies that creativity in composition could take place without being visible in the musical output, i.e. without being embodied in the performative body of the music’s “sounding moved forms,” to speak with the famous words of Eduard Hanslick [49]. Hanslick’s definition of music is
23.2 Softening One’s Boundaries in Creativity
261
surprisingly precise for understanding our argument: Music is not forms but sounding moved forms. The forms as such are pre-musical, and their evidence only arises when they are moved qua sound, when they are embodied. In this spirit, musical creativity in composition must have its faithful reflection in embodiment. A compositional creation that is invisible in the embodied musical utterance is irrelevant, its existence is not musical. It is not astonishing that many distinctively creative composers and improvisers, such as Beethoven, Busoni, Monk, Taylor, Coltrane, etc., are known to have composed at their instruments and in a quasi-improvisational process; see in particular our discussion of Beethoven’s sonata, op. 109, in chapter 26. This fact is not so strongly related to the individuals that we see composing as to the embodiment they can communicate by their living gestures. It is a common mistake to believe that it is the unique individuality and person that fascinates with the great composers. We argue that it is much more their unique stamp of creativity in its embodiment that is responsible for their deep impact. In the music video Burning Poles, Taylor gives a fascinating lesson on this fact in the first piece, where he only moves around the piano and communicates his creative musicality through a dance of virtually silent gestures. This insight might be viewed as a highly intellectual result that would not be understood or even not be relevant for common music practice, but it is astonishing how fundamentally relevant this is when we look at popular music. When we observe the shape of embodiment in, say, pop music, it is prominently focused on the lead singer. He or she personifies the musical ideas as an intensely moving body with a characteristic gestural language. The audience’s access to pop music is mainly channeled through the lead signer’s gestural dance, Elvis Presley’s swinging hips, Michael Jackson’s moon walk, and Mick Jagger’s running hysteria are keys to understanding their music which, if reduced to its symbolic abstraction, would crash to trivialities. In view of these facts and findings, it is advisable for composers to create their works in an intimate relationship with their embodiment, and not to trust abstract formulas more than as hints and initiators of gestural embodiment. Contemporary composition should review its connection to embodiment, its creation of a body of time where the music, whenever it’s made and performed, should be a living one. The ideal performer should know that it is good to enjoy the music perfectly played like a machine without any mistakes, but if one wants to pursue the human being’s imaginations and deep expressions in higher dimensions, it is essential to be the one who creates and controls actively, who is responsible for what he/she makes, and who inserts a living gesture as the owner of what is performed.
262
23 The CD Passionate Message
23.3 The Problem of Creativity in a Dense Cultural Heritage of Compositions Composing contemporary art music is a big challenge. It is trapped between the hopeless insight that “everything has been said” and the powerless perspective that “anything goes.” Both are wrong: Most of the possible sets of notes and pauses have not been composed, and most of the possibilities would not sound like music anyway. But the young composer nevertheless feels lost between all sorts of New Music, from New Simplicity to New Complexity, from Noise Music to Just Tuning Archaisms, and so on: For all that still is possible, there is no orientation. And there is a big fear that one might be judged as lacking originality, of writing in some already recognized style. Being original is a conditio sine qua non: a composer wants to be an inventor, at least if his/her work is not just for commercial output. Moreover, the music industry has radically changed its communication and business interface since Internetbased music distribution has taken over the channels of global distribution. The global village is omnipresent and never asleep. How and why should a young composer create anything original—and eventually acclaimed—in such a hysterical environment? This is the problem we want to tackle in a creative way. The critical concept is that of an original composition. So let us think about its walls. We want to address two walls here: originality and the object itself, the composition. 23.3.1 First Wall: Composition, an Object? Let us start with the composition as such. It is that thing that was addressed in the two initial limit points. It seems unavoidable that the work of a composer would be such a thing, a score. But all music philosophers agree with Theodor W. Adorno that music is only complete when performed. For an improviser, it is evident and unavoidable to have his/her work embodied in performance. For a composer, this aspect must be an integral part of what composition means, too. Therefore, any reduction of a work to its objective score level is an error. Nice scores are paper music, not music. Writing music means writing for a living embodiment, not for abstract information—see also section 23.2.1, where we have discussed embodied composition in modern Western art music. This is, however, not an easy task because Western art music has no culture of the living composition; such an aspect lies beyond professional education. And it is not about expressing the individual person, the composer’s subjectivity. It is a mistake to believe that subjectivity guarantees living works: Virtual subjects are quite frequent, no less than living dead. Embodiment is another category. Glenn Gould has embodied Johann Sebastian Bach’s Wohltemperiertes Klavier without any reduction to subjectivity, but incorporating a divine puppet that moves sounding forms, he makes the compositional mechanics visible and audible.
23.3 The Problem of Creativity in a Dense Cultural Heritage of Compositions
263
In Joomi Park’s composition American Carnival, she has created a tango dance rhythm in a complex contemporary music composition. This dimension of her composition cannot be understood from the score but must be added by the performer as an essential part of the work. This work’s score is a collection of frozen dance gestures, its symbols similar to Laban’s dance symbols, but they only capture limit points of dance gestures, as it is not possible to understand dance from a Laban score. In other words, the first wall opening would be that we question the object character of the composition and extend it to a scenario for living embodiments. As explained in section 22.1, a composition is not sounding music, but a command structure for the production of sounding music. This command structure must explicitly incite the embodied performance. To be clear, this is not an enrichment of the classical performance commands, such as accelerando, legato, or textual commands such as con amore. It is about understanding what it means to make it yours, and then creating a new meaning of what is performed as the owner of the music (see section 23.1.3). This approach is radically different from the production of paper music and can enable creations that open an existentiality of music not covered by Western art music tradition. 23.3.2 Second Wall: Originality The second wall, originality, is a strong challenge for young composers. They are subjected to a chaotic system of validations of works. Their incessant fear is to be judged as composing in the style of some acclaimed other composer. “Your composition sounds like Stravinsky” is a killer argument; originality is an absolute must, so it is not by coincidence that we have the concept of New Music for Western art music in the twentieth and twenty-first century, a concept invented by the journalist Paul Bekker in 1919 and focusing on originality. It is well-known that all young composers who write complex but agreeable music (yes, this exists!) are afraid of being downgraded as being irrelevant to the development of music, of being unoriginal, since original music is “by definition” unaccessible and must be conquered with pains. In a number of definitions, see chapter 18, the concept of creativity has been associated with originality, and therefore opening the wall of originality is essential to creativity. Originality means to be at the origin of music, to build something new at the source. Compositional creativity should approach that origin. This requirement is no doubt justified: Who would want to compose music that has already been conceived, and to even copycat some other’s music? So the naive solution would be to just compose in a new formal system, and the problem is solved. But searching for such a niche of musical material is in vain. Composer Isabel Mundry, winner of a number of prestigious prizes, stresses that it would be a waste of energy to compose in the nineteenth subdivision of the octave as a variation of the eighteenth division that has already been used by some composer. Such formal extensions are not really original—they are variations of a known scheme. Instead, she stresses the corporeality of music, the embodiment
264
23 The CD Passionate Message
we discussed in section 23.3.1, a quality that is only being discovered in the present time by the contemporary music community. She works strongly interdisciplinary, interpenetrating dance with sound and literature, such as Heinrich ¨ von Kleist’s famous writing Uber das Marionettentheater. The search for originality therefore opens the question of the nature of such an origin. If the origin is just a new instance of a given scheme, the search was a failure. This type of search is built on the criterion of maximal originality: Nothing known should be used, no given scheme, and in the limit, one would look for the absolute original, avoiding anything known. This is obviously absurd since composition always uses a huge quantity of known structures and objects. The question “Which originality?” does not find its answer in the selection of unknown material, and this suggests a first opening of the second wall: What kind of origin are we looking for if not the origin of material choices? In section 23.3.1, we investigated the nature of a composition that would open the traditional object character of a score. And this was the extension of musical composition to the embodied living music-making. The question would then boil down to asking about the originality in this extended mode of existence. What is originality in the composition of embodied living musicmaking? Mundry in her approach stresses the interdisciplinary collaboration, integrating dance and literature with music. But music already knows and cultivates interdisciplinary efforts in, say, the classical opera and its paradigm of a “Gesamtkunstwerk” as propagated by Richard Wagner. Such an extension is not more than the accumulation of other materials from dance, litearture, etc. This cannot be the step we are looking for—it is just more of the same. It is evident that the opening of the wall of originality must transcend the material character of composition. This is the direction to be investigated. In fact, when analyzing Mundry’s approach, it turns out that it is the nonmaterial quality of embodiment and of intense interaction between artists and the audience—in other words, a gestural exchange of utterances—that characterize these new approaches. The situation has a parallel in biology: The search for an answer to what is life is being made by biochemistry. The genes, the DNA code, all of that is a strong effort, but it will never solve the question because it only deals with the material reality of life, not with life as it vibrates in love, emotions, sensibility, and vitality beyond the material reality. Hard science might also be a domain that misses the point of life. In music, the material investigation can be refined, supported by music technology, and refined to highly sophisticated material assemblies, but the living substance cannot be dissolved into these categories. More precisely, these categories are facticity and processuality. The dimension they are missing is the living vibration of gestures. It became clear that the innovative approach to composition in the embodied living music-making strongly relies on gestural categories. This is the point of Mundry’s approach. She bases her success on the virtuosic exchange of gestures. This is the spirit of Adorno’s philosophy of performance: heat-
23.3 The Problem of Creativity in a Dense Cultural Heritage of Compositions
265
ing up score material until those frozen gestures return to life from the score’s immobilized schemes. So how does the question of originality appear when reviewed under these new perspectives? How can originality be achieved in the vibrating realm of embodied gestural interaction? It is not a movement towards material origins, but toward the origins of gestural embodiment. What are original gestures? In the French philosophy of gestures, as described by Gilles Chˆ atelet and Maurice Merleau-Ponty [23, 97], original gestures are pre-semiotic entities that do not represent and encode given contents. The gestures that function as expressions of content are what French philosophers call “tamed gestures”—a degenerate derivative of the original ones. The latter do not represent but incite new gestures, their realm stands for themselves, and as such they generate other gestures, they are the vibration of living entities, they are elastic force fields whose material carriers vanish with respect to their dynamic pulsation. Being original in this realm then means to not mimic others’ gestures, to not mickeymouse in empty imitations. If a composer acts in this dimension, he/she must free him/herself from those borrowed gestures and set free one’s own gestures. Embodiment in gestures then becomes a challenge that is only successful when one has reached the state of being in complete autonomy, if one’s gestures are embodying the self and not imitating some other’s gestural utterances.
24 The Escher Theorem
The Escher Theorem was first proved and discussed in the context of mathematical gesture theory [84, 87]. We shall review the theorem here as a case study relating to explicit strategies for creativity. This theorem was first applied to describe creative strategies in free jazz, see [85].
24.1 A Short Review of the Escher Theorem 24.1.1 Gestures and Hypergestures Let us first give the definition of a gesture and recall for this purpose the classical definition of medieval theologist Hugues de Saint Victor (in Latin): “Gestus est motus et figuratio membrorum corporis, ad omnem agendi et habendi modum.” The definition suggests a configuration of parts, a topological space where the gesture’s curve moves, and an abstract skeleton that formally frames the configuration. We therefore refer to two mathematical structures: (1) the category T of topological spaces and continuous maps, and (2) the category D of directed graphs (digraphs) and morphisms. We then need these constructions: First, denoting by I the closed unit interval I = [0, 1] ⊂ R of real numbers 0 ≤ t ≤ 1, the set I@X of continuous − → maps f : I → X into a topological space X generates a directed graph X , 1 whose arrows are the maps f ∈ I@X, whose vertices are the elements of X, and the head and tail of f are hf = f (1), tf = f (0). With this, we have the following definition of a gesture (see Figure 24.1): − → Definition 1 A gesture is a morphism g : Γ → X . The digraph Γ is called the gesture’s skeleton, the space X is called its space, and the curve configuration in X defined by g is called the gesture’s body. 1
We use the standard notation X@Y of sets of morphisms f : X → Y from object X to object Y in a category.
G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 24, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
267
268
24 The Escher Theorem
Fig. 24.1. A gesture, with skeleton and body.
This definition is also intuitive: A gesture is a body of curves in a space, which are formally combined by the background skeleton. Let us now focus on the power of this simple definition. It is a seemingly poor description of what is going on in the embodiment of such a gesture in the concrete physical shape of hands. That representation only describes movements of fingertips, and not of the entire hand (see Figure 24.2). But the problem is not only one of realistic representation of body movement. The piano pedagogue Renate Wieland [120] says: “The sound contact is the target of the embracing gesture, the touch is Fig. 24.2. A tip gesture, which neglects so to speak the gesture within the the hand’s real shape. gesture.” She stresses that much more happens when fingers interact with piano keys: the tactile action germinates a gesture within a gestures, a gesture of gestures. We are challenged to incorporate this inner life of gestures into our geometric setup. − → This is achieved by a simple observation: If we consider the set Γ @ X of all gestures with skeleton Γ and space X, this space is a canonical topology, which − → is intuitively understood as follows: A neighborhood of a gesture g : Γ → X − → is the set of all gestures k : Γ → X , whose body points are near to those of g at all parameter values of the occurring curves. This new topological space
24.1 A Short Review of the Escher Theorem
269
− → is denoted by Γ @ X. Therefore, the gestures of the given skeleton and space are themselves points within a topological space, and nothing can hinder us − → to build gestures, which now have the space Γ @ X instead of X. But such a − → gesture h : ∆ → Γ @ X is effectively a gesture of gestures! We call this type of gesture a hypergesture. Let us explain this far-reaching generalization. A first example shows how real body shapes can be built by hypergestures (see Figure 24.3). We first consider gestures with the loop digraph 1 as their skeleton and R3 as space. Their body therefore is a circle, i.e. a closed curve in 3D space. When building hypergestures of such circles, we have bodies of moved circles. In the special − → case of the same loop skeleton, a hypergesture h : 1 → 1 @ R3 is just a knot surface, namely the trace of the small circle being moved along a big circle.
Fig. 24.3. A hypergesture, built from a loop of loops in 3D space.
The remarkable thing about this first small example is that time does not intervene here; this hypergesture is a purely spatial one. This means that the general setup enables a rich language describing spatial shapes. Of course, time is also one of the specifications that we can introduce here. The time domain is specified as being one of the topological space coordinates, and it becomes obvious now that time is (in general) a completely independent specification from those curve parameters. A more complex example is shown in Figure 24.4. This one is a hypergesture in time, built on a three-armed hypergesture of circles. It is now evident that a hypergesture, which represents the real movement of a human body, is easily realized starting from the frame skeleton instead of the tree-armed skeleton. We show this in the manikin in the same figure. Remark 12 The concept of a hypergesture is a huge generalization of what in algebraic topology is know as homotopy. Intuitively, two shapes in a given space are homotopic to each other if they can be deformed into each other by a one-parameter family of intermediate shapes. For example, looking at our example in Figure 24.4, the movement through time of that three-armed shape
270
24 The Escher Theorem
Fig. 24.4. A hypergesture showing a moving body in time, and also the idea of realizing human body movements by use of adequate frame skeletons.
is a homotopy between the initial and the final positions of that shape. So this hypergesture of three-armed gestures is a homotopy. Gestures of gestures are therefore generalized homotopies. 24.1.2 The Escher Theorem The Escher Theorem is the following, seemingly inoffensive, statement, which essentially states that iterated hypergestures2 can be built in any order of the involved directed graphs: Theorem 1 [84, proposition 4.1] Let Γ1 , Γ2 , . . . Γn be n digraphs, X a topological space, and π a permutation of the set {1, 2, . . . n}, element of the symmetric group Sn . Then there is a canonical3 homeomorphism (i.e. a bijection that conserves all topological structures) − → − → − → ∼ − → − → − → Γ1 @ Γ2 @ . . . Γn @ X → Γπ(1) @ Γπ(2) @ . . . Γπ(n) @ X. This does not mean that the hypergestures in the space to the left are the same as those in the space to the right, but there is a one-to-one correspondence among these hypergestures that is perfectly compatible with all topological relations among neighborhoods. 2
Iterated hypergesture spaces are defined by → − → − → − → − → − → − Γ1 @ Γ2 @ . . . Γn @ X = Γ1 @ (Γ2 @ . . . (Γn @ X) . . .).
3
In mathematics “canonical” means directly deduced by the given structures.
24.1 A Short Review of the Escher Theorem
271
Fig. 24.5. Bottom: The first species Fux counterpoint exhibits two melody lines: the cantus firmus (lower melody, c.f.) and the discantus, upper melody.
Let us give a musical example from first species Fux theory of counterpoint. It considers two voices, punctus contra punctum. There are two melodic lines, the cantus firmus (c.f.) and the discantus, as shown at the bottom of Figure 24.5. There are two readings of the term “punctus contra punctum”: According to the common ‘vertical’ understanding, the discant ‘point’ (the upper tone at a given onset in the example) is set against the cantus firmus ‘point’ (the lower tone at a given onset in the example). This must always be a consonant interval (prime, minor third, major third, fifth, minor sixth, major sixth). The more adequate, but less known, interpretation is the ‘horizontal’ one: The ‘point’ is a defined interval at a given onset time, whereas the ‘counter-point’ to this is the subsequent interval [102]. This makes more sense since the compositional tension is not vertical, but horizontal. We compose in time and not only in pitch. Counterpoint is a theory about the logic of interval sequences in time. If the composer does not think about the horizontal deployment, he/she does not really care about how the music will be played. See sections 11.5, 11.6 for more details. Whatever the interpretation, the result is this double melodic configuration, whose vertical or horizontal genealogy is, however, no longer retraceable, i.e., the listener or reader of a given contrapuntal composition cannot tell from that data how it was constructed: vertically or horizontally: The result is neutral.
272
24 The Escher Theorem
When admitting continuous extensions4 of discrete sequences of gestures, if we allow the horizontal (in time direction) continuous extension of the discrete sequence of a two-voice counterpoint melody and simultaneously the vertical (in pitch class direction) continuous extension of the two discrete melodies, then the entire configuration looks like a tubular shape, as shown in Figure 24.5 above the bottom score. The upper left reading is then the common interpretation: connecting two melodies by a curve of melodies in the pitch class circle domain. The upper right reading is the more essential one, showing the time-oriented curve of intervals in pitch class space. In terms of hypergestures, the left one is a loop of lines, whereas the right one is a line of loops. The Escher Theorem lets these two hypergestures correspond to each other. This elementary example shows that the interpretation of a complex shape may give rise to very different readings in terms of skeletons and bodies of hypergestures. This generates a dramatic hot spot in the interpretational activity, which drives the free understanding of musical shapes. We have to stress the adjective “free” here, since in a standard interpretation only one view is cultivated. It is never a line of loops, but must be strictly read as a loop of lines. Standardization is a strong poison against creativity: Its etymology from “stand hard” is speaking and the softness of interpretation is given no chance. But if we want to open up walls, they must be softened, and this is also a strong argument against standards. They often kill creativity because their hard-wired appearance forbids asking for walls and their limiting power. This hot spot is based upon the n! permutations of skeletal digraph sequences that generate the Fig. 24.6. Maurits Cor− → − → − → nelis Escher’s Belvedere hypergesture space Γπ(1) @ Γπ(2) @ . . . Γπ(n) @ X. These permutational variants are ways of breakas an illustration of the bifurcation of neutral ing the delicate equilibrium of an uninterpreted shape. image regions into in- Each permutation generates a completely different compatible perspectives. hypergestural setup. One could view these departures © Cordon Art B.V. - from the neutral cusp toward a variety of interpreBaarn - Holland. tational sinks as a bifurcation process: The neutral trajectory of perception explodes into n! interpretations, perspectives, or ways of handling one and the same neutral datum. Such a bifurcational process is best illustrated by a work of Maurits Cornelis Escher (see Figure 24.6), where the neutral cusp region of the graphic (here the horizontal yellow strip between the two levels of the building) is split into different, mutually exclusive sink perspectives. This is the reason we coin the above theorem “Escher Theorem.” It is evident that such a bifurcation process is a strong argument for creative decisions. We come back to this topic in section 24.3. 4
There are cognitive arguments for such extenions, see [85, chapter 8.3 ].
24.2 The Escher Theorem and Creativity in Free Jazz
273
24.2 The Escher Theorem and Creativity in Free Jazz Before we discuss the general power of the Escher theorem in the process of creativity, we should add a theme that is very characteristic in improvised music: creativity in free jazz. The Escher theorem has concrete musical application to the crucial but difficult question5 of creativity in free jazz and in other free improvisation contexts. Some of the biographies that have been written about the important figures in jazz and free jazz, such as John Coltrane, Ornette Coleman, and Cecil Taylor, prove that creativity is not an ineffable subject and is pedagogically accessible. David Borgo, Derek Bailey, and other experts have worked on this topic and agree that teaching “the making” asks for and generates another pedagogics than the simple transfer of stored works of art. Following Borgo’s excellent book [14], the central point resides in “the attitude projected by the instructor and on how (s)he frames the creative moment.” We believe that the following ideas are helpful in that task. Let us now apply the theorem in
Fig. 24.7. The creative perspectives between the musicians of a trio.
the concrete musical situation of a trio, comprising a pianist, a bassist, and a drummer. 5
Our application matters above all because we know of those mumbo-jumbo “theories” about inspiration and transpiration and drugs and meditation and other far-out sorcery of self-destruction. We have been in the free jazz “business” for over forty years and have enjoyed a broad spectrum of creative musicians and, h´elas, of tragic musicians.
274
24 The Escher Theorem
The three musicians are involved in hypergestural perspectives in the following ways. In a specific hypergestural space, each musician momentarily chooses a permutation π of his/her directed graphs (relating to his/her topological space). In Figure 24.7, this is graphically represented by a named symbolic figure (pianist, bassist, drummer) and a short, thick arrow that points to a determined height of that figure, which symbolizes the permutation π. This choice is also a function of the musical partner, to which the attention is directed. Therefore every musician is provided with two such short, thick arrows. Next, each self-perspective is taken as a starting position to point to one of the partners. This partner then is also viewed under a specific permutation of the partner’s sequence of hypergestural directed graphs. This is shown by a long, thinner arrow pointing to the partner’s body at a determined height. There are twelve arrows in total, all symbolizing selections of permutational perspectives that relate to the hypergestural “towers” of gestural utterances made by the musicians. Although this configuration is quite abstract, it gives precise hints about the special types of attention and awareness that musicians become skilled in through interaction with other musical personalities. It is also essential here that such perspectives may change at any moment during the musical interaction. This strategy prevents musicians from falling into groove traps that very often hinder inexperienced free jazz musicians from inventing creative trajectories. Although the general idea is clear, the question arising from Cavaill`es’s colorful concept of “throwing around gestures in the band” is still too abstract. How should one throw one’s (hyper)gestural action at a fellow’s configuration? This question relates to the precise meaning of the longer arrows that connect pairs of musicians in Figure 24.7. The situation is this: For a ‘sender’ musician s and a ‘receiver’ musician r, we are given two hypergestural towers of directed graphs, referring to the basic topological spaces, respectively. By the choice of the two permutations πs , πr , one for the sender, one for the receiver, we are given the two directed graphs ∆ = Γπs (1) , Φ = Γπr (1) , which define the gestural surface structure, namely those that stand to the left-most position, i.e., Γπ(1) − → − → − → in the hypergesture skeleton of type Γπ(1) @ Γπ(2) @ . . . Γπ(n) @ X, and we set − → − → Y = Γπ(2) @ . . . Γπ(n) @ X for the remainder. So we are given these surface − → − → structures ∆ @ Ys , Φ @ Yr , where these musicians’ momentary hypergestures are located. Musically speaking, the sender musician throws his hypergesture to the receiver’s hypergesture. This means that the sender’s gestural surface is projected onto the receiver’s. For example, the pianist makes a hypergesture, whose surface gesture imitates or projects into the drummer’s surface gesture. From this example, we see the importance of the skillful process of selecting and manipulating a given surface gesture. When altering the surface gesture of either sender or receiver, the projection may look quite different; even if the
24.2 The Escher Theorem and Creativity in Free Jazz
275
sender’s surface is unaltered, the mere change of perspective onto the receiver (“line of loops or loop of lines”) creates new options. Let us now make precise such a “projection” between surface gestures. In mathematics, the projection of a given structure into another structure is called a morphism—a map conserving relevant structures6 . Our situation would − → therefore be to define a “throw morphism” τ : gs → gr , where gs ∈ ∆ @ Ys , gr ∈ − → Φ @ Yr are the two present (hyper)gestures of sender s and receiver r. Such a throw is defined as follows (see Figure 24.8):
Fig. 24.8. The mathematical definition of a throw morphism between two hypergestures.
The directed graph ∆ of gs is morphed into the graph Φ of the receiver, while the topological space Ys is mapped into the space Yr in such a way that the diagram shown in Figure 24.8 commutes. In this diagram, the right vertical arrow maps curves in Ys to corresponding curves in Yr . This throw construction defines morphisms between (hyper)gestures and therefore the category H of (hyper)gestures. Such a setup opens a rich conceptual framework, which enables an explicit discussion of interpretational communication between free jazz (and other gesturally creative) musicians. Let us now discuss the general method that enables creativity in free improvisation in light of our theory of creativity. 6
From Greek morph´e = form.
276
24 The Escher Theorem
24.3 Applying the Escher Theorem to Open Walls of Critical Concepts The bifurcational chain giving rise to a hypergestural tower in the interpretation of a neutral phenomenon is a strong tool for creativity. The important fact added to such a tool by the Escher Theorem is its possibility to change the bifurcation without changing the neutral setup—to change the perspective on the same substance. Why is this bifurcational change a tool for creativity? It is evident that it is an inspiration to view or hear things differently, as explained in the previous section. But we want also understand this tool more precisely in relation to our theory of creativity. The Escher Theorem compares spaces of (hyper)gestures of two types: the − → − → − → original type (for the identical permutation Id) X(Id) = Γ1 @ Γ2 @ . . . Γn @ X − → − → − → and any other type X(π) = Γπ(1) @ Γπ(2) @ . . . Γπ(n) @ X associated with a permutation π (see Figure 24.9).
Fig. 24.9. The Escher Theorem states that the (hyper)gesture spaces X(π) for permutations π in the symmetric group Sn are all isomorphic as topological spaces. Our figure shows a (hyper)gesture in the space of the identical permutation Id and its corresponding (hyper)gestures in other spaces.
When thinking about critical concepts, the original space X(Id) is such a concept, and this hypergesture has been defined using the original ordering of skeleta Γ1 , Γ2 , . . . Γn . The wall here is this given ordering. There is no reason to put it into question and to think of another possible construction. For example, in the interpretation of first species counterpoint as shown in left half of Figure 24.5, the counterpoint as a hypergesture was given as a hypergesture connecting the cantus firmus line with the discantus line in consonant distances within the pitch class circle. This was the classical way that punctus contra punctum was conceived. This wall, however, blocks a deeper understanding of the idea in contra. What is against what? Is it discantus
24.3 Applying the Escher Theorem to Open Walls of Critical Concepts
277
against cantus firmus? But why “against”? Everything here is set in consonances. Following the work of Klaus-J¨ urgen Sachs [102], we have opened this wall by reinterpreting such counterpoint with the Escher Theorem as being a line of consonant intervals, not an intervallic line coupling (right half of Figure 24.5). The difficulty in this wall is that there is no a priori evidence for other constructions of hypergestures. Fact 1 The Escher Theorem is a tool that opens up reinterpretations of concepts by use of alternative constructions. This bifurcation flips the original construction to a permuted one with respect to the underlying skeletons. Psychologically speaking, it is the same situation as with Escher’s art works. One would not try to reinterpret one’s perspective until some hints are given to try another perspective. In the simplest situation, Escher draws convex geometric shapes, but all of a sudden one is led to reinterpret them as being concave. In the sophisticated art works, such as Concave and Convex or in Belvedere (Figure 24.6), both perspectives are confronted as bifurcational splittings of the neutral middle layer. The Escher-induced flipping is also shown in Figure 24.10, where the hypergestural construction, a three-armed hypergesture of circles (see also Figure 24.4), can also be seen as a circle of a three-armed graph.
Fig. 24.10. Left: a circle of a three-armed graph; right: a three-armed hypergesture of circles.
We have shown that the Escher Theorem is an excellent tool for new strategies in musical creativity, for a creative style of thinking in nonconservative ways that allow you to see hidden perspectives of musical objects without stepping into chaotic randomness. Remark 13 So far, we have stressed the bifurcation between the two orderings of two skeletons Γ1 , Γ2 . The case of a general permutation of n skeletons is,
278
24 The Escher Theorem
however, no more difficult for the following reason: Recall that every permutation π of the n natural numbers 1, 2, . . . n, n > 1, is a product of transpositions (exchanges) (i, i+1) of a pair of successive numbers i, i+1. So we may effectively restrict our discussion to the situation of a pair of skeleta Γ1 , Γ2 and a topologi− → − → ∼ − → − → cal space X, where the Escher Theorem states that Γ1 @ Γ2 @ X → Γ2 @ Γ1 @ X.
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
In [19], Pierre Boulez describes a compositional strategy called analyse cr´eatrice, creative analysis, which is opposed to what he calls “sterile academic” analysis in that the analytical results are used as germs to create new compositions. Before discussing Boulez’s ideas in detail, we should stress that his procedure transcends the purely analytical or compositional activities: He proposes a coherent double activity that includes both analysis and composition. This means that our own discourse in this chapter will deal with both, analysis and composition, the latter more specifically realized by use of the music composition software RUBATO [75].
25.1 Boulez’s Idea of a Creative Analysis Let us explain the practical consequences of Boulez’s strategy for the analytical and compositional efforts1 . Anne Boissi`ere [15] has given a concise summary of Boulez’s ideas on creative analysis, which comprise these core items: The analysis focuses more on the limits of the given composition than on the historical adequacy. These limits open up what has not been said, what was omitted or overlooked by that composer. This hermeneutic work is not driven to deduce a new composition as a special case of what has been recognized (deduction), nor is it meant to help build the new composition by a passage from the particular to the general (induction). Referring to Gilbert Simondon’s philosophical reflections [106], the creative movement consists of the opening of a topological neighborhood of the given analysis within a space of analytical parameters. In such a space, analytical structures similar to the given one are selected and eventually used as germs for the construction of new compositions. This ‘horizontal’ movement is called “transduction” by Simondon. In this transduction process, what Boulez calls the composer’s gesture, is the movement toward the creation of new compositions, which share precisely 1
For a more philosophical discussion of this approach, we refer to [82, ch. 7].
G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 25, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
279
280
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
those analytical structures reflecting the given analysis. More concretely, we take the analysis of the given work and make a number of “small” value changes to the analytical parameters. For example, if we have exhibited a set of pitch inversion symmetries that govern the given work, we may extend that set and include also time inversion symmetries (retrograde). Or if we have recognized that the voices of the different instruments are derived by some systematic procedure, e.g. time expansions (dilations) plus transpositions from a leading voice, then we may add more instruments and apply the same procedure, e.g. further time expansions (dilations) plus transpositions to define these added voices. This creative gesture—building new works from the transgression of the analytical structure discovered in the given work—is what Boissi`ere calls a detonation. It is precisely this act of breaking the given structures and stepping into unknown neighborhoods that characterizes Boulez’s concept of an open work. Boulez’s approach is visibly akin to our concept of creativity. Boulez’s creative analysis takes the given work as the critical concept in our theory and then inspects its walls with the analytical efforts. The open work is exactly this analytical search for walls where the given work might be limited. The creative act then would consist in the action of opening those walls and stepping to new compositional paths. To our knowledge, these ambitious claims have not been backed by concrete examples: How should and would such a strategy work in detail? This is what we have accomplished in a formal (mathematical) setup and on the level of computer-aided composition and what we want to discuss in this chapter. In view of Boulez’s poetical text, such an enterprise cannot be more than a first proposal. But we believe that it could open a fruitful discourse on the role of creativity in the dialectic between analysis and composition. In this sense, our approach is not a thesis but a detailed experiment following Boulez’s ideas. It is, therefore, completely logical to pursue the trajectory to its completion: to the construction of a full-fledged composition2 . Our choice of Boulez’s Structures is not random; it relates to the prominent role that this composition has played in the development of serialism. This is also confirmed by the fact that Gy¨ orgy Ligeti has published a very careful analysis of Structures, part Ia. Ligeti’s investigation [67] is neutral and precise, but it abounds with strong judgments on the work’s compositional and aesthetic qualities. Therefore, our experimental application of creative analysis to Structures is not by chance. The very success (or failure) of the serial method has been related to this composition, which was not only one of Boulez’s sucesses, but also a turning point in his compositional development. 2
It should however be noted that such a creative analysis had been applied in the case of Beethoven’s op. 106 [71] before we knew about Boulez’s idea. The present approach is somewhat more dramatic, since we shall now apply Boulez’s idea to two of his own works, namely Structures [17, 18].
25.1 Boulez’s Idea of a Creative Analysis
281
In view of Boulez’s principle of creative analysis, when applied to his compositional turning point in the Structures, one is immediately led to the question: Would it be possible to write a world of new music on the principle of serialism or was it just a radical experiment without much long-range effect? This is an important question when taking seriously the idea of creative analysis, and not only as a recipe for fabricating yet another work. And it is also an important question relating to a more systematic and demystifying understanding of musical creativity using analytical activity. In our case, the Structures, the Boulezian gesture of opening a work’s limits is a doubly critical and difficult one: On the one hand, it should help determine whether the huge calculations that led to the composition are worth being reused with aesthetic success. On the other hand, the method of serialism also marks the computational limits of humans to compose music. This latter fact will lead to the question of using music technology and in particular computers in a creative context. We must understand here how to integrate computational power into creative works of music, and on what level of creation this can or should be done. Boulez’s Structures is an excellent testbed to learn this lesson. It teaches us that the control of laborious computational processes cannot be systematically delegated to very limited human calculation power and that there is a life beyond strictly human composition. To paraphrase Schoenberg, “Somebody had to be Boulez.” Of course, computers are widely used by modern composers, but it is a common belief that creativity is separated from such procedures; it terminates when the big ideas are set. And computers are just doing the mean calculations. Apart from being classically wrong, we shall see that this is not realistic. In fact, no composer would contest the creative contribution of trying out a new composition on the piano—playing it on the keys and listening to its acoustical realization, which may give a strong feedback for the creative dynamics, even on the gestural level of one’s hands, as is testified by Ligeti and other composers, see [68]. We have to contradict Marshall McLuhan: The medium is not always the message. But it gives the message’s germ the necessary mold and resonance to grow into a full-fledged composition. Before delving into the technical details, we should address the question of whether not only computational computer power is necessary or advantageous for modern compositions, but also conceptual mathematical power. Isn’t musical composition anyway sufficiently controlled by plain combinatorial devices: permutations, recombinations, enumerations, and the like? The question is in some sense parallel to the question of whether it is sufficient to control a computer’s behavior on the level of binary chains, or machine language. Or else the question of whether it is not completely sufficient to perform a composition for piano by simply controlling the mechanical finger movements and forgetting about all those psycho-physicological ‘illusions’ such as gestures. The parallelism lies in the fact that all of these activities are shaped by high-level concepts that create the coherence of low-level tokens in order to
282
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
express thoughts and not just juxtapose myriad atomic units. Of course can one write a computer program in machine language, but only after having understood the high-level architecture of one’s ideas. The artistic performance of a complex composition only succeeds when it is shaped on the high mental level of powerful gestures. And the composition of computationally complex musical works needs comprehensive and structurally powerful concepts. Combinatorics is just a machine language of mathematical thinking. We shall see in the following analysis that it was precisely Ligeti’s combinatorial limitation that hindered his understanding of the real yoga of Boulez’s creative constructions. You can do combinatorics, but only if you know what is the steering idea—much as you can write the single notes of Beethoven’s Hammerklavier Sonata if you know the high-level ideas. The mathematics deployed in the modern mathematical music theory is precisely the tool for such an enterprise. It is not by chance that traditional music analysis is so poor for the composition of advanced music: Its conceptual power is far too weak for precise complex constructions, let alone for their computer-aided implementation. This lesson is interesting in the creativity process when it comes to successfully inspecting those walls. The critical point in wall inspection is to recognize walls, but this might be very difficult for many reasons. One reason is that one might stand too close to a wall and not be able to see that there is a wall exactly where one stands. One then needs tools to recognize the bigger architecture of the critical concept, to conceive entire walls instead of staring at an unrecognized surface detail. Higher-level languages are exactly what is needed to conceive higher architectures of critical concepts in the creative process. Why is this needed? Because the abstraction provided by higher languages reduces phenomena to their essential characteristics. Modern mathematics are such higher languages; they enable insights into what is essential. The great mathematician Alexander Grothendieck had exactly this ingenious capability to construct those powerful abstractions that gave access to solutions of difficult problems (such as the Weil conjectures or Fermat’s conjecture). If you want to open a wall, you have to understand where it is fixed and how it is connected to other parts of that critical concept. We shall now see that Boulez had exactly this capability to understand the higher architecture of serial approaches to musical composition to solve some of its basic problems.
25.2 Ligeti’s Analysis Ligeti’s analysis [67] of Structures Ia exhibits the totality of rows appearing in this section of the composition. It starts from the given serial rows SP for pitch classes and SD for durations (the primary parameters), as well as SL for loudness and SA for attack (the secondary parameters). It then presents and investigates that central 12 × 12-matrix3 Q = (Qi,j ) which gives rise to all row 3
Ligeti names it R, but we change the symbol since R is reserved for retrograde in our notation.
25.3 A First Creative Analysis of Structure Ia from Ligeti’s Perspective
283
permutations for all four parameters. Whereas the construction of Q is relatively natural, the subsequent permutations thereof for the primary parameters seem to be completely combinatorial, and even more radically those for the secondary parameters. Ligeti attributes to these constructions the qualification of combinatorial fetishism4 . This is even worse when it comes to the secondary parameters, where Boulez applies what Ligeti calls chessboard knight paths, a procedure that in Ligeti’s understanding qualifies as purely numerical game without any musical signification. This (dis)qualification remains valid in Ligeti’s final remarks on the new ways of hearing, which are enforced by this new compositional technique. He compares the result to the flashing neon lights of a big city, which, although being driven by precise machines, generate an overall effect of statistical sound swarms. He concludes that with this radical elimination of expressivity, still present in Webern’s compositions, the composition finds its beauty in the opening of pure structures. And Boulez—we follow Ligeti’s wording—in such a “nearly obsessive-compulsive neurosis, strains himself at the leash and will only be freed by his colored sensual feline world of ‘Marteau.’ ” Ligeti’s main objection to Boulez’s approach is that he makes abstraction from the parameters and plays an empty game of numbers instead. We now want to contradict this verdict and show that in the language of modern mathematics—topos theory to be precise—Boulez’s strategy is perfectly natural, and in fact, only reasonable when dealing with such diverse parameters as pitch classes, durations, loudnesses, and attacks. When we say “natural,” we mean mathematically natural, but the fact that a musical construction is only understood by advanced mathematical conceptualization, and not by naive combinatorial music theory, proves that mathematical naturality effectively hits the musical point. This fact will be confirmed later in this chapter by our ability to implement our findings in the music software Rubato in order to comply with the creative part of Boulez’s principle. Music theorists have to learn that from time to time, conceptual innovations may even enlighten their ossified domains. It is not the music’s fault if they are “dark to themselves”5 .
25.3 A First Creative Analysis of Structure Ia from Ligeti’s Perspective We observe right from the beginning that there is no intrinsic reason to transfer the twelve-pitch-class framework to the other parameters. If the number twelve is natural in pitch classes, its transfer to other parameters is a tricky business. How can this be performed without artificial constructs? 4
5
“. . . schliesslich die Tabellen fetischartig als Mass f¨ ur Dauernqualit¨ aten angewandt ...” Title of a Cecil Taylor LP.
284
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
To understand Boulez’s procedure, let us first analyze the matrix Q construction. It yields one pitch class row for every row. The ideas run as follows. We start with a modern interpretation of what is a dodecaphonic pitch class series SP . Naively speaking, SP is a sequence of twelve pitch classes: SP = (SP,1 , SP,2 , . . . SP,12 ). More mathematically speaking, it is an affine morphism6 SP : Z11 → Z12 , whose values are determined by the twelve values on e1 = 0 and the eleven basis vectors ei = (0, . . . 1, . . . 0), i = 2, 3, . . . 12, where the single 1 stands on position i − 1 of that sequence. This reinterpretation yields SP,i = SP (ei ). The condition that a series hits all twelve pitch classes means that the images SP (ei ), SP (ej ) are different for i = j. This reinterpretation of a dodecaphonic series means that it is viewed as a Z11 -addressed point of the pitch class space Z12 in the language of topos theory of music [78]. This language views the series as a point in the space Z12 , but just from the perspective of a particular domain, or address, namely Z11 . In topos theory of music, a space Z12 is replaced by its functor @Z12 , which at any given address B, i.e. module over a specific ring, evaluates to the set B@Z12 of affine module morphisms f : B → Z12 . This means that the address B is a variable and that our dodecaphonic series is just a point at a specific address among all possible addresses. In other words, the change of address is completely natural in this context. What does this mean? Suppose that we have a module morphism g : C → B between address modules. Then we obtain a natural map B@Z12 → C@Z12 that maps f : B → Z12 to the composed arrow f · g : C → Z12 . For example, if we take B = C = Z11 , and if g(ei ) = e12−i+1 , then the new series SP · g is the retrograde R(SP ) of the original series. Our claim is that all of Boulez’s constructions are simply address change maps and as such follow a very systematic construction. So the combinatoriality is viewed as a particular technique from topos theory. Of course, Boulez did not know this, since topos theory was not even invented at that time, and Yoneda’s lemma, which is the password to all these mathematical constructions, was only published in 1954, one year after the publication of Structure I. But this makes his approach even more remarkable; one could even state that in view of this temporal coincidence, Boulez’s Structures are the Yoneda lemma in music. 25.3.1 Address Change Instead of Parameter Transformations The trick that enables Boulez to get rid of the unnatural association of different parameters with the serial setup stemming from pitch classes is this: For any (invertible) transformation T : Z12 → Z12 , we have a new pitch class series, namely the composition T · SP . For a transposition T = T n , we get the n-fold 6
An affine morphism f : M → N between modules M, N over a commutative ring R is by definition the composition f = T t · g of a R-linear homomorphism g : M → N and a translation T t : N → N : n → t + n. Affine morphisms are well known in music theory, see [78].
25.3 A First Creative Analysis of Structure Ia from Ligeti’s Perspective
285
transposed series. For an inversion U (x) = u−x, we get the inverted series, etc. Now, it is evident that one can also obtain this effect by an address change, more precisely, if T : Z12 → Z12 is any affine transformation, then there is precisely one address change C(T ) : Z11 → Z11 by a base vector permutation such that the diagram C(T )
Z11 −−−−→ ⏐ ⏐ SP T
Z11 ⏐ ⏐S P
(25.1)
Z12 −−−−→ Z12
commutes. Instead of performing a parameter transformation on the codomain of the pitch class row, we may perform an address change on the domain Z11 . Note, however, that the address change C(T ) is also a function of the underlying series SP . What is the advantage of such a restatement of transformations? We now have simulated the parameter-specific transformation on the level of the universal domain Z11 , which is common to all parameter-specific series. This enables a transfer of the transformation actions on one parameter space (the pitch classes in the above case) to all other parameter spaces, just by prepending for any series the corresponding address change. So we take the transformation T on Z12 , replace it with the address change C(T ) on Z11 , and then apply this one to all other series, i.e. building SD · C(T ), SL · C(T ), SA · C(T ). This means that we now have a completely natural understanding of the derivation of parameter series from address changes, which act as mediators between pitch class transformations and transformations on other parameter spaces. This is the only natural way of carrying over these operations between intrinsically incompatible parameter spaces. We replace the spaces by their functors and act on the common addresses. This is quite the opposite of purely combinatorial gaming. It is functoriality at its best. For a deeper understanding of Boulez’s selection of his duration series, referring to Webern’s compositions, please see [35]. 25.3.2 The System of Address Changes for the Primary Parameters Now, nearly everything in Boulez’s construction of part Ia is canonical. The most important address change is the matrix Q. It is constructed as follows. Its ith row Q(i, −) is the base change C(T SP (i)−SP (1) ) associated with the transposition by the difference of the pitch class series at position i and 1. The natural7 number Q(i, j) in the matrix is therefore Q(i, j) = SP (i) + SP (j) − SP (1), a symmetrical expression in i and j. Moreover, we now see immediately from the definition of the operator C in the above commutative diagram that the composition of two permutations (rows) of the matrix is again such a permutation row; in fact, the transpositions they represent are the group of all transpositions. 7
We represent elements x ∈ Z12 by natural numbers 0 ≤ x ≤ 11.
286
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
We may now view Q as an address change Q : Z11 ⊠ Z11 → Z11 on the affine tensor product Z11 ⊠ Z11 , see [78, E.3.3], defined on the affine basis (ei ⊠ ej ) by Q(ei ⊠ ej ) = eQ(i,j) . For any such address change X : Z11 ⊠ Z11 → Z11 , and any parameter Z series SZ → P aramSpace with values in parameter space P aramSpace, we obtain twelve series in that space by address change SZ · X of the series, and then restricted to the ith rows of X, or equivalently, prepending the address change (!) rowi : Z11 → Z11 ⊠ Z11 defined by rowi (ej ) = ei ⊠ ej . Given any such address change matrix X : Z11 ⊠ Z11 → Z11 , we therefore get twelve series in every given parameter space. So we are now dealing with the construction of specific matrix address changes, and the entire procedure is settled. The general idea is this: One gives two address changes g, h : Z11 → Z11 with g(ei ) = eg(i) , h(ei ) = eh(i) and then deduces a canonical address change g ⊠h : Z11 ⊠Z11 → Z11 ⊠Z11 by the formula g ⊠h(ei ⊠ej ) = eg(i) ⊠eh(j) . So, when X is given, we obtain a new address change of the same type by building the composed address change X · g ⊠ h. For example, the retrograde matrix in Ligeti’s terminology is just the matrix Q · Id ⊠ R deduced from Q by the address change Id ⊠ R. And Ligeti’s U -matrix is deduced from Q by U ⊠ U , where U is the address change associated with the inversion at e♭ , i.e. it is the composite Q · U ⊠ U . Now everything is easy: For the first piano, for the primary parameters pitch class P and duration D, and for parts A and B, Boulez creates one matrix Q1P,A , Q1D,A , Q1P,B , Q1D,B address change each, all deduced from Q by the above 1 1 composition with product address changes TP,A = U ⊠ Id, TD,A =U ·R⊠U · 1 1 R, TP,B = U · R ⊠ U · R, TD,B = R ⊠ U via 1 1 1 1 , Q1D,A = Q · TD,A , Q1P,B = Q · TP,B , Q1D,B = Q · TD,B . (25.2) Q1P,A = Q · TP,A
This is quite systematic, but the second piano is now completely straightforward, in fact the product address changes of this instrument differ just by one single product address change, namely U ⊠ U : 1 2 TP,A , = U ⊠ U · TP,A
(25.3)
1 , TD,A 1 TP,B , 1 TD,B .
(25.4)
2 TD,A 2 TP,B 2 TD,B
=U ⊠U · =U ⊠U · =U ⊠U ·
(25.5) (25.6)
25.3.3 The System of Address Changes for the Secondary Parameters For the secondary parameters, loudness and attack, Boulez takes one such value per series—deduced from the given series SL , SA —that was derived for the primary parameters. Intuitively, for each row in one of the above matrixes, we want to get one loudness and one attack value.
25.3 A First Creative Analysis of Structure Ia from Ligeti’s Perspective
287
For loudness, we start with the Q matrix address change for piano 1 and with the U matrix for piano 2. We then take an address change a : Z11 → Z11 ⊠ Z11 for part A, and another c : Z11 → Z11 ⊠ Z11 for part B. These address changes are very natural paths in the given matrix. Path a is just the codiagonal of the matrix, i.e. a(ei ) = e12−i ⊠ ei , while path c is the path shown in Figure 25.1.
Fig. 25.1. The two paths a, c for loudness, part A and part B, in Ligeti’s Q matrix for piano 1; same paths in the U matrix for piano 2.
Contradicting Ligeti’s verdict, these paths are by no means arbitrary. They are both closed paths if one identifies the boundaries of the matrix. Path a is a closed path on the torus deduced from Q by identifying the horizontal and vertical boundary lines, respectively. And path c is closed on the sphere obtained by identifying the adjacent left and upper, and right and lower boundary lines, respectively. The torus structure is completely natural, if one recalls that pitch classes are identified exactly like the horizontal torus construction, while the vertical one is a periodicity in time, also a canonical identification. The sphere construction is obtained by the parameter exchange (diagonal reflection!) and the identification of boundary lines induced by this exchange. For the attack paths, one has a similar construction, only that the paths a and c are rotated by 90 degrees clockwise and yield paths α and γ. Again, piano 1 takes its values on Q, while piano 2 takes its values on the U matrix. So apart from that rotation, everything is the same as for loudness. Summarizing, we need just one product address change given by the U transformation for the primary parameters in order to go from piano 1 to piano 2, while one rotation 90 degrees suffices to switch between the secondary parameter paths. Observe that this rotation is just the address change on the matrix space Z11 ⊠ Z11 induced by a retrograde on each factor! It could not be simpler, and barely more beautiful.
288
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
25.3.4 The First Creative Analysis A first transduction is now immediate. Of course, there are many ways to shift from the given analytical data to neighboring data in the space of analytical data. A first way is obvious, and it is also the one in which we urgently need to remedy the evident imperfection of the given construction, namely the number of instruments. Why only two instruments? In order to obtain a more intrinsically serialist construction, one should not work with two, but with twelve instruments. This is achieved in the most obvious way: We had seen that the second piano is derived from the first by taking the U matrix instead of the Q matrix. This suggests that we may now take twelve address changes Ui : Z11 → Z11 , starting with the identity Id, and generate one instrumental variant for each such address change, starting with the structure for the first piano and then adding variants for each successive instrument. This yields a total of twelve instruments and for each a succession of twelve series for part A and twelve series for part B, according to the twelve rows of the matrix address changes as discussed above. For the ith series, this gives us twelve instruments playing their row simultaneously. Boulez has, of course, not realized such a military arrangement of series. We hence propose a completion of the serial idea in the selection of the numbers of simultaneously playing series. Observe that the series SP of pitch classes has a unique inner symmetry that exchanges the first and second hexachord, namely the inversion I = T 7 .−1 between e and e♭ , i.e. the series defines the strong dichotomy No. 71 in the sense of mathematical counterpoint theory [78, chapter 30]. In part A, we now select the instrument SP (i) from below and then take I(SP (i)) successive instruments in ascending order (and using the circle identification for excessive instrument numbers). For part B we take the I-transformed sequence of initial instrumental numbers and attach the original serial numbers as successively ascending occupancies of instruments. Figure 25.2 shows the result. The next step will be to transform this scheme into a computer program in order to realize such compositions and to test their quality. It is now evident that such a calculation cannot be executed by a human without excessive efforts and a high risk of making errors. Moreover, it is also not clear whether such creative reconstructions will yield interesting results, or perhaps only for special transformational sequences U1 , U2 , . . . U12 . We come back to this issue after the analytical discussion of the second part of Structures.
25.4 Implementing Creative Analysis on RUBATO As already mentioned in the introduction, the concrete realization of a variety of creative analyses in terms of notes is beyond human calculation power, or at least beyond the patience of the artistic creator. Therefore, we have implemented the above mathematical procedure on the music software RUBATO [75]. This involves seven new rubettes (Rubato PlugIns), specifically programmed for our procedure (see also Figure 25.3): BoulezInput, BoulezMartix,
25.4 Implementing Creative Analysis on RUBATO
289
Fig. 25.2. The instrumental occupancies in part A, B, following the autocomplementarity symmetry I = T 7 . − 1 of the original pitch class series. The lowest instruments are taken according to the series, while the occupancies are chosen according to the I-transformed values. For example for the first column, we have the serial value 3, and its I transformed is 4, so we add 4 increasingly positioned instruments.
Transformation, BaseChange, Chess, SerialSystem, and Boulez2Macro. We call them boulettes to distinguish them from general-purpose rubettes. In order to understand the data flow of this network of rubettes, we need to briefly sketch the data format that is used; details are found in the documentation [75]. Rubettes communicate exclusively via transfer of denotators. These are instances of forms, a type of generalized mathematical space comprising universal constructions, such as powersets, limits, and colimits, that are derived from mathematical modules. The outputs A and B of boulette Boulez2Macro create one zero-addressed denotator for each part A, B of Boulez’s score. These two denotators, MA , MB , are not just sets of notes, but are more refined in that they include hierarchies of notes. This is the form where MA , MB live: It is a circular form, namely M acroScore:.Power(N ode) N ode:.Limit(N ote, M acroScore) N ote:.Simple(Onset, P itch, Loudness, Duration, V oice) Onset:.Simple(R), P itch:.Simple(Z), Loudness:.Simple(Q) Duration:.Simple(R), V oice:.Simple(Z)
290
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
So the formal notation of these denotators is MA :0@M acroScore(MA,0 , MA,1 , . . . MA,m ), MB :0@M acroScore(MB,0 , MB,1 , . . . MB,n ) with the nodes MA,i , MB,j , respectively. Each node has a note, its anchor note, and satellites, its MacroScore set denotator. Observe that the concept of an anchor with satellites is grano cum salis also the approach taken by Boulez in his multiplication of chords, where the anchor is the distinguished note, and where the satellites are represented by the intervals of the other notes with respect to the anchor. This output A, B is then united in the Set rubette and its output C is sent to the AllFlatten rubette, which recursively “opens” all the nodes’ satellite MacroScore. How is this performed? Given a node with empty satellite set, one just cuts off the set. Else, one supposes that its satellite MacroScore has already recursively performed the flattening process, resulting in a set of notes. Then one adds these notes (coordinate-wise) to the node’s anchor note. This means that the satellites are given a relative position with respect to their anchor note. A trill is a typical example of such a structure: The trill’s main note is the anchor, while the trill notes are the satellites, denoted by their relative position with respect to the anchor note. The output from the Boulez2Macro boulette is given as a MacroScore denotator for strong reasons: We want to work on the output and take it as primary material for further creative processing in the spirit of Boulez, a processing that, as we shall see, requires a hierarchical representation. The multiplication of chords used in Structure II implicitly also uses a hierarchical construction of the above type. Therefore, the chosen M acroScore form acts as a unifier of conceptual architectures in parts I and II of this composition. 25.4.1 The System of Boulettes But let us se first how the Boulez composition is calculated. We are given the following input data: Outlet 1 in the BoulezInput boulette contains the series for all parameters as a denotator Series:@Z11 BoulezSeries(SP , SD , SL , SA ) of the form BoulezSeries:. lim(P, L, D, A) with the factor forms P :.Simple(Z12 ), D:.Simple(R), L:.Simple(Z), A:.Simple(R3 ). The attack form A has values in the real 3-space, where the first coordinate measures the fraction of increase of nominal loudness, the second the articulatory fraction of increase in nominal duration, and the third the fraction of shift in onset defined by the attack type. For example, a sforzato attack (sfz) would increase nominal loudness by factor 1.3, shorten duration to a staccato by 0.6, and add to the nominal onset a delay of −0.2 × nominal duration. As discussed in section 25.2, the address Z11 yields the parametrization by the twelve indices
25.4 Implementing Creative Analysis on RUBATO
291
Fig. 25.3. The Rubato network generating MIDI files (played by the ScorePlay rubette) with arbitrary input from the creative analysis that is encoded in the BoulezInput rubette.
required for a serial sequence of parameters. For example, the pitch class series is the factor denotator SP :Z11 @P (3, 2, 9, 8, 7, 6, 4, 1, 0, 10, 5, 11). Outlet 2 contains the two address changes for retrograde R and inversion U . They are encoded as denotators R:Z11 @Index(R1 , R2 , . . . R12 ), U :Z11 @Index(U1 , U2 , . . . U12 ) in the simple form Index:.Simple(Z), which indicates the indices Ri of the affine basis vectors, which are the images of the basis vectors ei C(R) and inversion C(U ). Outlet 3 encodes the above sequence U. = (Ui ) of address changes for the instrumental sequence, i.e. a denotator U.:Z11 @Sequ(U1 , U2 , . . . U12 ) with Ui :Z11 @Index(Ui,1 , Ui,2 , . . . Ui,12 ), and the list type form Sequ:.List(Index). (This, in fact, also works for any number of instruments, but we restrict our example to twelve instruments as chosen above.) Outlet 4 encodes the registers, which must be defined in order to transform the pitch classes into real pitches. We give this information in the same form as the address change sequence, where the coordinates for the ith sequence are the octave numbers where the pitches of the respective pitch class series in the corresponding instrument are positioned. Octaves are numbered starting from octave 0 at pitch 60 in MIDI format. This information is also used to position the pitches according to an instrumental range. The Split rubette takes the input series Series and sends its pitch class factor SP to outlet 5. This denotator is taken as input of the BoulezMatrix
292
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
boulette and yields the famous matrix Q at outlet 6, which we interpret as a denotator Q:Z11 ⊠ Z11 @Index(Qi,j , i, j = 1, 2, . . . 12). The boulette BaseChange is devoted to the calculation of the address changes on outlet 8 for the primary parameters described in the four formula groups 25.2 and 25.3 ff. for the primary parameters of the twelve instruments and takes as input the matrix Q from outlet 6 and the sequence U. of instrumental address changes. The boulette Chess is devoted to the calculation of the corresponding address changes on outlet 9 for the secondary parameters loudness and attack, as described by the chessboard paths. Given the address change systems on input 8 and 9 of the SerialSystem boulette, and taking as a third input the total series from outlet 1, the total system of series is calculated according to our formulas described in sections 25.3.2 and 25.3.3. This yields outlet 10, which is finally added as input, together with the input 4 of octaves to calculate the effective parameters. The pitches, nominal durations, and loudnesses are now given, and the nominal onsets are calculated to produce the rectangular scheme shown in Figure 25.2. The attack data is used to transform the nominal values into the attack-specific deformations, and we obtain the outputs A and B as required. This output is a denotator of form M acroScore. Its nodes in part A and B are 144 series each. The anchor note of each serial node is taken to be the first note in the series. The satellites of this node are the remaining 11 notes with their relative positions with respect to the anchor note. Moreover, the output denotators at A and B have one instrumental voice number for each instrument. Taking the union of these parts in outlet C, we obtain a large M acroScore denotator MC = MA ∪ MB . Selecting from this system, the series as shown in Figure 25.2 yields the final “raw” material, which will now be used to generate more involved creative constructions in section 25.5. The system as calculated by Rubato is shown in Figure 25.4. The graphical representation is realized on the BigBang rubette for geometric composition. The input to this rubette is the denotator MC , while the selection of the instruments according to the selection shown in Figure 25.2 is made by direct graphically interactive editing. The functionality of the BigBang rubette is discussed in section 25.5.2.
25.5 A Second More Creative Analysis and Reconstruction One of the most creative extensions of techniques in musical composition is the opening of the transformational concept. This was already a crucial argument in Boulez’s own construction of derived Q matrixes, where he invented that ingenious tool of address change in order to extend pitch class transformations to parameters where such operations would not apply in a natural way. Our extension of Boulez’s approach was presented above and implemented in Rubato’s boulettes, yielding the denotator MC :0@M acroScore().
25.5 A Second More Creative Analysis and Reconstruction
293
Fig. 25.4. The final “raw” material for twelve instruments. Instruments are distinguished by colors. Satellites pertaining to a given anchor note are connected by rays to that note.
In this section, we shall add other extensions of the given transformations and apply them to the construction of huge extensions starting from the present “raw material” MC . There are two threads of extensions: The first is the conceptual extension, i.e. conceiving new types of transformations, while the second deals with the associated concrete manipulation of compositions on the level of graphically interactive gestures. The background of this double strategy is the following general idea: The formulaic rendition of compositional tools, when implemented in software, pertains to what is somewhat vaguely called algorithmic composition. This is what happens in Rubato’s boulettes. The drawback of such an implementation is that the result is “precooked” in the cuisine of the code and cannot be inspected but as a res facta. A composer would prefer to be able to influence his/her processes in the making, not only when it is (too) late. This is why we have now realized a different strategy: The transformations, which are enabled by the the BigBang rubette8 , are immediately visible when being defined and can be heard without delay. The general idea behind this approach is that any algorithm should be transmuted into a graphically interactive gestural interface, where its processes would be managed on the fly, gesturally, and while they happen (!). Why should I wait until rotation of musical parameters is calculated? I want to generate it, and while I actually rotate the system by increasing angles, I would like to see the resulting rotated set of note events and also hear how that sounds, and then decide upon the success or failure of that rotation. 8
The BigBang rubette is Florian Thalmann’s work.
294
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
25.5.1 The Conceptual Extensions The conceptual extension of transformations has two components: the extension of the transformations as such and the application of such transformations as a function of the hierarchical structure of the M acroScore form. The serial transformations on the note parameters of a composition usually comprise the affine transformations generated by inversion (pitch reflection), retrograde (onset reflection), transposition (pitch translation), and time shift (onset translation). But they also include the construction of assemblies of iterated transformations, and not just one transformed note set but the union of successively applied transformations. The latter is typically realized by regular patterns in time, where rhythmical structures are constructed. So we have these two constructions: Given a set of notes M and a transformation f , one either considers one transformed set f (M ) or else the union i=0,1,...k f i (M ). The latter is well known as a rhythmical frieze construction if f is a translation in time. If we generalize frieze constructions to two dimensions, using two translations f, g in the plane, we obtain a wallpaper i=0,1,...k,j=0,1,...l f i g j (M ). 25.5.1.1 Extensions of Single Transformations The natural generalization of such transformational constructions is to include not only those very special transformations, but also any n-dimensional non−→ singular affine transformation f in the group GLn (R), whose elements are all functions of shape f = T t · h, where h is an element of the group GLn (R) and where T t (x) = t + x is the translation by t ∈ Rn . It is well known from mathematical music theory that any such transformation can be decomposed as a concatenation of musical standard transformations, which each involve only one or two of the n dimensions. In view of this result, we have chosen the generalization of the above transformations to these special cases in 2-space: (1) translations T t , (2) reflections RefL at a line L, (3) rotations Rotα by angle α, (4) dilation DilL,λ vertical to the line L by factor λ > 0, (5) shearing ShL,α along the line L and by angle α. These are operations on real vector spaces, while we have mixed coefficients in the M acroScore form. The present (and quite brute) solution of this problem consists of first embedding all coefficents in the real numbers, performing the transformations, and then recasting the results to the subdomains, respectively. −→ Given the group GLn (R) of transformations (generated by the above twodimensional prototypes), we now have to deal with the hierarchical structure of denotators in the M acroScore form. How can transformations be applied to such objects? To this end, recall that a M acroScore denotator is9 a set M of nodes N = (AN , SN ), which have two components: an anchor note AN from the (essentially) five-dimensional form N ote and a M acroScore-formed satellite set SN . Common notes are represented by nodes having empty satellite 9
All denotators in this discussion will be zero-addressed.
25.5 A Second More Creative Analysis and Reconstruction
295
−→ sets. Given a transformation f ∈ GLn (R) and a M acroScore denotator M , a first operation of f upon M is defined by anchor note action: f · M = {(f · AN , SN )|N ∈ M }
(25.7)
This type of action is very useful if we want to transform just the anchors and leave the relative positions of the satellite notes invariant. For example, if the satellites encode an embellishment, such as a trill, then this is the right operation in order to transform a trill into another trill. This operation is easily generalized to any set S of nodes in the tree of M acroScore denotator M , such that no two of them are hierarchically related (one being in the satellite tree of the other). The above situation of formula (25.7) referred to the top-level anchors. Suppose that S consists of nodes N . For non-satellite nodes, we have the above function. Suppose now that such a node N is a satellite pertaining to a well-defined anchor note A(N ). Thinking of that anchor note as a local coordinate origin, we may now apply a trans−→ formation f ∈ GLn (R) to all selected satellite nodes of A(N ) by the above formula (25.7), yielding a transformed set of satellites of the same anchor note. We may apply this operation to each set of satellites of given anchors occurring in S. Since there are no hierarchical dependencies, no contradiction or ambiguity appears, i.e., no note will be transformed together with one of its direct or iterated satellite notes. This means that we are simultaneously applying f to all satellite sets of S. In other words, we take the disjoint union S = Sk of satellite sets Sk pertaining to specific anchor notes Ak and then apply a simultaneous transformation f to each of these Sk . We denote this operation by f ⊙ S. There is another operation that we may apply to a set S with the above properties. This one takes not the relative positions of S-elements, but their flattened position and then applies the transformation f to these flattened notes. It is the operation one would apply in a hierarchical context, such as a Schenker-type grouping, but without further signification of the hierarchy for the transformational actions. After the transformation, each of these transformed flattened notes is taken back to its original anchor note. For example, if s = 1, and if N = (AN , SN ) is a satellite of level zero anchor note A(N ), then we first flatten the note (once), which means that we take N ′ = (A(N ) + AN , SN ), we then apply f to its new anchor A(N ) + AN , yielding N ′′ = (f (A(N ) + AN ), SN ), and we finally subtract the original anchor, yielding the new satellite N ′′′ = (f (A(N ) + AN ) − A(N ), SN ) of A(N ). This operation is denoted similar to the above operation, i.e., by f · S. 25.5.1.2 Extensions of Wallpapers Let us now review the construction of wallpapers in view of a possible creative extension. Mathematically speaking, a wallpaper is a structure that is produced by repeated application of a sequence of translations T . = (T t1 , T t2 , . . . , T tr )
296
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
acting on a given motif M of notes. Each T ti of these translations is repeatedly performed in the interval numbers of the sequence I. = (Ii = [ai , bi ]), ai ≤ bi , of integers, what means that the total wallpaper is defined by W (T . , I.)(M ) = T λ1 t1 T λ2 t2 . . . T λr tr (M ) (25.8) ai ≤λi ≤bi
This formula has nothing particular regarding the special nature of the different powers of translations. This means that the formula could be generalized without restrictions to describe grids of any sequence of transformations −→ f. = (f1 , f2 , . . . , fr ) for fi ∈ GLn (R), thus yielding the generalized wallpaper formula W (f., I.)(M ) = f1λ1 ◦ f2λ2 ◦ . . . frλr (M ) (25.9) ai ≤λi ≤bi
which also works for negative powers of the transformations, since these are all invertible. In our context, the motif M will no longer be a set of common notes, but a denotator of M acroScore form. Therefore, we may replace the naive application of transformations to a set of notes by the action of transformations on such denotators as discussed above. This means that—mutatis mutandis— we have two transformation wallpapers for a set S of nodes of a M acroScore denotator with the above hierarchical independency property: the relative one f1λ1 ◦ f2λ2 ◦ . . . frλr ⊙ S (25.10) W (f., I.) ⊙ S = ai ≤λi ≤bi
or the absolute one f1λ1 ◦ f2λ2 ◦ . . . frλr · S
W (f., I.) · S =
(25.11)
ai ≤λi ≤bi
This generalizes the transformations and the motives in question. A last generalization is evident when looking at the range of powers of the intervening transformations. Until now, these powers are taken within the hypercube D = i Ii of sequences of exponents. However, nothing changes if we admit more generally any finite “domain” set D ⊂ Zr and make the union according to the sequences of exponents appearing in D: f1λ1 ◦ f2λ2 ◦ . . . frλr ⊙ S
W (f., D) ⊙ S =
(25.12)
(λ1 ,λ2 ,...λr )∈D
or else the absolute one: W (f., D) · S =
(λ1 ,λ2 ,...λr )∈D
f1λ1 ◦ f2λ2 ◦ . . . frλr · S
(25.13)
25.5 A Second More Creative Analysis and Reconstruction
297
These are the generalizations that we need to describe the transformations in Structures in a uniform way. The situation in Structures I has been described above. The nature of the multiplication relating to Structures II can also be controlled by the above constructions; we omit this here and refer to [69]. 25.5.2 The BigBang Rubette for Computational Composition The BigBang rubette was implemented during a research visit of one of the authors (Florian Thalmann) at the School of Music of the University of Minnesota. It allows for graphically interactive gestural actions for transformations and wallpapers on ScoreF orm denotators. We shall not describe all transformations in detail, but show the typical gestural action to be taken for a rotation of a denotator (see Figures 25.5 and 25.6).
Fig. 25.5. Rotation (right) of the first bars of Beethoven’s op. 106, Allegro (left). The rotation circle shows the mouse movement on its periphery; the original is also shown.
The user loads (or draws) a composition (a denotator in M acroScore form) M . This is shown in the left half of Figure 25.5; the example is the first bars of Beethoven’s op. 106, Allegro. This composition is shown in the plane of onset (abscissa) and pitch (ordinate), but the user may choose any two of the five axes corresponding to the note parameters and perform all transformations on the corresponding plane. After having selected with the mouse (drawn rectangles around the critical note groups) the notes from this
298
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
Fig. 25.6. Here, a relative rotation is performed on the two satellite sets, with their two anchor notes at the rays’ centers. The original positions are also shown.
composition to be transformed, the user next chooses a rotation center by clicking anywhere on the window, i.e. the center of the circle on top of Figure 25.5. Then pressing and holding the mouse button apart from the selected center, a rotation tool appears, showing the current angle in gray. As long as the mouse is not released, the rotation simultaneously acts on the selected note group. The rotated music is also immediately played when the user holds the mouse still. The user may hold on and redo his rotational movement on the circle. The visual result in our example is shown to the right of Figure 25.5. As to the relative rotation, Figure 25.6 shows the result of such an action, together with the original composition. To achieve this operation, the user chooses a set of satellites throughout the given composition. We have chosen two satellite groups derived from the composition in Figure 25.5. Then the user chooses one anchor note and defines the center of rotation relative to that anchor. Here, our center was chosen near the anchor of the right satellite group. Then the same gestures are performed as in the previous rotation. The circle is shown in Figure 25.6, and all chosen satellite notes are rotated relative to their respective centers. Here, we see two rotated groups: the left one stemming from the initial chords of the composition (red), the right one is overlapping with the original selection. Again, the user may hold on (without releasing the mouse) and redo the rotation after having listened to the result. The selected notes will remain selected, and the user may then add a next transformation, and so forth. This enables a completely spontaneous and delay-less transformational gesture in musical composition.
25.5 A Second More Creative Analysis and Reconstruction
299
A similar procedure realizes wallpapers as defined in equations (25.12) and (25.13). Let us illustrate the wallpaper construction for a motif of top-level nodes, as shown by the darkened set on Figure 25.7. The user selects this motif and then switches to wallpaper mode. Now, whenever a transformation (and also a composed transformation, such as a translation followed by a rotation, much like with single transformations) is defined by the previous gestural action, the union of all iterated transformations of the motif is simultaneously shown (and heard). The range of iteration (the powers of that transformation) can be set at will. For a second transformation, the wallpaper mode is clicked again and allows the user to perform a second transformation, and a third, fourth, etc. The user can also switch to another parameter plane when adding new transformations, and thereby create wallpaper structures in less evident, but musically precious parameters, such as loudness and voice. The example in Figure 25.7 has two transformations, each of them being a translation followed by a rotation and then a dilation. The BigBang rubette also allows for multidimensional alterations and morphing. These are deformation operations, which alter given notes (on specified levels of the Macroscore hierarchy) in the direction of another composition, which might be anything, or just a single point of attraction. We do not discuss this technique further here and refer to [117] for details.
Fig. 25.7. A wallpaper is built from a motif (darkened). Two transformations are used—both are translations followed by rotation and shrinking dilation.
25.5.3 A Composition Using the BigBang Rubette and the Boulettes Here is a composition, logically named restructures, which Guerino Mazzola and Schuyler Tsuda co-composed using of the above techniques, start-
300
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
ing from the raw material MC shown in Figure 25.4. We also applied the alteration techniques implemented in the BigBang rubette but will not discuss this technique further here. The composition can be downloaded from http://www.encyclospace.org/special/restructures.mp3. This composition has four movements. Each movement is transformed according to a specific geometric BigBang rubette technique, which we describe in the following paragraphs. After executing these operations, the twelve voices of each movement, which are avaliable as twelve separate MIDI files, were elaborated by adequate orchestrations. This was realized by Tsuda, who is an expert in sound design. He orchestrated and attributed the MIDI files to specific sounds in order to transform the abstract events into an expressive body of sound. The first movement (Expansion/Compression) takes a copy of MC , then “pinches” the satellites (but not the anchors!) of part A in the sense that the first (in onset) satellites are alterated 100 percent in pitch direction only to a defined pitch, whereas the last satellites are left as they were (0 percent alteration). The satellites inbetween are pinched by linear interpolation. The same procedure is applied to part B; however, this time the pinching is 100 percent at the end and 0 percent at the start. This is shown in Figure 25.8. Instrumentation 1: Voice 1 = grand piano, voice 2 = scraped, bowed, rolled, and struck suspended cymbals, voice 3 = electronic mallets, voice 4 = solo cello, voice 5 = pizzicato strings, voice 6 = electronic space strings, voice 7 = plucked e-bass, voice 8 = grand piano, voice 9 = electronic percussion, voice 10 = timpany, voice 11 = electronic toms, voice 12 = electronic bells.
Fig. 25.8. First movement: variable pinching the satellite onsets—100 percent pinching at start and end onsets, no pinching in the meeting of end of part A and start of part B.
25.5 A Second More Creative Analysis and Reconstruction
301
Fig. 25.9. Fourth movement: sucking down the anchors, expanding their durations, lifting the satellites in part A, then progressive pinching of notes in part B.
For the second movement (Space-Time), we took another copy of MC and expanded the onsets and the durations of the anchors of the second appearance to the double, which yielded the situation shown in Figure 25.10. Instrumentation 2: Voice 1 = strings, voice 2 = flute and horn, voice 3 = grand piano, voice 4 = sine waves, voice 5 = electronic voice, voice 6 = grand piano, voice 7 = trombone and tuba, voice 8 = electronic strings, voice 9 = triangle and finger cymbals, voice 10 = bowed piano, voice 11 = clarinetes, voice 12 = electronic bells.
Fig. 25.10. Second movement: expanding onsets and durations.
For the third movement (Rotations), taking again a copy of MC , and focusing first on part A, we apply a retrograde inversion to the anchors, and then in a second operation also to all satellites relative to their anchors. We then take part B and apply a rotation of all satellites, relative to their anchors, by 45 degrees in the counterclockwise direction. The result shown in Figure 25.11.
302
25 Boulez: Structures Recomposed
Instrumentation 3: Voice 1 = sine waves, voice 2 = oboe and bassoon, voice 3 = pizzicato strings, voice 4 = marimba, voice 5 = horns, voice 6 = electronic mallets, voice 7 = temple blocks and tam-tam, voice 8 = grand piano, voice 9 = electronic percussion, voice 10 = sine waves, voice 11 = trombones, voice 12 = electronic bells.
Fig. 25.11. Third movement: retrograde inversion of anchors and satellites in part A, rotation of satellites in part B.
Finally, for the fourth movement (Coherence/Opposition), taking again a copy of MC , we take part A and pinch to low pitches the anchors and dilate their durations, whereas the satellites are pinched to high pitches. In part B, we also operate such separation of pitch of satellites from anchors, but we also execute a progressive pinching of the pitches toward a fixed pitch toward the end of the composition. The result is shown in Figure 25.9. Instrumentation 4: Voice 1 = glockenspiel and electronic noise, voice 2 = glockenspiel and electronic noise, voice 3 = grand piano and electronic noise, voice 4 = harp, electronic noise, and pizzicato strings, voice 5 = sine waves, voice 6 = finger cymbals and timpani rolls, voice 7 = electronic bells, voice 8 = grand piano, voice 9 = Chinese opera gong and low and high gongs, voice 10 = bowed cymbals, voice 11 = triangle and bass drum rolls, voice 12 = triangle and bass drum rolls. 25.5.4 Was This “Creative Analysis” a Creative Success? Let us summarize the efforts we have described above in a computer-aided recomposition of Boulez’s Structures. In a first step, we have opened the walls of Boulez’s serial approach by a mathematical restatement of his critical structures. Here the technique to open those walls was the usage of modern mathematics—more precisely, Yoneda’s lemma. This conceptual extension is set up starting from the formally very naive approach of music theorists or composers and then using universal theories set forth by advanced insights that are driven by the most abstract and precise style of (mathematical) thought: topos theory. This style of extension can be criticized as being “overdressed” with respect to the technical level of our
25.5 A Second More Creative Analysis and Reconstruction
303
conceptual reconstruction. But it is clear that such extensions would never be possible when sticking to the naive style of musical set theory. We definitely needed the topos-theoretical perspective to find those extensions that enabled our recomposition. We then applied the conceptual extensions to an implementation in the composite software RUBATO . This was not a creative action per se, but it was the embodiment of those theoretical concept extensions, which is necessary to eventually make music. This implementation is mandatory when we speak about the instrumental reality of music. And it also shows the role of computer programs in music. They are not creative per se but mediate between complex thoughts and instrumental realization. In our case, the complexity of the recomposition was far beyond human score writing, and we could achieve the control of a variety of system parameters in Boulez’s compositional experiment. In this sense, the program was not only an embodiment of abstract ideas but also a creative environment for inventing new variants of the thoughtful creative analysis. We hope that the concrete results of our efforts have given some suggestions of how to work effectively in Boulez’s spirit for future creative analyses.
26 Ludwig van Beethoven’s Sonata opus 109: Six Variations
This case study illustrates the mathematical variant of our concept of creativity as discussed in section 19.2. The musical example we are looking at in this chapter is the third movement of Beethoven’s piano Sonata in E-major, op. 109, which is a sequence of six variations on the sonata’s main theme, and which is titled “Gesangvoll, mit innigster Empfindung” (“Lyrical, with deepest sentiment”). We mainly follow the brilliant analysis by J¨ urgen Uhde [119, p. 465 ff.].
Fig. 26.1. The main theme of Beethoven’s sonata op. 109.
The theme is presented mezza voce in the first eight measures before the first variation (see Figure 26.1). It appears in four variants of two measures each, the first being the five-note motif X in the soprano voice g♯, e, f ♯, d♯, b of this imaginary string quartet setting (Uhde). We include the f ♯ because it fills up the dominant triad f ♯, d♯, b that follows the tonic triad g♯, e(, b) (whose b appears in the alto voice).
G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6 26, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
305
306
26 Ludwig van Beethoven’s Sonata opus 109: Six Variations
26.1 Uhde’s Perspective Metaphor The six variations V1 , V2 , . . . V6 are variations of this theme, but they are not independent of the theme (as is the case in Beethoven’s Diabelli variations), or even just ornamentations and fillers as in Mozart’s “Ah, vous dirai-je Maman” KV 265, but “dance around it in large circles” and serve it at its “maiorem gloriam” (Uhde)1 . So V1 , V2 , . . . V6 are all directed toward the theme X, a fact that we would write as if this configuration were embedded in a category, namely by six morphisms (perspectives on X, taken from the addresses V1 , V2 , . . . V6 ) f1 : V1 → X, f2 : V2 → X, . . . f6 : V6 → X. Each of these perspectives stresses a particular aspect of X, and Uhde draws a beautiful picture of this configuration of variable perspectives. When the first five variations are over, he asks whether there is still an efficient position for the sixth, and adds: Wurde das Thema nicht von allen Seiten aus der N¨ ahe und aus der Ferne, nach Klang und Struktur ausgeleuchtet? Die bisherigen Variationen ‘umtanzten’ das Thema, und jede huldigte einer anderen thematischen Eigenschaft.2 So Uhde really interprets these variations as variable perspectives of the theme X. Each perspective focuses on a specific aspect. We do not have to go into the details of these variations and just summarize their overall character: 1. A melodic variation f1 : V1 → X built upon a homophonic setting with waltz accompaniment. 2. A rhythmical variation f2 : V2 → X with sophisticated shiftings of the theme’s tones in a sequence of intervallic arpeggios. 3. A contrapuntal variation f3 : V3 → X built upon correspondences by inversion of the theme and its redistribution on different voices. 4. A permutational variation f4 : V4 → X exchanging some notes of the theme to grasp all of the theme’s cantabile power in a fughetta-like rendition. 5. This variation f5 : V5 → X also works as a permutational one, but it is devoted to reveal the power of the third, which was also the initial interval (g♯, e) of the original theme. In our mathematical version of the creative process, this list of perspectives fi constitutes the opening of the critical concept’s walls. We inspect the theme X as if it were a functor @X and look how it behaves from a number of 1
2
Mozart seems to be looking for something from outside, floating around in the sky. This might be the reason his music always doesn’t sound grounded—opposite to Beethoven, whose view is substantial, from inside. Wasn’t the theme illuminated from all sides from near and from far, and following sound and structure? The preceding variations ‘danced’ around the theme, and each was devoted to another thematic property.
26.2 Why a Sixth Variation?
307
characteristic perspectives fi . And like in our mathematical version of creativity, Uhde stresses that these five perspectives are “all that can be said,” they are characteristic addresses.
26.2 Why a Sixth Variation? Following our mathematical model, we now have to consider the colimit3 colim(D) of the system D of these five perspectives, together with their mutual relations. This colimit perspective colim(D) → X then would present a concise perspective (uniting all five single perspectives) containing all the previous insights in a single item.
Fig. 26.2. The beginning of the trill explosion in measure 164 of the third movement of op. 109.
It is natural to interpret the sixth variation as being precisely this colimit that we require in the mathematical approach. Of course, we are not in the context of a formally defined mathematical category here, but we can try to interpret the sixth variation in terms of the essential property of a colimit. A colimit, in fact, allows for the synthesis of a number of perspectives on X into a single one; everything that had been said in the five variations can now be seen in concentrated form in the sixth variation. It is fascinating to read Uhde’s interpretation of the sixth variation. He views it as if it were itself a body of six micro-variations, and he describes this body as a “streamland with bridges,” the bridges connecting the six micro-variations. This is very similar to the construction of a colimit, which is also essentially a landscape connecting its components by bridge functions. Looking at the sixth variations, it in fact contains a number of restatements of the theme but then dramatically converges to a finale that is a kind of synthesis of all these aspects, and Uhde describes this final explosion of energy that is incited by the dominant’s vibrational axis with that long-lasting trill b − c♯. It is, however, critical that the dominant lasts so long (measure 165-187, 3
Intuitively, the colimit is the union and connection of these five perspectives.
308
26 Ludwig van Beethoven’s Sonata opus 109: Six Variations
Fig. 26.3. First movement of Mozart’s piano sonata KV 545 in C-major. The trill d, e prepares the tonic c in a cadential function.
almost half of the sixth variation!) without being resolved to the tonic. Expecting the cadential function of the dominant, the audience would be annoyed when hearing such a never-ending announcement of the tonic. The function of this trill must be different. We can make this explosion more precise. The dominant’s vibration is more concretely shown as a alternative rendition of the dominant tone b and the neighboring c♯. This rotation around these two tones is first set as a set of explicit notes, but then with increasing energy converges to a fulminant final explosion of a trill b − c♯ (see Figure 26.2). William Kinderman, in his description of the finale of op. 109 [61, Vol I, p. 90], writes: “Through a kind of radioactive breakup, the theme virtually explodes from within, yielding an array of shimmering, vibrating sounds. One might regard the sustained trill on B with its upper neighbor C ♯ , which migrates into the treble in the passage before the thematic reprise, as the utmost elaboration of the melodic peak of the sarabande on these two notes.” This trill pairing is not only a nice emotional effect of rotational energy, but it has a very substantial interpretation in terms of a cadence of the underlying tonality! In fact, the inversional movement Ib/c♯ around b − c♯ is identical to the inversion Ic at c or its tritone f ♯ (see also Figure 26.4). As c is not in the E-scale, the inversion of its neighbors b − c♯ does the job. In other words, the trill characterizes or cadences the basic tonality E-major via its unique inner symmetry inversion at f ♯. Also this is a cadential function not normally used in harmony, but we have shown in other analyses of Beethoven’s work that this view is a reality in his compositional structures. Frequently, the trill in a cadential function is used with the second and third scale degrees, preparing the tonic, such as shown in Figure 26.3 for Mozart sonata KV 545. And Figure 26.5 makes evident that Beethoven did arrange the sequence of interval arpeggios in measures 173-174 in strong correspondence with the E major symmetry. We would
26.2 Why a Sixth Variation?
309
Fig. 26.4. Left: The inversion symmetry of E major; right: the symmetrically arranged arpeggiated intervals 1,2,3,4,5 in measures 173-174. Intervals 1,4,5 are symmetric, and intervals 2,3 correspond to each other by the E-major symmetry.
not be astonished if this fact were also a conscious component of Beethoven’s approach to tonality, but we do not know. The structures, however, confirm this hypothesis. Summarizing, the ‘colimit’ variation six shows an explosion of the theme that is dissolved in a burning rotation of that trill, which expresses the basic tonality by its unique inversional inner symmetry.
Fig. 26.5. The sequence of interval arpeggios is arranged with high symmetry with respect to the E-major symmetry If ♯ = Ib/c♯ , see also Figure 26.4.
In terms of creativity, we have interpreted the sixth movement as a creative target issued from the characteristic wall extensions of the first five variations of the critical theme X. But we also learned that variation can mean very different things in music. Whereas Mozart’s approach in “Ah, vous dirai-je Maman” is a view from outside, extensive only in the sense that the theme
310
26 Ludwig van Beethoven’s Sonata opus 109: Six Variations
to be varied is taken for granted and then serves as a skeleton model that is dressed by a selection of ‘clothes,’ Beethoven’s approach intensive—he looks into the ‘anatomy’ of the theme and searches for its substance. In the CD Passionate Message as described in chapter 23, Joomi Park and Guerino Mazzola have also composed and performed a series of variations, and of multiple variations in soli and duos. All these variations were realized in Beethoven’s spirit. This connection to the first case study gives us a good completion of our series of case studies, beginning and ending with a description of creative work in musical variations.
Part V
References, Index
References
1. Adorno Th W: Zu einer Theorie der musikalischen Reproduktion. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt/M. 2001 2. Albert R S and M A Runco: A History of Research on Creativity. In: R J Sternberg (ed.): Handbook of Creativity. Cambridge University Press, New York 1999 3. Agust´ın Aquino O A: Counterpoint in 2k-tone equal temperament. Journal of Mathematics and Music, Vol. 3, nr. 3, pp. 153–164, 2009 4. Aleinikov A G: On Creative Pedagogy. Higher Education Bulletin, 12, 29–34, 1989 5. Assayag G and S Dubnov: Using Factor Oracles for Machine Improvisation. Soft Computing 8, pp. 1432–7643, September 2004 ¨ 6. Assmann J: Sch¨ opfungsmythen und Kreativit¨ atskonzepte im Alten Agypten. In: R M Holm-Hadulla (ed.): Kreativit¨ at. Springer, Heidelberg 2000 7. Baer J and J C Kaufman: Creativity Research in English-Speaking Countries. J C Kaufman and R J Sternberg (eds.): The International Handbook of Creativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 10–38, 2006 8. Bahle J: Der musikalische Schaffensprozess. Psychologie der sch¨ opferischen Erlebnis- und Antriebsformen. S Hirzel, Leipzig 1936 9. Bars I: Extra Dimensions in Space and Time (Multiversal Journeys). Springer, Heidelberg 2009 10. Becker M: Nineteenth Century Foundations of Creativity Research. Creativity Research Journal, Vol. 8, pp. 219–229, 1995 11. Bednarik R G: A Figurine from the African Acheulian. Current Anthropology, Vol. 44:3, pp. 405–413, 2003 12. Boden M A: The Creative Mind: Myths and Mechanisms. Routledge, London 2004 13. Boden M A: Creativity & Art. Oxford University Press, Oxford 2010 14. Borgo D: Sync or Swarm. Continuum International Publishing Group 2006 15. Boissi`ere A: Geste, interpr´etation, invention selon Pierre Boulez. Revue DEM´eter, d`ec. 2002, Univ. Lille-3 16. Bott J, J Crowley, J LaViola Jr: Exploring 3D Gestural Interfaces for Music Creation in Video Games. CFDG 2009 April 26–30, 2009, Orlando 2009 17. Boulez P: structures, premier livre. UE, London 1953 18. Boulez P: structures, deuxi´eme livre. UE, London 1967 G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
313
314
References
19. Boulez P: Jalons (dix ans d’enseignement au Coll`ege de France). Bourgeois, Paris 1989 20. Butsch C and H Fischer: Seashore-Test f¨ ur musikalische Begabung. Huber, Bern/Stuttgart 1966 21. Cage J: ASLSP. http://www.john-cage.halberstadt.de 22. Cavaill`es J: M´ethode axiomatique et formalisme, Hermann 1938 23. Chˆ atelet G: Figuring Space. Kluwer 2000 24. Cherlin M: Memory and Rhetorical Trope in Schoenberg’s String Trio. Journal of the American Musicological Society, 51/3, pp. 559–602, fall 1998 25. Cook P: http://www.cs.princeton.edu/~prc/SingingSynth.html 26. Cook N: Playing God: Creativity, Analysis, and Aesthetic Inclusion. In: I Deli`ege and G A Wiggins (eds.): Musical Creativity: Multidisciplinary Research in Theory and Practice. Psychology Press, Hove/New York, pp. 9–24, 2006 27. Cooley J W and J W Tuckey: An Algorithm for the Machine Calculation of Complex Series. Math. Comput. 19, 297–301 1965 28. Cope D: Virtual Music: Computer Synthesis of Musical Style. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA 2001 29. Cope D: Computer Models of Musical Creativity. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA 2005 30. Cs´ıkszentmih´ alyi M: Beyond Boredom and Anxiety. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco 1975 31. Cs´ıkszentmih´ alyi M: Society, Culture, and Person: A Systems View of Creativity. In: R J Sternberg (ed.): The Nature of Creativity: Contemporary Psychological Perspectives. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 325–339, 1988 32. Cs´ıkszentmih´ alyi M: The Psychology of Optimal Experience. Harper and Row, New York 1990 33. Cs´ıkszentmih´ alyi M: Creativity: Flow and the Psychology of Discovery and Invention. HarperCollins, New York 1996 34. Dacey J S and K Lennon: Understanding Creativity: The Interplay of Biological, Psychological, and Social Factors. Josey-Bass, San Francisco, 1998 35. Deyoung L: Pitch Order and Duration Order in Boulez Structure 1a. PNM 16/2: 27–34, 1978 36. Drake R M: Drake Musical Aptitude Tests. Science Research Associates, Chicago 1954 37. Duffy M and S Tsuda: Shield Your Eyes Sonic Anarchy. The Sonic Alchemists, Minneapolis 2010 ¨ 38. Ehrenfels Chr von: Uber Gestaltqualit¨ aten. Vierteljahresschrift f¨ ur wissenschaftliche Philosophie XIV, 1890 39. Eimert H: Grundlagen der musikalischen Reihentechnik. Universal Edition, Wien 1964 40. Ericson K: Heinz Holliger. Spurensuche eines Grenzg¨ angers. Peter Lang, Bern 2004 41. Felver Chr: Cecil Taylor – All The Notes. A Chris Felver Movie, 2003 42. Finke R A, Th B Ward, S M Smith: Creative Cognition: Theory, Research, and Applications. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA 1992 43. Florida R: The Rise of the Creative Class. Basic Books, 2003 44. Fux J J: Gradus ad Parnassum (1725). Dt. und kommentiert von L. Mitzler, Leipzig 1742
References
315
45. Galenson D W: Old Masters and Young Geniuses: The Two Life Cycles of Creativity. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ 2006 46. Gardner H: Kreative Intelligenz: Was wir mit Mozart, Freud, Woolf und Gandhi gemeinsam haben (Translated by Andreas Simon). Campus Verlag, Frankfurt/New York 1999 47. Grisey G: Tempus ex machina: A Composer’s Reflections on Musical Time. Contemporary Music Review 2, no. 1:238–275, 1987 48. H´ aba A: Neue Harmonielehre.(Reprint from 1927) Universal Edition, Wien 1978 49. Hanslick E: Vom Musikalisch-Sch¨ onen. Breitkopf und H¨ artel (1854), Wiesbaden 1980 50. Hayes J R: Cognitive Processes in Creativity. In: J A Glover, R R Roning, C R Reynolds (eds.): Handbook of Creativity. Plenum, New York 1989 51. Hawking S: A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes. Bantam Books, New York 1988 52. Hjelmslev L: La Stratification du Langage. Minuit, Paris 1954 53. Hofstadter D R: Staring Emmy Straight in the Eye—and Doing my Best not to Flinch. In: D Cope (ed.): Virtual Music: Computer Synthesis of Musical Style. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA 2001 54. Holm-Hadulla R M: Kreativit¨ at. Konzept und Lebensstil. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, G¨ ottingen 2005 55. Hosken D: An Introduction to Music Technology. Routledge, New York 2011 56. Howe M J A: Prodigies and Creativity. In: R J Sternberg (ed.): Handbook of Creativity. Cambridge University Press, New York 1999 57. Hull P et al.: The Music Business and Recording Industry. Third Edition. Routledge, New York and London 2011 58. Jakobson R: Linguistics and Poetics. In: T A Seboek (ed.): Style in Language. Wiley, New York 1960 59. Johnson-Laird P N: Freedom and Constraint in Creativity. In: R J Sternberg (ed.): The Nature of Creativity: Contemporary Psychological Perspectives. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 202–219, 1988 60. Junod J: Counterpoint Worlds and Morphisms. Dissertation, University of Zurich, Zurich 2010 61. Kinderman W: Artaria 195. University of Illinois Press, Urbana and Chicago 2003 62. Kozbelt A, R A Beghetto, M A Runco: Theories of Creativity. In: J C Kaufman and R J Sternberg (eds.): The Cambridge Handbook of Creativity. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 20–47, 2010 63. Kronland-Martinet R: The Wavelet Transform for Analysis, Synthesis, and Processing of Speech and Music Sounds. Computer Music Journal, 12 (4), 1988 64. Lachenmann H: Mouvement (- vor der Erstarrung) f¨ ur Ensemble. Breitkopf und H¨ artel, 1984 65. Langley P, H A Simon, G L Bradshaw, J M Zytkow: Scientific Discovery: Computational Explorations of the Creative Process. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1987 66. Lerdahl F: Cognitive Constraints on Compositional Systems. In: J Sloboda (ed.): Generative Processes in Music. Oxford University Press, Oxford 1988. Reprinted in Contemporary Music Review 6, no. 2 (1992):97–121 67. Ligeti G: Pierre Boulez: Entscheidung und Automatik in der Structure Ia. Die Reihe IV, UE, Wien 1958
316
References
68. Ligeti G and G Neuweiler: Motorische Intelligenz. Wagenbach, Berlin 2007 69. Losada C: Isography and Structure in the Music of Boulez. Journal of Mathematics and Music 2008, Vol. 2, no. 3, pp. 135–155, 2008 70. Ledderose L: Kreativit¨ at und Schrift in China. In: R M Holm-Hadulla (ed.): Kreativit¨ at. Springer, Heidelberg 2000 71. Mazzola G: Gruppen und Kategorien in der Musik. Heldermann, Berlin 1985 72. Mazzola G: Geometrie der T¨ one. Birkh¨ auser, Basel 1990 73. Mazzola G: Synthesis. SToA 1001.90, Z¨ urich 1990 74. Mazzola G and O Zahorka: The RUBATO Performance Workstation on NeXTSTEP. In: ICMA (ed.): Proceedings of the ICMC 94, San Francisco 1994 75. Mazzola G et al.: RUBATO on the Internet. http://www.rubato.org 1996 ff. 76. Mazzola G: Semiotic Aspects of Musicology: Semiotics of Music. In: R Posner et al. (eds.): A Handbook on the Sign-Theoretic Foundations of Nature and Culture. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin and New York 1998 77. Mazzola G: The Topos of Music. Birkh¨ auser 2002 78. Mazzola G et al.: The Topos of Music—Geometric Logic of Concepts, Theory, and Performance. Birkh¨ auser, Basel et al. 2002 79. Mazzola G: L’essence du bleu. Acanthus 2002 80. Mazzola G, G Milmeister, J Weissmann: Comprehensive Mathematics for Computer Scientists, Vols. I, II; 700 pp. Springer, Heidelberg et al. 2004 81. Mazzola G: Elemente der Musikinformatik. Birkh¨ auser, Basel et al. 2006 82. Mazzola G: La v´erit´e du beau dans la musique. Delatour, Paris 2007 83. Mazzola G and M Andreatta: From a Categorical Point of View: K-nets as Limit Denotators. Perspectives of New Music, Vol. 44, No. 2, 2006 84. Mazzola G and M Andreatta: Diagrams, Gestures, and Formulas in Music. Journal of Mathematics and Music 2007, Vol. 1, no. 1, 2007 85. Mazzola G and P B Cherlin: Flow, Gesture, and Spaces in Free Jazz—Towards a Theory of Collaboration. Springer Series Computational Music Science, Heidelberg et al. 2009 86. Mazzola G et al.: Topos Theory for a Creative Analysis of Boulez’s Structures. In: S Naimpally, G Di Maio (eds.): Quaderni di Matematica, Theory and Applications of Proximity, Nearness and Uniformity, Vol. 23, 2009 87. Mazzola G: Categorical Gestures, the Diamond Conjecture, Lewin’s Question, and the Hammerklavier Sonata. Journal of Mathematics and Music Vol. 3, no. 1, 2009 88. Mazzola G, C Losada, F Thalmann, S Tsuda: Topos Theory for a Creative Analysis of Boulez’s Structures. In: S Naimpally, G Di Maio (eds.): Quaderni di Matematica, Theory and Applications of Proximity, Nearness and Uniformity, Vol 23, 2009 89. Mazzola G: Musical Performance—A Comprehensive Approach: Theory, Analytical Tools, and Case Studies. Springer Series Computational Music Science, Heidelberg et al. December 2010 90. Merker B H: Layered Constraints on the Multiple Creativities of Music. In: I Deli`ege and G A Wiggins (eds.): Musical Creativity: Multidisciplinary Research in Theory and Practice. Psychology Press, Hove/New York, pp. 25–41, 2006 91. Milmeister G: The Rubato Composer Music Software: Component-Based Implementation of a Functorial Concept Architecture. Springer Series Computational Music Science, Heidelberg 2009 92. http://forumnet.ircam.fr/701.html
References
317
93. http://www.nime.org 94. Owens Th: Bebop: The Music and the Players. Oxford University Press, New York 1995 95. Parker W: Conversations. Rogueart, 2011 96. Penrose R: The Road to Reality. Vintage, London 2002 97. Merleau-Ponty M: Ph´enom´enologie de la perception. Gallimard 1945 98. Ramachandran V S: Mirror Neurons and imitation learning as the driving force behind the great leap forward in human evolution. See: http://www.edge.org/3rd_culture/ramachandran/ramachandran_p6.html 99. Rauchfleisch U: Musik sch¨ opfen, Musik h¨ oren. Ein psychologischer Zugang. Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, G¨ ottingen and Z¨ urich 1996 100. Reti R: The Thematic Process in Music (1951). Greenwood Press, Westport 2nd ed. 1978 101. Runco M A and I Chand: Cognition and Creativity. Educational Psychology Review, Vol. 7:3, pp. 243–267, 1995 102. Sachs K-J: Der Contrapunctus im 14. und 15. Jahrhundert. AMW, Franz Steiner, Wiesbaden 1974 103. Sawyer R K: Improvisation and the creative process: Dewey, Collingwood, and the aesthetics of spontaneity. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 58, pp. 149–161, 2000 104. Sawyer R K: Group Creativity: Music, Theater, Collaboration. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah 2003 105. Seashore C E: Psychology of Music. McGraw-Hill, New York 1938 106. Simondon G: Du mode d’existence des objets techniques. Aubier, Paris 1989 107. Sch¨ onberg A: Harmonielehre (1911). Universal Edition, Wien 1966 108. Sch¨ onberg A: Fundamentals of Musical Composition. Edited by Gerald Strang, with an introduction by Leonard Stein. St. Martin’s Press, New York 1967 109. Simonton D K: Thematic fame, melodic originality, and musical zeitgeist: A biographical and transhistorical content analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 38, pp. 972–983, 1980 110. Simonton D K: Thesaurus of scales and melodic patterns. Coleman-Ross Company, New York 1947 111. Spanier E H: Algebraic Topology. McGraw-Hill, New York et al. 1966 112. Sternberg R J and T I Lubart: The Concept of Creativity: Prospects and Paradigms. In: R J Sternberg (ed.): Handbook of Creativity. Cambridge University Press, New York 1999 113. Stravinsky I: The Poetics of Music. Harvard University Press 1947 114. Tanaka A: Interaction, Experience, and the Future of Music. In: K O’Hara and B Brown (eds.): Consuming Music Together. Springer, Dordrecht 2006 115. Tatarkiewicz W: A History of Six Ideas: An Essay in Aesthetics. Polish Scientific Publishers, Warszawa 1980 116. Taylor C: Silent Tongues. Freedom 1974 117. Thalmann F: Musical composition with Grid Diagrams of Transformations. Master’s Thesis, University of Bern, Bern 2007 118. Tymoczko D: Mazzola’s Model of Fuxian Counterpoint. In: C Agon, G Assayag, E Amiot, J Bresson, J Mandereau (eds.): Mathematics and Computation in Music. LNAI 6726, Springer, Heidelberg 2011 119. Uhde J: Beethovens Klaviermusik III. Reclam, Stuttgart 1974 ¨ 120. Uhde J and R Wieland: Forschendes Uben. B¨ arenreiter 2002
318
Index
121. Val´ery P: Cahiers I–IV (1894–1914). Celeyrette-Pietri N and Robinson-Val´ery J (eds.), Gallimard, Paris 1987 122. Wallas G: The Art of Thought. Harcourt, New York 1926 123. Weisberg R W: Creativity and Knowledge: A Challenge to Theories. In: R J Sternberg (ed.): Handbook of Creativity. Cambridge University Press, New York 1999 124. Wiggins G et al.: A Framework for Evaluation of Music Representation Systems. Computer Music Journal 17:3, 1993 125. Wiil U K (Ed.): Computer Music Modeling and Retrieval (CMMR 2003). Springer, Heidelberg 2004 126. Wiil U K (Ed.): Computer Music Modeling and Retrieval (CMMR 2004). Springer, Heidelberg 2005 127. Wittgenstein L: Tractatus Logico Philosophicus = Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung, W Ostwald (ed.), Annalen der Naturphilosophie, 14, 1921 128. Zlotin B and A Susman: Creative Pedagogy. Journal of TRIZ. no. 4, pp. 9–17 (in Russian) 1991
Index
A, 171 C(T ), 285 D, 76 GLn (R), 294 H, 177 K, 76 P , 171 P h, 176 Q, 282 S(b, a), 183 ST RG, 227 SA , 282 SD , 282 SL , 282 SP , 282 T t · h, 294 W (t), 181 @X, 157 C, 164 Δ78 , 84 Δ, 195 Δ64 , 80 Δ68 , 80 Δ71 , 80 Δ75 , 80 Δ78 , 80, 83 Δ82 , 80 N, 163 Q, 163 R, 158, 163 Z, 163 Z11 , 284 Z12 , 284
♭, 41, 215 −→ GLn (R), 294 D, 267 T , 267 ♯, 41, 215 Hz (Hertz), 171 Pa (Pascal), 169 dB (Decibel), 171 ez , 197 f , 171, 176 f ∗ g, 211 g(t), 183 k, 176 m, 176 s(t), 183 w(t), 176 x, 176 ℗, 124 ©, 124 3M, 17, 153 A AAC (Advanced Audio Coding), 202 abstraction, 216, 238 acoustics, 169 musical -, 6 ACROE, 184 Adagio movement, 108 ADC (Analog to Digital Conversion), 201 address, 157 change, 285
G. Mazzola et al., Musical Creativity, Computational Music Science, DOI 10.1007/978-3-642-24517-6, © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011
319
320
Index
Adler, Alfred, 136 Adorno, Theodor Wiesengrund, 88, 262, 264 ADSR, 177 aesthesic, 7 aesthesis, 239 aesthetic, 7 needs, 136 aesthetics, 51, 53, 111, 124, 126, 132, 151 affine morphism, 284 agogics, 234, 253 Agust´ın Aquino, Octavio Alberto, 73 AIFF, 202 air pressure, 169 vibration, 173 aleatoric music, 252 Aleinikov, Andrei, 161 algebraic topology, 269 algorithm FFT -, 200 algorithm (Yamaha), 181, 182 all interval row, 96 alteration, 299, 300 Altshuller, Genrich, 162 Amati, 175 Amberol cylinder, 191 amplitude, 171, 176, 177 spectrum, 176 analog, 186 analysis creative -, 279, 281 Schenker -, 230 analytical parameter, 280 anchor, 290 ancient China, 132 Egypt, 132 antecedent, 107 appreciation, 118, 124 appropriate, 145 architecture concept -, 112, 113, 226 Aristotle, 37
art history, 132 articulation, 234 artificial intelligence, 99 artist performing -, 240 artistic presence, 242 ASCII, 227 aspect commercial -, 16, 123 community -, 16, 117 instrumental -, 16 large form -, 16 system -, 16, 93 contrapuntal -, 16 harmonic -, 16, 47 large form -, 107 melodic -, 16, 57 motivational -, 16, 23 pitch -, 16, 37 rhythmical -, 16, 29 associative field, 59, 109 atomic concept, 113 form, 107 instrument, 176, 179 sound, 182, 183 attack, 282 audience, 11, 101, 102, 247 Audio Engineering Society, 217 audio file formats digital -, 203 auditory cortex, 169 masking, 204 nerves, 169 Augustine, Saint, 29 auto-conversation, 120 autocomplementarity symmetry, 79, 80, 289 axis of embodiment, 240 of semiotics, 241 B Baboushka principle, 10
Index Bach, Johann Sebastian, 29, 65, 83, 114, 234, 262 back plate, 175 BACON, 138 Bahle, Julius, 145 Bailey, Derek, 273 balance, 240, 243 band harmonic -, 63, 64 band pass filter, 212 Bars, Itzhak, 242 basis orthonormal -, 199 bass clef, 41 Batteux, Charles, 134 Baud, 219 beat, 30 Beatles, 34, 65, 126, 148 Michelle, 58, 62, 70 Yesterday, 252 beauty, 51, 53, 55, 123 Beethoven, Ludwig van, 4, 25, 29, 31, 48, 70, 85, 123, 131, 165, 173, 234 Diabelli variations, 306 Sonata op. 106 (Hammerklavier), 31, 70, 103, 108, 238, 260, 280, 297 Sonata op. 109, 4, 108, 115, 167, 305 Sonata op. 57 (Appassionata), 149 String Quartet GrosFuge op. 133 B♭-major, 116 String Quartet No. 9, op. 59, No. 3, 116 being needs, 136 Bekker, Paul, 263 belly plate, 175 Bergson, Henri, 135 Berliner, Emile, 191 bifurcation, 276 BigBang rubette, 92, 292, 293, 297 biology, 264 bitonality, 53 bitrate, 203, 207 Blues
321
form, 109 Boccherini, Luigi, 173 Boden, Margaret, 144 body, 243, 267 musician’s -, 240 of sounds, 240 of time, 30, 37, 241, 243, 261 Boissi`ere, Anne, 279, 280 Boissier, Valerie, 154 Boolean calculus, 63, 66 Borgo, David, 273 Bott, Jared, 91 boulette, 289, 292 Boulez, Pierre, 4, 92, 231, 279–282, 292 Structures pour deux pianos, 4, 92, 102, 258, 280 bow, 175 Brandenburg, Karlheinz, 202 bridge, 109, 175 Buddhism, 37, 133 Busoni, Ferrucio, 42 Buteau, Chantal, 57 Byungki Hwang, 34 C cable MIDI -, 219 cadence, 50, 100, 308 Cadence Jazz Records, 188 Cage, John, 26, 169, 214, 236 ASLSP, 169, 214 cantabile, 57 cantus firmus (c.f.), 74, 276 carrier, 181 catastrophe modulation, 238 catechism, 73, 104 category theory, 157 Cavaill`es, Jean, 166, 241, 244, 274 CCRMA, 184 CD, 190, 191, 235 Chˆ atelet, Gilles, 265 Chand, Ivonne, 142 change address -, 285 channel MIDI -, 221 Cherlin, Michael, 110, 237
322
Index
chess automaton, 99 Chladni mode, 175 Chladni, Ernst, 175 chop, 175 Chopin, Fr´ed´eric Second Piano Sonata, 114 chord, 48 Chordis Anima, 184 chords multiplication of -, 290 choreography, 100–102 Chowning, John, 180, 231 chronospectrum, 177 circle vicious -, 112 circular reference, 111, 113, 230 clarinet, 173 class creative -, 162 clef bass -, 41 treble -, 41 Clynes, Manfred, 88 cochlea, 169 coda, 108 cognitive psychology, 143 coherence, 111 col legno, 175 Coleman, Ornette, 169, 273 colimit, 158, 225, 307 form, 229 Coltrane, John, 29, 151, 273 combinational type, 144 combinatorial question, 26 combinatorics, 282 comes, 60, 115 commercial, 117 aspect, 16, 123 value, 237 communication, 5, 7, 101, 117, 200, 217, 239, 258, 262 MIDI -, 219 community, 117 aspect, 16, 117
commutative ring, 228 compact gesture, 216 completeness, 226 complex number, 197 complex number representation of sinusoidal functions, 197 composer, 11 creative -, 166 composition, 86, 166, 176, 233, 236, 258, 260, 279 computer-aided -, 281 dance -, 100 flow chart, 236 instant -, 247 lead sheet -, 234 spectral -, 180 compositional creativity, 147 narrativity, 239 compression, 201 Huffman -, 202 Joint Stereo Coding -, 208 lossless -, 201 lossy -, 201 MP3 -, 201 psychoacoustical -, 202 computational models, 146 computer music, 43 computer-aided composition, 281 concept architecture, 112, 113, 226 atomic -, 113 critical -, 24, 31, 38, 49, 60, 77, 87, 98, 111, 120, 124, 151, 159, 166, 178, 180, 188, 200, 209, 216, 224, 244, 257, 258, 262, 276, 280, 282, 306 conceptual extension, 294 concert pitch, 39 conjecture, Fermat -, 282 conjectures, Weil -, 282 connectivity gestural -, 243
Index connotation, 10 consciouness, 247 consequent, 107 consonant, 47, 54, 74, 76, 165 construction recursive -, 228 universal -, 228 consumerism, 124 contemporary art music, 262 music, 252 theories, 141 content, 7, 111, 186 of music, 48 context, 24, 30, 38, 48, 59, 76, 86, 110, 119, 124, 149, 159, 244 semiotic -, 17 continuous map, 267 contrapuntal aspect, 16 tension, 77, 78, 80 variation, 306 world, 82 convergent production, 137 thinking, 139 convolution, 211 Cook, Nicholas, 146 Cook, Parry, 184 Cooley, James W., 200 coordinate, 227 coordinator, 227 Cope, David, 146 copyright, 124 cortex auditory -, 169 Corti organ, 178 counterpoint, 45, 47, 54, 73, 165, 173, 271, 288 counting, 253 Cox, Catharine, 137 CRC (Cycle Redundancy Check), 205 creatio ex nihilo, 133 creation gestural -, 92 musical -, 165 creative, 164
323
analysis, 279, 281 class, 162 composer, 166 improviser, 166 pedagogy, 15, 161 performance, 242 personality, 147 creativity, viii, 15, 51, 73, 133, 134, 149, 169, 177, 215, 233, 237, 259, 280, 309 compositional -, 147 concept mathematical variant of -, 305 four P’s of -, 141 gestural -, 243 group -, 138, 147 improvisational -, 147, 236, 239, 245 in free jazz, 273 mathematical model of -, 157 musical -, 145 process, 159 recursion in musical -, 239 Western concept of -, 133 creator, 131 critical concept, 24, 31, 38, 49, 60, 77, 87, 98, 111, 120, 124, 151, 159, 166, 178, 180, 188, 200, 209, 216, 224, 244, 257, 258, 262, 276, 280, 282, 306 Crowley, James, 91 Cs´ıkszentmih´ alyi, Mih´ aly, 138, 143, 247 curve tempo, 215 cutoff frequency, 213 D D, 50 D’Alembert, Jean le Rond, 224, 225 Dallapiccola, Luigi, 146 dance, 90, 173, 240, 243, 253 composition, 100 Darwin, Charles, 132, 134, 135 DAT, 190 Dawkins, Richard, 138 Decibel, 171 decomposition orthonormal -, 6 dedication, 120
324
Index
deduction, 279 deficiency needs, 136 deformation, 59, 66, 81, 114, 182, 299 deliverer role, 88 denotator, 150, 214, 224, 233 name, 227 Descartes, 259 detonation, 280 development, 108 developmental sentence, 107 diachronic, 110, 119, 239 dialogue inner -, 259 dichotomy, 165 imaginary -, 81 major -, 80 strong -, 80 Diderot, Denis, 134, 224, 225 digital, 186 audio file formats, 203 encoding of music, 191 digraph, 267 dilation, 294 directed graph, 267 discantus, 74, 276 discourse, 226 dissonant, 47, 50, 74, 76, 165 distributed identity, 242 divergent production, 137 thinking, 139 divine time, 152 dodecaphonic row, 94, 240 dodecaphonism, 52, 93, 95 Dolphy, Eric, 245 dominant, 50 dream, 146 dress-body metaphor, 109 Duff, William, 134 duration, 30, 172, 177, 215, 253, 282 dux, 60, 115 DX7 (Yamaha), 180
Dylan, Bob, 126 dynamics, 234 E ear, 188 eardrum, 39 Edison, Thomas, 190 educational methodology, 161 Ehrenfels, Christian von, 59 Eimert, Herbert, 214 Einstein, Albert, viii, 19, 26, 150, 254, 260 electrical circuit simulation of acoustical configurations, 213 electromagnetic encoding of music, 185 electronic music, 252 embodiment, 5, 9, 111, 259, 261, 262 axis of -, 240 emergent property, 231, 242 Emmy, 146 encoding of music, 189 Encyclop´edie, 225 Enlightenment, 134 envelope, 177, 178, 180, 182 EQ, 212 Ericsson, K. Anders, 148 Escher Theorem, 78, 155, 267, 270 Escher, Maurits Cornelis, 4, 272 Euler, Leonhard, 54, 79, 197 event sound -, 217 evolution, 132 exchange gestural -, 264 experiment, 280 exploratory type, 144 exponential function, 197 exposition, 108, 114 expression, 7, 173 poetical -, 111
Index extension conceptual -, 294 semiotic -, 150 F fact, 9 facticity, 264 family of violins, 174, 184 supportive -, 148 Faust, 125 Fermat conjecture, 282 fermata, 215 FFT algorithm, 200 FFT (Fast Fourier Transform), 195, 196 Fibonacci sequence, 260 field associative -, 59, 109 fifth perfect -, 44, 79 fifths forbidden parallels of -, 81 filter, 212 band pass -, 212 high pass -, 212 high shelf -, 212 low pass -, 212 low shelf -, 212 notch -, 212 Finale movement, 108 finder, 144 finite Fourier analysis, 193 first piano, 286 first species, 74 five-stage model, 136 flow, 144, 151, 241, 243 semiotic - process, 242 flute, 173 FM, 172, 180 forbidden parallels of fifths, 81 form, 111, 227 atomic -, 107 Blues -, 109 colimit -, 229
325
large -, 107, 109, 110 limit -, 228 name, 227 powerset, 230 rhetorical -, 108 simple -, 227 sonata -, 107 song -, 109 type, 227 formula, 100 Fourier -, 198 four P’s of creativity, 141 Fourier, 172 analysis finite -, 193 formula, 198 spectrum, 191 theorem, 6, 176, 177 transform, 210 Fourier, Jean Baptiste Joseph, 6, 176, 180 fourth perfect -, 44, 79 frame header, 206 MP3 -, 205 free improvisation, 151 free atonal music, 93 free jazz, 35, 242, 252, 253, 267 creativity in -, 273 frequency, 39, 176 cutoff -, 213 modulation, 180 Nyquist -, 196 sample -, 195 sampling -, 203 vanishing -, 210 Freud, Sigmund, 136, 146 Fromm, Erich, 136 frozen gesture, 88 Fry, Arthur, 18, 153 fugue, 60, 115 function exponential -, 197 harmonic -, 49, 53 periodic -, 193
326
Index
poetical -, 109 sinusoidal -, 176, 180 functor, 157, 306 functoriality, 285 fundamental group, 247 Fux’s rules, 74 Fux, Johann Joseph, 73, 81, 93, 165, 271 fuzzy harmonic function, 50, 53 logic, 153 G Galenson, David W., 144 Galois theory, 163 Galton, Sir Francis, 135, 136 Gauss, Carl Friedrich, 200 Gen Gan-ru, 125 Geneplore model, 138 general intelligence, 137 genius, 133 Gesamtkunstwerk, 264 gestalt, 59, 135 gestuality, 243, 246 gestural connectivity, 243 creation, 92 creativity, 243 exchange, 264 interface, 91 gesture, 9, 31, 59, 63, 77, 86, 166, 175, 216, 217, 240, 243, 247, 264, 267, 279, 281 compact -, 216 frozen -, 88 network, 244 theory, 267 three-finger -, 92 GIS (Geographic Information Systems), 230 God, 125 Goethe, Wolfgang von, 125 Gould, Glenn, 262 Graci, Baltasar, 134 Gradus ad Parnassum, 73 gradus suavitatis, 54, 79
graph directed -, 267 groove, 30 trap, 274 Grothendieck, Alexander, vii, 282 group creativity, 138, 147 fundamental -, 247 mathematical, 247 standardization -, 202 Grundreihe, 94 Guarneri, 175 Guilford, Joy Paul, 137 H H´ aba, Alois, 42, 43 hall music -, 170 Hanslick, Eduard, 260 harmonic aspect, 16, 47 band, 63, 64 function, 49, 53 fuzzy -, 50, 53 harmony, 45, 47, 77, 173 Harnoncourt, Nikolaus, 167 Hawking, Stephen, 242 Haydn, Joseph, 173 Hayes, John R., 143, 147 header frame -, 206 hearing, 38 threshold, 204 Hertz, 39 Hichert, Jens, 73 high pass filter, 212 high shelf filter, 212 Hindemith, Paul, 146 Hinduism, 37 historical social context of music, 118 history art -, 132 Hjelmslev, Louis, 10, 239 homotopy, 269 Honegger, Arthur, 146 Huffman compression, 202
Index human senses -, 37 voice, 57 hypercube of musical oniontology, 9 hypergesture, 78, 155, 243, 245, 269, 272 I ICMC, 184 identity distributed -, 242 imaginary dichotomy, 81 space-time, 247 imperfect consonance, 74 improvisation, 166, 233, 234, 242, 260 free -, 151 slow motion -, 245 improvisational creativity, 147, 236, 239, 245 improviser, 242 creative -, 166 IN port, 219 induction, 279 industry music -, 124, 262 inner dialogue, 259 inspiration, 131 instant composition, 247 instrument, 173, 184, 288 atomic -, 176, 179 musical -, 85, 86 instrumental aspect, 16 interface, 240 wall, 42 intelligence general -, 137 interdisciplinarity, 264 interface gestural -, 91 instrumental -, 240 Internet, 192 interpreter, 11 interval, 44, 45 invention
327
musical -, 164 IQ, 137 IRCAM, 184, 231 ISC (Intensity Stereo Coding), 208 ISO (Int. Organization for Standardization), 202 isolation wall, 42 J Jackson, Michael, 261 Jagger, Mick, 261 Jakobson, Roman, 109, 114 James, William, 136 jazz free -, 35, 242, 252, 253, 267 Jevons, William S., 134 Johnson, Eldridge R., 191 Johnson, Tom, 99 Formula, 99 Joint Stereo Coding compression, 208 Junod, Julien, 73, 83, 165 K kairos, 243 Keats, George, 51, 53 Kepler laws, 152 Kepler, Johannes, 47, 138, 152, 154 Kinderman, William, 308 King, Emily, viii Kleist, Heinrich von Marionettentheater, 264 Klumpenhouwer-network, 229 knock, 175 knowledge society, 162 Korean traditional music, 53 folk music, 93 Kozbelt, Aaron, 139 Krenek, Ernst, 146 Kris, Ernst, 136 L Laban, Rudolf von, 263 lacking originality, 262
328
Index
language, 162 Lanier, Sidney, 19 large form, 107, 109, 110 aspect, 16, 107 LaViola, Joseph, 91 laws Kepler -, 152 lead sheet composition, 234 Leibowitz, Ren´e, 96 leitfaden, 16 lemma Yoneda -, 157, 284, 302 Lewin, David, 229, 237 life value, 125 Ligeti, Gy¨ orgy, 29, 102, 110, 258, 280–282, 287 Lux Aeterna, 102 limit, 225 form, 228 lips, 173, 184 Liszt, Franz, 154 logic, 111 fuzzy -, 153 logical time, 236, 239, 246 longitudinal wave, 171 Lorentz transformation, 150 Losinger, Ania, 90 lossless compression, 201 lossy compression, 201 loudness, 172, 282 loudspeaker, 171, 186, 189 lour´e, 175 low pass filter, 212 low shelf filter, 212 LP, 189 Lubart, T. I., 145 L ukasiewicz, Jan, 135 Lutoslawski, Witold, 126
M M¨ obius band, 64 M¨ alzel, Johann Nepomuk, 30, 99 MacroScore, 290 major dichotomy, 80 making sound, 172 time, 254 Mao Tse Tung, 125 Mao Tse-tung, 118 map continuous -, 267 Maqam music, 42 marketplace, 123 ´ Martinville, Edouard-L´ eon Scott de, 190 masking auditory -, 204 temporary -, 204 Maslow, Abraham, 136 mass-spring model, 184 mathematical model of creativity, 157 music theory, 165 variant of creativity concept, 305 Mathews, Max, 231 Max MSP, 42, 232 Mazzola, Guerino, vii, 4, 34, 57, 68, 73, 251, 252, 256, 299, 310 L’essence du bleu, 104 Synthesis, 68 Verino qu’es, 252 McLuhan, Marshall, 231, 281 meaning of music, 26, 51, 58, 98, 111 melodic aspect, 16, 57 variation, 306 melody, 57, 58 memes, 138 memory, 137 musical -, 237 memory stick, 190 mental reality, 6
Index Merker, Bj¨ orn, 145, 147 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 265 message MIDI -, 217 MIDI channel -, 221 MIDI Real Time -, 222 MIDI system -, 221 MIDI System common -, 222 MIDI System Exclusive -, 222 message categories MIDI -, 221 metaphor dress-body -, 109 room -, 156 metasystem, 10 method synthesis -, 172 methodology educational -, 161 metronome, 30 mic, 186 mic types condenser, 187 moving coil dynamic, 187 ribbon, 187 Michelangelo, 134 Michelle, 58, 62, 70 microphone system, 171 microtonal, 42 MIDI, 7, 217, 233, 246, 256 cable, 219 channel, 221 channel message, 221 communication, 219 message, 217 message categories, 221 Real Time message, 222 Specification, 217 Standard - File, 218 System common message, 222 System Exclusive message, 222 system message, 221 tick, 222 time, 222 velocity, 221 word, 220 MIDI (Musical Instrument Digital Interface), 214
329
mixer, 186 Modalys, 184 mode, 175 Chladni -, 175 model five-stage -, 136 Geneplore -, 138 mass-spring -, 184 modeling physical -, 172, 184 models computational -, 146 modulation, 52, 77, 244 catastrophe -, 238 frequency -, 180 modulator, 181 module, 228 Molino, Jean, 7 Monk, Thelonious, 50 monochord, 44 Moore, Cooper, 117, 123 morphing, 299 morphism, 157 affine -, 284 motif, 57, 58, 107, 112, 115 three-element -, 68 motion contrary -, 74 direct -, 74 oblique -, 74 motivated semiotics, 10 motivational aspect, 16, 23 movement Adagio -, 108 Finale -, 108 Scherzo -, 108 Mozart, Wolfgang Amadeus, 57, 146, 165, 309 “Ah, vous dirai-je Maman” KV 265, 306 MP3, 192, 202 compression, 201 file identifier, 205 frame, 205 MP4, 202 MPEG (Moving Pictures Experts Group), 202
330
Index
MPEG-1, 202 MPEG-2, 202 MSSC (Mid/Side Stereo Coding), 208 multiplication of chords, 290 Mundry, Isabel, 263 Murray, Sunny, 123 music about music, 114 absolute -, 115 aleatoric -, 252 computer -, 43 contemporary -, 252 contemporary art -, 262 content of -, 48 digital encoding of -, 191 electromagnetic encoding of -, 185 electronic -, 252 encoding of -, 189 free atonal -, 93 hall, 170 industry, 124, 262 Korean folk -, 93 traditional -, 53 Maqam -, 42 meaning of -, 26, 51, 58, 98, 111 paper -, 87, 262 styles, 23 technology, 3 theory mathematical -, 165 universal data format for -, 224 Western art -, 253, 262, 263 music, historical social context of -, 118 musical acoustics, 6 creation, 165 creativity, 145 instrument, 85, 86 invention, 164 memory, 237 oniontology, 5 ontology, 5 performance, 243 reality, 260 story, 58, 98, 102 system, 93, 96 time, 29
musician’s body, 240 Muzak, 118 Muzzulini, Daniel, 73 mysticism, 132 N Nˆ oh, 29, 89 name denotator -, 227 form -, 227 NAMM (National Association of Music Merchants), 217 Nancarrow, Conlon, 123 narrativity compositional -, 239 needs being -, 136 deficiency -, 136 aesthetic -, 136 nerves auditory -, 169 network of gestures, 244 neumes, 88, 100, 216, 233 neuroscience, 6 neutral level, 7 niveau, 186, 240 New Complexity, 89, 262 Music, 262 Simplicity, 262 Newton, Isaac, 150, 176 Newtonian time, 152 NIME, 91 niveau neutral -, 240 Noise Music, 262 nose, 184 notation systems, 40 wall, 42 Western -, 25, 41, 46, 88, 214, 217 notch filter, 212 Note-ON, 221 novelty, 25, 131
Index number complex -, 197 Nyquist frequency, 196 theorem, 196 O objectivization, 237 obstruction psychological -, 164 octave, 44, 183 offset, 215 oniontology, 5, 240 hypercube of musical -, 9 musical -, 5 onset, 172, 177, 215, 253 ontology, 260 musical -, 5 open work, 280 OpenMusic, 232 orchestration, 176 order syntagmatic -, 96 organ Corti -, 178 originality, 263 lacking -, 262 orthogonality relations, 195, 199 orthonormal basis, 199 decomposition, 6 OUT port, 219 overtone, 176, 180 P PAC (Perceptual-Audio-Coding), 204 Palestrina, Giovanni Pierluigi da, 73, 98 paper music, 87, 262 paradigmatic, 59 paralogic, 162 parameter analytical -, 280 primary -, 282 secondary -, 282 Park, Joomi, vii, 4, 67, 251, 252, 256, 258, 310
American Carnival, 252, 256, 263 Black Summer, 67, 83, 252 Parker, Charlie, 147 Parker, William, 117 partial, 6, 176 passion, 123, 257 Passionate Message, 251, 310 path, 287 pause, 30, 33, 35 pedagogy creative -, 15, 161 perfect consonance, 74 fifth, 44, 79 fourth, 44, 79 performance, 214 creative -, 242 musical -, 243 theory, 215, 234 performer, 241 performing artist, 240 period, 107, 171 sample -, 195 periodic function, 193 permutational variation, 306 person, 141 personality creative -, 147 perspective, 158 perspectives variable -, 306 persuasion, 141 phase, 176 spectrum, 176 phonautogram, 190 phonoautograph, 190 phonograph, 190 phrase, 107 physical modeling, 172, 184 reality, 6 time, 236, 241 physics, 260 piano, 40, 43, 57, 86, 90, 154 first -, 286 second -, 286
331
332
Index
Picasso, Pablo, v Pino, Paolo, 134 pitch, 39, 171, 172, 176, 282 aspect, 16, 37 concert -, 39 place, 141, 147 Planck time, 21, 73 plate back -, 175 belly -, 175 pluck, 175 poesy Rhyme -, 109 poetical expression, 111 function, 109 poietic, 7, 186, 201 polyphony, 73 polyrhythm, 35 port IN -, 219 OUT -, 219 THRU -, 219 Porter, Cole, 124 Post-It, 17 postproduction, 189 potential, 141 powerobject, 225 powerset form -, 230 precision, 120 presence, 240, 243 artistic -, 242 Presley, Elvis, 261 pressure air -, 169 primary parameter, 282 principle Baboushka -, 10 problem, 142, 162 -finding theories, 143 -solving theories, 143 solving, 151 process, 8, 141 creativity -, 159 processuality, 264
product, 141, 147 production convergent -, 137 divergent -, 137 property emergent -, 231, 242 proximity, 66 psychoacoustical compression, 202 psychoanalysis, 146 psychological obstruction, 164 reality, 6 psychology, 135 cognitive -, 143 punctus contra punctum, 76, 78 Pythagoreans, 44, 47, 131 Q quartet string -, 173, 175 question combinatorial -, 26 open -, 17, 24, 29, 37, 48, 58, 75, 86, 96, 118, 124, 149, 159, 183, 209, 244, 258 R Raga, 53, 93 RAM, 190 Ramachandran, Vilayanur S., 166 Rank, Otto, 136 rate sample -, 191 realities, 5, 6 reality mental -, 6 musical -, 260 physical -, 6 psychological -, 6 recapitulation, 108, 114 recursion in musical creativity, 239 recursive construction, 228 reed, 173 reference circular -, 111, 113, 230 reflection, 294
Index regression, 136 relations orthogonality -, 195, 199 relevance, 120 religion, 132 Renaissance, 131 reservoir technique, 206 responsibility, 35, 101, 254, 256 Reti, Rudolf, 57 revelation, 131 rhetorical form, 108 Rhyme poesy, 109 rhythm, 31 rhythmical aspect, 16, 29 variation, 306 ride the horse, 35, 257 Riemann, Hugo, 50, 51, 53, 55, 76 ring commutative -, 228 Risset, Jean-Claude, 231 RLE (Run Length Encoding), 201 Rogers, Carl, 136 ROM, 190 room metaphor, 156 rotation, 65, 294 row all interval -, 96 dodecaphonic -, 94, 240 tone -, 94 RUBATO , 53, 214, 224, 279, 288 rubette BigBang -, 92, 292, 293, 297 rules system -, 98 Runco, Mark A., 142 S S, 50 Sachs, Klaus-J¨ urgen, 277 Saint Victor, Hugues de, 267 sample frequency, 195 period, 195 rate, 191
333
sampling frequency, 203 Sanders, Pharoah, 43 Sarbiewsky, Maciej Kazimierz, 134 satellite, 290 sautill´e, 175 Sawyer, Keith, 147, 151, 247 saxophone, 43 Say, Fazil, 91 scale, 41 C-major -, 50 Schenker analysis, 230 Schenker, Heinrich, 146 Scherzo movement, 108 Schnittke, Alfred, 114 Symphony No. 1, 114 Schoenberg, Arnold, 52, 53, 63, 77, 85, 93, 97, 102, 111, 117, 120, 146, 236, 240, 244, 246, 258, 281 op. 33, 95 string quartet op. 10, 114 string trio op. 45, 237 Waltz for Piano, op. 23 no. 5, 93 Schuppanzigh, Ignaz, 173 score, 11, 25, 34, 214, 233, 253, 262 Scriabin, Alexander, 29 Piano Sonata, op. 72 (Vers la flamme), 116 Seashore, Carl E., 146 second piano, 286 secondary parameter, 282 seeker, 144 Seitzer, Dieter, 202 self, 259 self-referential, 244 semantics, 48, 51, 52, 55, 110 semiotic extension, 150 flow process, 242 semiotics, 5, 8, 48, 110, 119, 149, 162 axis of -, 241 motivated -, 10 senses human, 37 sentence
334
Index
developmental -, 107 serialism, 52, 93, 252, 280 seriousness, 120, 237 Sessions, Roger, 88 shearing, 294 shuffle, 175 sign critical -, 17 signification, 7 Silver, Spencer, 17, 153 similarity, 66 Simondon, Gilbert, 279 Simonton, Dean Keith, 138, 145 simple form -, 227 singer synthesis, 184 sinusoidal functions complex number representation of -, 197 function, 176, 180 Sirone, 123 skeleton, 267 slave, 218 slow motion improvisation, 245 Smirnov, Andrey, 91 Smith, Dave, 217 society knowledge -, 162 solving problem -, 151 sonata form, 107 song form, 109 songwriter, 124 sound, 169 atomic -, 182, 183 event, 217 making -, 172 source, 169 sounds body of -, 240 source sound -, 169 space, 240 topological -, 267
space-time imaginary -, 247 spectral composition, 180 spectrum amplitude -, 176 Fourier -, 191 phase -, 176 sphere, 287 spontaneity, 242 staff, 41 Standard MIDI File, 218 standardization, 217, 272 group, 202 startbit, 220 status word, 220 Sternberg, Robert, 131, 145 Stockhausen, Karlheinz, 146 Klavierst¨ uck IX, 260 stopbit, 220 story musical -, 58, 98, 102 Stradivari, 175 Strauss Jr, Johann Blue Danube waltz, 114 string, 175 quartet, 173, 175 theory, 47 strong dichotomy, 80 Studio f¨ ur elektronische Musik, 214 style Venetian polychoral -, 171 styles music -, 23 subdominant, 50 sublimation, 136 substance, 227, 310 super-summativity, 59 support, 177 supportive family, 148 Susman, Alla, 162 syllabus, 21 symbolic time, 236, 237 symmetry
Index autocomplementarity -, 79, 80, 289 synchronic, 119, 239 syntagm, 48, 59, 109, 237, 239 syntagmatic order, 96 synthesis method, 172 singer -, 184 synthesizer, 218 system aspect, 16, 93 microphone -, 171 musical -, 93, 96 rules, 98 systems theories, 144 T T, 50 Taoism, 133 tape, 190 Taylor, Cecil, 29, 34, 35, 90, 117, 120, 123, 154, 165, 252, 256–258, 273, 283 Tchaikovsky, Peter, B♭-minor Piano Concerto, 114 technique reservoir -, 206 tempo, 30, 215, 253 curve, 215 temporary masking, 204 tension contrapuntal -, 77, 78, 80 Terman, Lewis, 137 tetractys, 47 Thalmann, Florian, viii, 92, 293 theme, 57 Theorem Escher -, 78, 155, 267, 270 theorem Fourier -, 6, 176, 177 Nyquist -, 196 theories contemporary -, 141 problem-finding -, 143 problem-solving -, 143 systems -, 144 theory
335
category -, 157 Galois -, 163 gesture -, 267 performance -, 215, 234 string -, 47 topos -, 157, 283, 302 transformational -, 237 thinking convergent -, 139 divergent -, 139 three-element motif, 68 three-finger gesture, 92 threshold hearing -, 204 throat, 184 THRU port, 219 tick MIDI -, 222 time, 33, 150, 236, 253 body of -, 30, 37, 241, 243, 261 divine -, 34, 152 logical -, 236, 239, 246 making -, 254 MIDI -, 222 musical -, 29 Newtonian -, 152 physical -, 236, 241 Planck -, 21, 73 signature, 30, 34, 35 symbolic -, 236, 237 Tinctoris, Johannes, 134 to apply, 100 to play, 87, 100 tonality, 50, 52, 53 tone row, 94 tonic, 50 topological space, 267 topology, 267, 279 algebraic -, 269 topos, 225 theory, 157, 283, 302 Torrance Tests of Creative Thinking, 137 Torrance, E. Paul, 137 torus, 287
336
Index
transduction, 279, 288 transform Fourier -, 210 transformation, 59, 65, 98, 114, 294 Lorentz -, 150 transformational theory, 237 type, 145 translation, 294 trap groove -, 274 treble clef, 41 triad, 50, 53 trill, 290, 308 TRIZ (=Theory of Inventive Problem Solving), 162 trumpet, 173, 177 truth, 51, 53, 111 Tsuda, Schuyler, 299 Tuckey, John W., 200 tuning, 215 well-tempered -, 44 tutorial, vii, 3, 15, 23, 166 type combinational -, 144 exploratory -, 144 form -, 227 transformational -, 145 U Uhde, J¨ urgen, 305–307 unity, 226 universal construction, 228 data format for music, 224 V Val´ery, Paul, 7 value commercial -, 237 life -, 125 vanishing frequency, 210 variable perspectives, 306 variation contrapuntal -, 306 melodic -, 306
permutational -, 306 rhythmical -, 306 velocity MIDI -, 221 Venetian polychoral style, 171 Venus of Hohle Fels, 132 of Tan-Tan, 132 vibration air -, 173 vicious circle, 112 violin, 40, 43, 85, 90, 169, 175, 184 violins family of -, 174, 184 virtuosity, 185 visualization of walls, 155 VL-1 (Yamaha), 184 voice, 173 human -, 57 W Wagner, Richard, 264 waiter role, 111 wall, 162, 170, 171, 178, 180, 238, 253, 259, 263, 264 instrumental -, 42 isolation -, 42 notation -, 42 visualization of -, 155 wall (physical), 170 Wallas, Graham, 135, 142 wallpaper, 295 walls, 17, 25, 33, 39, 49, 51, 77, 88, 99, 111, 120, 125, 152, 159, 188, 194, 200, 209, 216, 224, 244, 257, 258, 262, 276, 280, 282, 306 extended -, 17, 27, 34, 43, 45, 53, 66, 79, 89, 101, 113, 121, 126, 157, 159, 178, 280, 309 open -, 159 wave, 176 longitudinal -, 171 wavelet, 172, 182 Weil conjectures, 282 Weisberg, Robert W., 148 well-tempered tuning, 44
Index Western art music, 253, 262, 263 notation, 25, 41, 46, 88, 214, 217 Wieland, Renate, 88, 268 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 8 Wood, Chet, 217 word MIDI -, 220 status -, 220 work, 11, 131 open -, 280 world contrapuntal -, 82 X XALA, 90
Xenakis, Iannis, 63, 126 Nomos Alpha, 63 Y Yamaha, 180 Yoneda lemma, 157, 284, 302 Yoneda, Nobuo, 284 Z Zahorka, Oliver, 57 Zlotin, Boris, 162 zone, 247 Zuccari, Federico, 134
337