139 106 1MB
English Pages [82] Year 2024
Priest
To come
The Philosophy of Mathematics
About the Series This Cambridge Elements series provides an extensive overview of the philosophy of mathematics in its many and varied forms. Distinguished authors will provide an up-to-date summary of the results of current research in their fields and give their own take on what they believe are the most significant debates influencing research, drawing original conclusions.
Cover image: CTRd / Getty Images
Series Editors Penelope Rush University of Tasmania Stewart Shapiro The Ohio State University
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Mathematical Pluralism
Mathematical Pluralism Graham Priest
ISSN 2399-2883 (online) ISSN 2514-3808 (print)
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Elements in the Philosophy of Mathematics edited by
Penelope Rush University of Tasmania
Stewart Shapiro The Ohio State University
MATHEMATICAL PLURALISM Graham Priest
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
City University of New York University of Melbourne Ruhr University of Bochum
Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB2 8EA, United Kingdom One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia 314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre, New Delhi – 110025, India 103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467 Cambridge University Press is part of Cambridge University Press & Assessment, a department of the University of Cambridge. We share the University’s mission to contribute to society through the pursuit of education, learning and research at the highest international levels of excellence. www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781009500968 DOI: 10.1017/9781009091640 © Graham Priest 2024 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment. When citing this work, please include a reference to the DOI 10.1017/9781009091640 First published 2024
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library. ISBN 978-1-009-50096-8 Hardback ISBN 978-1-009-09541-9 Paperback ISSN 2399-2883 (online) ISSN 2514-3808 (print) Cambridge University Press & Assessment has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
Mathematical Pluralism Elements in the Philosophy of Mathematics DOI: 10.1017/9781009091640 First published online: March 2024
Graham Priest City University of New York University of Melbourne Ruhr University of Bochum Author for correspondence: Graham Priest, [email protected]
Abstract: Mathematical pluralism is the view that there is an irreducible plurality of pure mathematical structures, each with its own internal logics, and that qua pure mathematical structures they are all equally legitimate. Mathematical pluralism is a relatively new position on the philosophical landscape. This Element provides an introduction to the position. Keywords: mathematical pluralism, mathematical foundationalism, mathematical objects, applied mathematics, non-classical logic © Graham Priest 2024
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
ISBNs: 9781009500968 (HB), 9781009095419 (PB), 9781009091640 (OC) ISSNs: 2399-2883 (online), 2514-3808 (print)
Contents
1
From the Foundations of Mathematics to Mathematical Pluralism
2
An Examination of Mathematical Pluralism
22
3
Applied Mathematics
41
4
Matters of Logic
55
References
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
5
66
Mathematical Pluralism
1
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Foreword Since I came to philosophy from mathematics, my first philosophical love was the philosophy of mathematics. I have acquired many other philosophical interests since then; but I have never lost a philosophical interest, and every new interest makes the old interests richer. So it is that I have regularly returned to the philosophy of mathematics, seeing old issues in new lights. In fact, over the years, I think my views on the philosophy of mathematics have changed more than those concerning any other area of philosophy. I was never sympathetic to platonism;1 but the landscape of the philosophy of mathematics (to say nothing of the rest of philosophy) has changed substantially in the last 50 years, and (it seems to me) there are now much better ways of framing an anti-platonist view. In particular, over the last 10 years or so I have become sympathetic to mathematical pluralism. So when Penny Rush and Stewart Shapiro approached me to write a short Element on the topic in their Philosophy of Mathematics Cambridge Elements Series, I was very happy to accept. This provided a welcome opportunity to attempt to weld a number of things I have written on the topic in the last few years into a (hopefully!) coherent whole. These are referenced in what follows.2 Section 1 largely reproduces Priest (2019a), and Section 3 largely reproduces Priest (202+a). I am grateful to the editors and publishers of those pieces for permission to reuse the material. Many thanks go to a number of friends who, in commenting on earlier drafts of the manuscript, parts thereof, or in conversation, gave me valuable thoughts and criticisms. These include Justin Clarke-Doane, Hartry Field, Will Nava, Lavinia Picollo, Andrew Tedder, and Elia Zardini. Thanks go to Joel Hamkins for technical help on set theory. I taught a course on the philosophy of mathematics at the CUNY Graduate Center in the Spring semester, 2022, where my students read (amongst other things) a draft manuscript and gave me valuable comments and criticisms. Many thanks go to them too. A special thanks goes to Stewart Shapiro. Stewart read what I expected to be essentially the final draft of the manuscript, and his perceptive comments and suggestions led to the current improved version.
1 2
As can be seen from Priest (1973). My first foray into the area was Priest (2013a).
Philosophy of Mathematics
2
Preface One may hold there to be a unity to mathematics; that is, that there is one overarching framework into which all of (true) mathematics fits. I doubt that one finds this view in the history of mathematics before the twentieth century. At least before Descartes, there was a pretty rigid distinction between arithmetic (the investigations of numbers) and geometry (the investigation of spatial relations). And after the invention/discovery of non-Euclidean geometries, there was, I think, no sense that they could all be subsumed under a unifying framework before Riemann. In the twentieth century, the view that there was such a unity to mathematics did, however, become orthodox. The unifying framework was that of Zermelo– Fraenkel set theory – usually, with the Axiom of Choice – ZFC. That ZFC played this role emerged from studies in the foundations of mathematics in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. As one highly respected philosopher of mathematics, Penelope Maddy, describes this moment in the history of mathematics/philosophy:3 The view of set theory as a foundation for mathematics emerged early in the thinking of the originators of the theory and is now a pillar of contemporary orthodoxy. As such, it is enshrined in the opening pages of most recent textbooks; to take a few illustrative examples:
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
All branches of mathematics are developed, consciously or unconsciously, in set theory. (Levy (1979), 3) Set theory is the foundation of mathematics. All mathematical concepts are defined in terms of the primitive notions of set and membership . . . From [the] axioms, all known mathematics may be derived. (Kunen (1980), xi) [M]athematical objects (such as numbers and differentiable functions) can be defined to be certain sets. And the theorems of mathematics (such as the fundamental theorem of calculus) then can be viewed as statements about sets. Furthermore, these theorems will be provable from our axioms. Hence, our axioms provide a sufficient collection of assumptions for the development of the whole of mathematics – a remarkable fact. (Enderton (1977), 10–11) From its Cantorian beginnings through its modern flowerings, set theory has also raised problems of its own, like any other branch of mathematics, but its larger, foundational role has been and remains conspicuous and distinctive.
What it means to say that a theory is foundational for mathematics is no straightforward matter, and different philosophers have held somewhat 3
Maddy (1997), p. 22.
Mathematical Pluralism
3
different views on the matter. Maddy discusses various possible interpretations of the view: ontological, epistemological, and methodological. But the details here need not concern us.4 However one understands what, exactly, it amounts to, ZFC is taken to be a single framework into which all of mathematics, in some sense, fits. As Maddy herself summarises matters:5 Finally, perhaps most fundamentally, this single, unified arena for mathematics provides a court of final appeal for questions of mathematical existence and proof: if you want to know if there is a mathematical object of a certain sort, you ask (ultimately) if there is a set theoretic surrogate of that sort; if you want to know if a given statement is provable or disprovable, you mean (ultimately), from the axioms of the theory of sets.
And again:6
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
set theoretic foundations . . . play a strong unifying role: vague structures are made more precise, old theorems are given new proofs and unified with other theorems that previously seemed quite distinct, similar hypotheses are traced at the basis of disparate mathematical fields, existence questions are given explicit meaning, unprovable conjectures can be identified, new hypotheses can settle old open questions, and so on. That set theory plays this role is central to modern mathematics, that it is able to play this role is perhaps the most remarkable outcome of the search for foundations.
That there is a unity to mathematics became, as she says, the orthodox view amongst philosophers of mathematics in the twentieth century. Arguably, it still is.7 However, the view is now starting to give way to one according to which there is no such unity. Mathematics is irreducibly a plurality. There is no grand narrative into which it can all be fitted. Indeed, it is investigations into the area of the foundations of mathematics which have themselves brought the view to breaking point. One may call the emerging view, naturally enough, mathematical pluralism, and the point of this Element is to explain and examine the view. It is no impartial guide, however. It also endorses and argues for the view. It is none 4 5 6 7
For one clear discussion of the matter, see Shapiro (2004). Maddy (1997), p. 26. My italics in this and the next quotation. Maddy (1997), p. 34 f. In a later publication Maddy reiterates her position, though she restricts it, without much explanation, to ‘classical’ mathematics (Maddy (2007), p. 354). What she means by ‘classical mathematics’ is not entirely clear; but if it means mathematics based on classical logic, even this more restricted claim runs aground on classical mathematical theories that do not fit into ZFC, as we will note in 2.2.
4
Philosophy of Mathematics
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
the worse, I think, for that. New views need advocates to make their full force felt. Orthodoxy will never lack its conservative defenders. In Section 1, we will look at the evolution of studies in the foundations of mathematics in the twentieth century, and see how mathematical pluralism arose naturally out of these. Then in Section 2, we will have a closer look at mathematical pluralism itself, some of its features, and some possible objections. The mathematics I have been talking about and which is discussed in the first two sections is pure mathematics. But mathematics also encompasses applied mathematics. What is one to make of this on a pluralist view? Section 3 investigates. Unsurprisingly, the picture which emerges is different from that which normally goes with set-theoretic foundationalism. As hardly needs to be said, the nature of mathematics is deeply entangled with the nature of logic. Here is not the place to discuss all matters involved in the bearing of mathematical pluralism on that topic. However, the last section in the Element, Section 4, discusses what I take to be some of the most important issues. Of course, in an Element of this length it is inevitable that a number of important issues receive no more than a cursory discussion. However, by the end of our short journey through the terrain of mathematical pluralism, you, the reader, will, I hope, have a decent understanding of the view and its features. What to make of it is, as ever in philosophy, up to you to decide.
Mathematical Pluralism
5
Indeed, even at this stage, I predict a time when there will be mathematical investigations of calculi containing contradictions, and people will actually be proud of having emancipated themselves from consistency. Wittgenstein (1964), p. 332. (Written in 1930.)
1 From the Foundations of Mathematics to Mathematical Pluralism 1.1 Introduction I think that an illuminating way of understanding contemporary mathematical pluralism is to see how it has come about. As I indicated in the preface, it has done so as a result of studies in the so-called foundations of mathematics and the problems this has exposed in the attempt to find such a foundation. In this section I will review this story. For the most part, the story is well known. Where this is so, I shall just give some standard reference to the material at the end of each section.8 When, towards the end of the section, we move to material that is not so well known, I will give fuller references.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
1.2 A Century of Mathematical Rigour Let us start by winding the clock back to the end of the nineteenth century. The nineteenth century may be fairly thought of as the age of mathematical rigour, in a certain sense. At the start of the century, many species in the genus of number were well known: natural numbers, rational numbers, real numbers, negative numbers, complex numbers, infinitesimals; but many aspects of them and their behaviour were not well understood. Equations could have imaginary roots; but what exactly is an imaginary number? Infinitesimals were essential to the computation of integrals and derivatives; but what were these ‘ghosts of departed quantities’, as Berkeley had put it?9 The century was to clear up much of the obscurity. Early in the century, the notion of a limit appeared in Cauchy’s formulation of the calculus. Instead of considering what happens to a function when some infinitesimal change is made to an argument, one considers what happens when one makes a small finite change and then sees what happens ‘in the limit’, as that number approaches 0 (the limit being a number which may be approached 8 9
A good general reference for the standard material is Hatcher (1982). The Analyst, or a Discourse Addressed to an Infidel Mathematician (1734), §XXXV.
6
Philosophy of Mathematics
as closely as one pleases, though never, perhaps, attained). Despite the fact that Cauchy possessed the notion of a limit, he mixed both infinitesimal and limit terminology. It was left to Weierstrass, later in the century, to replace all appeals to infinitesimals by appeals to limits. At this point, infinitesimals disappeared from the numerical menagerie – though they were later to make some comebacks in the forms of non-standard analysis and the theory of smooth infinitesimals, as we shall see.10 Weierstrass also gave the first modern account of negative numbers, defining them as signed reals, that is, pairs whose first members are reals, and whose second members are ‘sign bits’ (‘+’ or ‘−’), subject to suitable operations. A contemporary of Weierstrass, Tannery, gave the first modern account of rational numbers. He defined a rational number as an equivalence class of pairs of natural numbers, ⟨m, n⟩, where n , 0, under the equivalence relation, ∼, defined by
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
⟨m, n⟩ ∼ ⟨r, s⟩ iff m · s = r · n. Earlier in the century, Gauss and Argand had shown how to think of complex numbers of the form x + iy as points on the two-dimensional Euclidean plane – essentially as a pair of the form ⟨x, y⟩ – with the arithmetic operations defined in an appropriate fashion. A rigorous analysis of real numbers was provided in different ways by Dedekind, Weierstrass, and Cantor. Weierstrass’ analysis was in terms of infinite decimal expansions; Cantor’s was in terms of infinite sequences of rationals which converge to each other. Dedekind’s analysis was arguably the simplest. A Dedekind section is any partition of the rational numbers into two parts, ⟨L, R⟩, where for any l ∈ L and r ∈ R, l < r. A real number can be thought of as a Dedekind section (or just its left-hand part). So this is how things stood by late in the century. Every kind of number in extant mathematics – with the exception of infinitesimals, which had been abolished – had been reduced to simple set-theoretic constructions out of, in the last instance, natural numbers. What, then, of the natural numbers themselves? Dedekind gave the first axiomatisation of these – essentially the now familiar Peano Axioms. This certainly helped to frame the question, but it did not answer it.11
1.3 Frege and the Natural Numbers Which brings us to Frege. Frege was able to draw on the preceding developments, but he also defined the natural numbers in purely set-theoretic 10 11
See Bell (2022). For the material in this section, see Priest (1998).
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Mathematical Pluralism
7
terms.12 The natural number n was essentially the set of all n-membered sets (so that 0 is the set whose only member is the empty set, 1 is the set of all singletons, etc.) This might seem unacceptably circular, but Frege showed that circularity could be avoided, and indeed, how all the properties of numbers (as given by the Dedekind axioms) could be shown to follow from the appropriate definitions. But ‘follow from’ how? The extant canons of logic – essentially a form of syllogistic – were not up to the job, as was pretty clear. Frege, then, had to develop a whole new canon of logic, his Begriffsschrift. Thus did Frege’s work give birth to ‘classical logic’. Given Frege’s constructions, all of the familiar numbers and their properties could now be shown to be sets of certain kinds. But what of sets themselves? Frege took these to be abstract (non-physical) objects satisfying what we would now think of as an unrestricted comprehension schema. Thus (in modern notation), any condition, A(x), defines a set of objects {x : A(x)}. Because he was using second-order logic, Frege was able to define membership. Again in modern notation, x ∈ y if and only if ∃Z(y = {z : Zz} ∧ Zx). Moreover, Frege took these set-theoretic principles themselves to be principles of pure logic. Hence all of arithmetic (that is, the theory of numbers) was a matter of pure logic – a view now called logicism. And this provided an answer to the question of how we may know the truths of arithmetic – or to be more precise, reduced it to the question of how we know the truths of logic. As to this, Frege assumed, in common with a well-worn tradition, that these were simply a priori. Frege’s achievement was spectacular. Unfortunately, as is well known, there was one small, but devastating, fly in the ointment, discovered by Russell. The naive comprehension principle was inconsistent. Merely take for A(x) the condition that x < x, and we have the familiar Russell paradox. If B is the sentence {x : x < x} ∈ {x : x < x} then B ∧ ¬B. Given the properties of classical logic, everything followed – a disaster. After the discovery of Russell’s paradox, Frege tried valiantly to rescue his program, but unsuccessfully. The next developments of the Zeitgeist were to come from elsewhere.13
1.4 Type Theory Namely, Russell – and his partner in logical crime, Whitehead. Russell was also a logicist, but a more ambitious one than Frege. For him, all mathematics, and 12 13
Strictly speaking, in terms of courses of values. For the material in this section, see Zalta (2016).
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
8
Philosophy of Mathematics
not just arithmetic, was to be logic. In the first instance, this required reducing the other traditional part of mathematics – geometry – to logic, as well. This was relegated to Volume IV of the mammoth Principia Mathematica, which never appeared. But by this time, things were more complex than this. The work of Cantor on the infinite had generated some new kinds of numbers: transfinite ones. These were of two kinds, cardinals, measuring size, and ordinals, measuring order. Russell generalised Frege’s definition of number to all cardinals: a cardinal number was any set containing all those sets between which there is a one-to-one correspondence. He generalised it further again to ordinals. An ordered set is well-ordered if every subset has a least member. An ordinal is any set containing all those well-ordered sets between which there is an order-isomorphism. Of course, Russell still had to worry about his paradox, and others of a similar kind which, by that time, had multiplied. His solution was type theory. The precise details were complex and need not concern us here. Essentially, sets14 were to be thought of as arranged in a hierarchy of types, such that quantifiers could range over one type only. Given a condition with a variable of type i, A(xi ), comprehension delivered a set {xi : A(xi )}; this set, however, was not of type i, but of a higher type, and so it could not be substituted into the defining condition delivering Russell’s paradox to produce contradiction. Russell’s construction faced a number of problems. For a start, it was hard to motivate the hierarchy of orders as a priori, and so as part of logic. Secondly, with his construction, Frege had been able to show that there were infinite sets (such as the set of natural numbers). The restrictions of type theory did not allow this proof. Russell therefore had to have an axiom to the effect that there was such a thing: the Axiom of Infinity. It was hard to see this as an a priori truth as well.15 On top of these, there were problems of a more technical nature. For a start, the hierarchy of types meant that the numbers were not unique: every type (at least, every type which was high enough) had its own set of numbers of each kind. This was, to say the least, ugly. Moreover, Cantor’s work had delivered transfinite numbers of very large kinds. Type theory delivered only a small ∪ range of these. Specifically, if ℶ0 = ℵ0 , ℶn+1 = 2ℶn , and ℶω = ℶn , then n 0, i+p = i – and of course, i+p , i too. We might depict the structure thus (where → is the successor function):
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
0 → 1 →
...
→
n → n+1 ↑ ↓ n+p−1 ← ...
How might such an arithmetic come to be applied? Let us suppose that we predict a collision between a star and a huge planet. Using a standard technique, we compute their masses as x1 and y1 . Since masses of this kind are, to within experimental error, the sum of the masses of the baryons (protons and neutrons) in them, it will be convenient to take a unit of measurement according to which a baryon has mass 1. In effect, therefore, these figures measure the numbers of baryons in the masses. After the collision, we measure the mass of the resulting (fused) body, and obtain the figure z, where z is much less than x1 +y1 . Naturally, our results are subject to experimental error. But the difference is so large that it cannot possibly be explained by this. We check our instruments, suspecting a fault, but cannot find one; we check our computations for an error, but cannot find one. Some days later, we have the chance to record another collision. We record the masses before the collision. This time they are x2 and y2 . Again, after the 102 103
104
I take this from Priest (2003). One might wonder how applying an arithmetical structure fits in to the schema I outlined earlier. Suppose, for example, that we have two bunches of objects, X and Y, we count each one, and then want to know how many things we have altogether. The ‘laws of counting’ tell us that µ(Z) = µ(X) + µ(Y), where Z = X ∪ Y and µ means ‘the number of objects in’. Suppose that we have established that µ(X) = 3 and µ(Y) = 12. Then abstracting, we have: z = x + y = 3 + 12. Working in the pure mathematical abstract structure, we infer that z = 15. De-abstracting, we get µ(Z) = 15, providing the answer. See, for example, Priest (1997b) and (2000).
Philosophy of Mathematics
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
50
collision, the mass appears to be z (the same as before), less than x2 + y2 . The first result was no aberration. We investigate various ways of solving the anomaly. We might revise the theories on which our measuring devices depend, but there may be no obvious way of doing this. We could say that some baryons disappeared in the collision; alternatively, we could suppose that under certain conditions the mass of a baryon decreases. But either of these options amounts to a rejection of the law of conservation of mass(-energy), which would seem to be a rather unattractive course of action. Then we realise that the results can be accommodated by supposing that when we count baryons we may use a non-classical arithmetic. (As noted, we already know that different sorts of fundamental particles obey different statistics. Baryons are certain kinds of fermions.) The empirical results can be accommodated by using an inconsistent arithmetic of the kind just described, where z is the least inconsistent number, n, and p = 1.105 For in such an arithmetic x1 + y1 = x2 + y2 = z, and our observations are explained without having to assume that the mass of baryons has changed, or that any are lost in the collisions. The thought experiment can be continued in ways which make the application of an inconsistent arithmetic even more apt – indeed, even accommodating the fact that if z′ > z, then z′ = z – but we do not need to go into the details here.106 Of course, these facts can be accommodated in a consistent – though still highly non-standard – arithmetic. What you cannot have in such an arithmetic is the rest of standard arithmetic; or even the fragment axiomatised in Peano Arithmetic. And this rest may well be important in applying the arithmetic structure in further computations. At any rate, the point is made. There is nothing in principle against applying such a paraconsistent arithmetic. Before I move on to comment on three philosophers whose writings deal with applied mathematics, let me summarise the picture of applied mathematics that has emerged in the preceding discussion. In applying mathematics, one uses a pure mathematical structure as depicted in the diagram of Subsection 3.4. The structure to be used is the one which gives the right empirical results (whatever that means). Sometimes, the pertinent pure mathematical structure will have arisen out of some kind of real-world practice, 105
So the structure now looks like this:
0 106
→
1
→
...
→
↶ n
They can be found in Priest (2003), §7.
Mathematical Pluralism
51
making the distinction between the pure structure and a certain application almost invisible. (Euclidean geometry and natural-number arithmetic are cases in point.) That, however, provides no guarantee that a different structure will not do that job better. (Geometry again illustrates.) Sometimes, a certain sort of application will occasion the development of a whole new kind of pure mathematical structure which seems to be right for doing the job in question. (The infinitesimal calculus illustrates.) Many pure mathematical structures were, however, produced and investigated with no thought of application in mind. (The investigation of higher infinitudes is a case in point.) Though sometimes it will turn out, later, that such pure structures are just what seem to be required for a certain application. (Group theory and the Special Theory of Relativity provide a case in point.) Historically, then, the connection between pure and applied mathematics can be a somewhat tangled one. All the more reason to keep the fundamentals of the relation between them straight.
3.6 Comments on Three Philosophers In the light of this discussion, let me comment on three notable philosophers of mathematics, pointing out where, in the light of the preceding account, they are right, and where they are wrong.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
3.6.1 Quine The first is Quine. Famously, according to Quine,107 claims of pure mathematics are verified (established as true) holistically, together with our empirical scientific claims. And since they are true, and quantify over abstract mathematical objects, these exist.108 The ontological claim, depending as it does on the view that anything quantified over in a true statement exists – at least if the language is an appropriately regimented one – is highly debatable.109 But set that matter aside here and concentrate on just the epistemic claim. It has many problems. The people who are best qualified to judge whether a claim of pure mathematics is true are pure mathematicians; and they care not at all about applications. What is important to them is proof. Next, 107 108
109
Perhaps most notably in Quine (1951). See Colyvan (2001), esp. 2.5. For more on Quine’s philosophy of mathematics see Hylton and Kemp (2019) and Priest (2010). This is sometimes known as ‘Quine’s indispensability argument’: abstract entities exist because they are indispensable for science. See, for example, Colyvan (2001; 2019). Note that the plausibility of the ontological conclusion goes via the thought that we are justified in taking the statements to be true (simpliciter). The existence of a God is indispensable for Christian theology; but this provides no argument for the existence of God if the theological statements are not true. See Priest (2005).
52
Philosophy of Mathematics
as noted, there are important parts of pure mathematics that have (as yet) no empirical applications, such as the theory of large transfinite numbers, infinitary combinatorics, and the theory of surreal numbers.110 Next, some theories can be applied in different areas. In some they are verified; in some, they would not be. Thus, the pure mathematical theory of the Lambek Calculus is verified when applied to grammatical parsing, but not when applied to simplifying Boolean electrical circuits. Does this mean that the pure mathematical statements are both true and false? Presumably not. As far as truth goes, one application would have to be privileged. But any such privileging is arbitrary. But what underlies all these issues, as we may now see, is that the account simply has the wrong take on applied mathematics. What gets confirmed or otherwise by an application are the statements which describe the real world – the likes of our D and E in the diagram of Subsection 3.4. Application has no relevance to pure mathematical statements, like D′ and E′. All that is confirmed or not in their application is whether they are the right bits of mathematics for the job at hand. The criterion of truth for statements like D′ and E′ is proof. And indeed, assuming the correctness of mathematical pluralism, this is truth secundum quid, truth-in-a-structure.111
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
3.6.2 Field Let us now turn to Field. His Science without Numbers112 is an essay on applied mathematics. The major explicit driver of Field’s project is what he calls nominalism – perhaps better, anti-platonism: the view that no abstract entities, notably mathematical entities, exist. Field shows how an important example, Newtonian gravitational theory, may be formulated quantifying over only physical entities. In scientific practice, pure mathematics, which quantifies over abstract entities can be (and is) used, but this is a conservative extension of the physical machinery, and so is not involved essentially.113 We are free, then, to adopt a fictionalist understanding of the pure mathematics. The pure mathematical statements are not really true. They are just ‘true in the mathematical fiction’ which is, say, R. (See Subsection 2.10.) Field’s view has some notable similarities to and notable differences with the view described earlier. To start with, I agree with Field’s anti-platonism. 110 111 112 113
On the last of these, see Knuth (1974). Hence the Quine indispensability argument also falters at the step that requires simple truth. Field (1980). In the way that non-finitary statements are used, according to Hilbert, in arithmetic. See Zach (2023).
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Mathematical Pluralism
53
However, as I have noted (2.10), I prefer a noneist approach to the matter. By all means, quantify over abstract entities. These are just non-existent objects. Next, according to the two accounts of applied mathematics, the world (or an aspect of it) is described in empirical terms. We then interpret some of what is going on in pure mathematical terms and use the results of this to infer an empirical situation. There are three important differences between our approaches. First, in my case, though not in Field’s, the empirical statements refer to mathematical objects, such as numbers. However, I stress, and as I have already noted, these statements may be empirically verifiable by means of familiar measuring devices. (Nor do I regard the truth of such statements as committing to the existence of abstract entities, for reasons I have already noted.114 ) Secondly, as the introduction to the second edition of Field’s book makes clear (see esp. p. P-4 ff.), there is another thought which drives his approach. Descriptions at the empirical level should make use of only intrinsic notions. How exactly to understand the notion of intrinsicality here is not a straightforward matter. But certainly the use of measuring scales and coordinate systems are not intrinsic. As is clear, my empirical level may make use of such notions. Now, I can understand the pull of intrinsicality from a certain theoretical perspective; but I think it fair to say that it is of virtually no importance for practicing (applied) mathematicians. If, in the end, science makes essential use of things such as measuring scales,115 and this introduces an ineliminable conventionality into actual science, so be it.116 Third, it is important for Field that the application of the pure mathematics is conservative over the empirical level.117 Conservativity plays no role in my account. Indeed, it is important that the result is not conservative. It is precisely this fact which allows for novel empirical predications, which can be used to test the machinery deployed. However, as just observed, Field and I understand different things by the empirical level. Of course, making novel predications does play an important role in science, and Field is well aware of this. He is happy with the fact that in practice mathematical machinery is used to make novel predications. In principle, however, these could be obtained simply from the empirical base, from 114
115 116 117
In the examples of Subsection 3.3, the empirical languages contained terms that refer to mathematical objects, though not quantification over them, for example, with things such as ∃r r = µ(I). The procedure I sketched carries over straightforwardly to such a syntax. The quantifiers are simply preserved in the abstracted pure mathematical statements (and back). So that they cannot be ‘factored out’ with invariance under the appropriate transformations. See the discussion of conventionalism in Tal (2020). One has to be a bit careful as to how to spell this out, though. See the discussion of conservativity in §0.4 of the second edition of the book.
Philosophy of Mathematics
54
which the appropriate mathematics may be thought of as abstracted via the appropriate representation theorem. His approach is therefore a sort of ‘rational reconstruction’, which mine is not.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
3.6.3 Wigner Finally, let us turn to Wigner’s essay ‘The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences’.118 As the title suggests, in this paper Wigner avers that we have no right to expect that mathematics can be effective in our engagement with the world. In a sense he’s right; in a sense, he’s wrong. First, there is absolutely no a priori reason why the world should be ordered or have structure. It is entirely logically possible that the world should be as random as can be. And if it were, no mathematics would help to explain or predict events. But of course, the world is not like this. We know that it has order – at least, pockets of it – because we are part of it, and we are ordered beings, as is our immediate environment. There is, then, at least in some sense, structure in the world. Mathematics is a science of structure (or structures); hence we can expect mathematics to get some grip on at least some aspects of the world. Of course, there is no a priori reason why any particular mathematical structure should get a grip on it. But it is hardly surprising that some of the mathematics we have does so, since it evolved out of relevant practices, or was developed specifically for that purpose. That it does so is, then, no more surprising than that a telescope allows us to see at a distance, or that the flu vaccine protects against flu. Naturally, it may turn out that the mathematics we have developed is the wrong mathematics for the project. As we know, it has been so sometimes in the past; and maybe it will be so again in the future. But if that turns out the be the case, people (or maybe, now, computers!) will at least attempt to design mathematics that works better. Such development is certainly not the point of pure mathematics, which is to investigate interesting abstract structures in their own right. But designing pure mathematical structures for intended applications is obviously a legitimate project as well.
3.7 Conclusion In this section, we have looked at the application of mathematics, and we have seen what goes on when a piece of pure mathematics is applied. Mathematical 118
Wigner (1960).
Mathematical Pluralism
55
pluralism delivers a natural picture of this, at odds with the way that the application of mathematics has frequently been thought of. In particular, only a notion of truth which is secundum quid is required by and/or justified by an application. And with this, my discussion here of mathematical pluralism, as such, is completed. But it is clear that the view has connections with and implications for other areas of philosophy: metaphysics, epistemology, and, of course, logic. It is impossible to explore all these connections in an Element of this length – or even any one book. However, the connections with logic are particularly salient. In the next (and final) section of the Element I will explore some of these.
4 Matters of Logic 4.1 Introduction
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
This Element is about mathematics, not logic; but as is clear, logic has been lurking beneath the surface of much of the discussion. This is not the place for a comprehensive discussion of the nature of logic and related matters, but in this section I will discuss briefly the bearing of mathematical pluralism on some issues here. Three will concern us. The first is the relationship between logic and applied mathematics. The second is logical pluralism. The third is non-classical logic. I will take up the matters in that order.
4.2 Logic as Applied Mathematics As hardly needs to be said, contemporary logic uses mathematical techniques. It is not normally thought of as a branch of applied mathematics. That is exactly what an important and central part of it is, however. Let us see how.119 4.2.1 Pure and Applied Logic Just as there is a distinction between pure and applied mathematics, there is a distinction between pure and applied logic. There is a multitude of pure logics (classical, intuitionist, paraconsistent, etc.) Each logic, L, will comprise a formal language, L, a consequence relation, ⊢, defined on sentences of L, and possibly other machinery. In general ⊢ ⊆ ℘(L) × ℘(L), but for our purposes we need be concerned only with consequence relations where the first component is a finite set, and the second is a singleton. A logic L may be specified proof theoretically, model theoretically, algebraically, or in some other way. 119
For further discussion, see Priest (202+b).
56
Philosophy of Mathematics
The pure mathematical structure may be used to establish the equivalence between different characterisations, and other important properties of ⊢, such as decidability or compactness. A pure logic can have many applications. It may be applied to simplify electrical circuits (as with Boolean logic), or to parse sentences (as with the Lambek Calculus). But just as with geometry, logic has always had what one might call a canonical application: the analysis of arguments. These are arguments expressed in a vernacular language. When people argue, be they lawyers, politicians, historians, scientists, or wot not, they do not do so in a formal language. And, note, this is just as true of mathematicians. If you open the pages of a mathematics journal or textbook, you will not find the argument presented in Principia-ese, or any other formal language. People argue in a natural language (though some of the vocabulary used may be of a technical nature). The canonical application of a pure logic is to evaluate such arguments. That is what the subject was originally invented for. 4.2.2 The Canonical Application of a Pure Logic How is this done? It precisely fits into the general schema of application given in Subsection 3.4. Suppose we have an argument phrased in a vernacular language, LV . Let this have premises P1, ...Pn , and conclusion C. We form the sentence:
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
• AV : the inference from P1, ...Pn to C is valid. The sentences of the language are transformed into sentences µ(P1 ), ..., µ(Pn ), µ(C) of L; and AV is transformed into the sentence: • A: µ(P1 ), ..., µ(Pn ) ⊢ µ(C) The translation of vernacular sentences into L is done by a process that is usually informal, but teachers of elementary logic courses will normally spend a considerable amount of time developing the required skills in their students. The appropriate translation on some occasions may, itself, be a matter of theoretical contention. Thus, for example, the standard translation of a definite description is as a term of L; but according to Russell’s theory of definite descriptions, the whole sentence in which it occurs is translated into a sentence which contains no corresponding noun-phrase. However, once this translation is made, the mathematical machinery of L is applied to determine whether A holds in the pure mathematical structure. The sentence is then ‘de-abstracted’ back to the real-world level, to tell us whether AV holds.
Mathematical Pluralism
57
Refer back to the diagram of Subsection 3.4. The real-world level comprises vernacular arguments. D is a statement of validity for such an argument. D′ is a corresponding mathematical statement of L to be proven or refuted, and E′ is the result. E is then the verdict for the original argument. 4.2.3 Pure Logic as Theory As I noted in Subsection 3.4, when one applies a piece of pure mathematics to some real-world phenomenon, what one obtains is, in effect, a theory of how the things in that domain behave (though the theory may be subject to various possible interpretations, as I also discussed in Subsection 3.4). Thus, when a pure logic, L, is given its canonical application, it constitutes a theory of the validity or otherwise of inferences in the vernacular language (or the relevant fragment thereof). Many such theories of (deductive) validity have been proposed, accepted, and/or rejected in the history of Western logic: Aristotelian syllogistic, medieval (and contemporary) connexive logic, medieval supposition theory, ‘classical’ logic, intuitionist logic, paraconsistent logics – to name but a few of the most obvious ones. And of course, different theories may give different verdicts on various inferences. Thus, if AV concerns the inference:
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
• Donald Trump is corrupt and Donald Trump is not corrupt, so π is irrational and L is classical logic, then it will return the verdict valid. But if L is a paraconsistent logic, it will return the verdict invalid. Given a collection of different theories, the question – one which has played a major role in contemporary philosophy of logic – then arises as to which of them is rationally preferable.120 Primary amongst the considerations for determining the answer is one of adequacy to the data. In the case of empirical theories, the data is provided by empirical observation and experimentation. In the case of logic it is provided by judgments about the validity or otherwise of particular inferences.121 Thus: [1] Mary is wearing a red dress and red shoes; so Mary is wearing a red dress strikes us as valid, but: 120 121
For a more extended discussion of the following, see Priest (2014) and (2016). Not, nota bene, forms of inference. These are always some kind of low-level theoretical generalisations.
58
Philosophy of Mathematics
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
[2] Mary is wearing either a red dress or red shoes; so Mary is wearing a red dress strikes us as invalid. Getting these data points right is a mark in favour of a theory; getting them wrong is a mark against the theory. Of course, as in the empirical sciences, data is not infallible. It can be wrong, and can be shown to be so by an otherwise good theory. Thus, an aberrant measurement in geometry may be taken to show that our measuring device, or our theory of how it works, is incorrect. Similarly, our naive judgments about the validity or otherwise of certain inferences may be wrong. ‘Mary’s dress is red, so Mary’s dress is coloured’ will strike most as valid. But standard logic says that it is not. What is valid is the inference with the extra premise ‘Whatever is red is coloured’. Of course, simply writing off an aberrant data point is bad methodology. Some independent explanation needs to be found. In the case of the logic example, a natural such explanation is that we frequently do not mention obvious premises (such as that all red things are coloured) because they are obvious, and life is short. In situations of any theoretical complexity, adequacy or otherwise to the data will not settle the matter. For a start, theories may be equally adequate or inadequate. In practice, other criteria are also important, such as simplicity, unifying power, non-reliance on ad hoc hypotheses, and so on. So it is in logic as well. Hence, the choice between different theories of this kind will bring into play, not only adequacy to the data, but other theoretical virtues.122 How one aggregates all these factors will, then, be a crucial issue. However, we need not go into these matters further here. Suffice it to say that the theory it is most rational to accept is the one which performs best overall. What we have here is some kind of abductive inference.123 The important thing to observe at present is that rational choice of theory is a fallible and, in a certain sense, an a posteriori one. It is fallible because the data against which a theory is measured is itself fallible; and, moreover, new and better theories may appear at any time. It is a posteriori because its acceptability is to be judged in the light of data and methodological criteria, not given by certain and infallible rational intuition. 122
123
In many cases, the mathematical structure, L, will contain machinery to be interpreted as truth, meaning, necessity, or some other vexed philosophical notion, when the structure receives its canonical interpretation. The theory of validity will then be embedded in a broader theory concerning, also, these notions. In this context, these other criteria will loom particularly large. See, further, Priest (2016; 2021a). This view is often now known as ‘anti-exceptionalism’. I find this term both ugly and potentially misleading. I prefer ‘abductivism’. For an application of this methodology in practice, see Berto et al. (2018).
Mathematical Pluralism
59
This does not mean that one has to use sensory information. One can, of course, sometimes use such information to establish that an inference is invalid. For some inferences we may be able to see (literally) that the inference is invalid. For example, consider the inference: • There are at least two people in the room; so there are a million people in the room. where the inference concerns a certain room at a certain time. We may be able to see that the premise is true and the conclusion is not. But most cases will not be like this. One may judge that the inference is valid or invalid, merely by reflecting on it. In a similar way – though the analogy is not to be pushed too far – a native English speaker can simply reflect on the string of words ‘The 45th President of the USA was corrupt’, to see that it is grammatical, though that this is so is, of course, an a posteriori fact about English. As with the application of a pure mathematical structure in any other area, then, finding the right pure logic for the canonical application is, as I argued in Subsections 3.4 and 3.5, an a posteriori matter, in the sense explained.
4.3 Logical Pluralism and Mathematical Pluralism Let us turn to our second topic, namely logical pluralism.124
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
4.3.1 Logical Pluralism Mathematical pluralism is the view that there are different pure mathematical structures – notably those based on different logics – which are, in an appropriate sense, equally legitimate. Correspondingly, logical pluralism is the view that there are different logics (consequence relations), which are, in an appropriate sense, equally legitimate. That claim can be understood in many ways, however; some of them quite innocuous; some of them highly contentious.125 But, one might hold that mathematical pluralism entails logical pluralism in the following sense: there is no uniquely correct notion of validity to be used for the canonical application of logic. I do not think this follows, however, as I will now explain.126 Whether the view is actually true is, of course, a different matter. 124 125
126
This section reprises a theme developed in Priest (2021b). For a general discussion of logical pluralism see Priest (2006b), ch. 12, Russell (2019), and Stei (2023). The term ‘logic’ is itself highly ambiguous. A discussion of the ambiguity of the term can be found in Priest (2014). Shapiro (2014) holds that it does. This, we both agree, is the main difference between his view concerning mathematical pluralism and mine.
60
Philosophy of Mathematics
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
4.3.2 Truth Simpliciter and Truth in a Structure The inference from mathematical pluralism to logical pluralism in this sense is a very straightforward one. When we reason about ZFC sets, classical logic is the correct logic to apply; when we reason about smooth infinitesimals, intuitionistic logic is the correct logic to apply; when we reason about inconsistent topologies, paraconsistent logic is the correct logic to apply. So each logic can be the correct one, depending on the context.127 It must be agreed that there is something right about this view. If we are reasoning about ZFC sets, it is appropriate to use classical logic; for this structure is closed under classical consequence. If we reason about smooth infinitesimals, it is appropriate to use intuitionistic logic; for this structure is closed under intuitionistic consequence. If we reason about inconsistent topologies, it is appropriate to use paraconsistent logic; for these structures are closed under paraconsistent consequence. Each logic is the correct logic for preserving truth-in-the-structure. It is the internal logic of the structure. But the canonical application of logic is not about truth-in-a-structurepreservation. It is about truth-preservation. When we reason, we are interested in whether, given that our premises are true [or assuming them to be true] our conclusion is [would be] so as well. That the canonical application of logic is about truth preservation is not a profound claim; in some sense, it is a simple truism. Of course, it is a contentious matter as to how to spell out exactly what it means. Nor is it even clear what machinery is best employed to articulate the thought: proof procedures, set-theoretic interpretations, modal notions, probability theory? These matters are not pertinent here, though. The point is the simple distinction between truth-preservation, however one understands this notion, and the preservation of truth-in-a-structure. And once this distinction is noted, it is clear that the fact that there are different ways to preserve truth in a structure, depending on the structure, does not imply that there are many ways to preserve truth, simpliciter. One way to make the point is as follows. Mathematical theories are not exactly stories, but they are much closer than one might have thought. In particular, when we reason about what holds in a mathematical structure, A, we, in effect, prefix our statements with the operator ‘In structure A...’. (Of course, traditionally, mathematicians did not think of their statements as having this prefix. But that this is so is what mathematical pluralism appears to have shown us.) When we reason about what holds in a work of fiction, we, in effect, prefix our reasoning with the operator ‘In fiction F...’. And in both cases, our
127
The argument is run by Shapiro (2014)).
Mathematical Pluralism
61
reasoning respects the internal logic of the structure/fiction – which does not have to be classical logic.128 And truth-in-a-structure is not a species of truth simpliciter – any more than truth in a fiction is. Another way of making the point is that any graspable and performable set of rules can be followed by an agent – rules of inference of some logical theory included. This obviously does not validate logical pluralism in the required sense. For logic, following the rules must have a certain point – truth-preservation is the traditional and correct candidate.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
4.3.3 Objections The preceding argument deploys the distinction between truth and truth-in-astructure. How might one challenge this? One way is as follows. Truth preservation simpliciter is validity. Validity is truth preservation in all interpretations. Interpretations are the same thing as structures. So preservation of truth is the same thing as preservation of truthin-a-structure. Several issues would have to be addressed to make this argument cogent. One would need to defend a model-theoretic account of validity. One would have to face the fact that in many pure logics validity is not defined in terms of truth preservation, but in some other terms. (For example, in many-valued logics it is defined in terms of the preservation of designated values.) And one would have to defend the anything but obvious claim that structures and interpretations are the same thing. (See Subsection 2.5.) But even assuming that these points can be adequately addressed, there is a simple and obvious problem with the objection. Model-theoretic validity is not truth-preservation in all interpretations. Different logics (intuitionist, classical, paraconsistent, etc.) have different kinds of interpretations. Their model theories therefore provide an understanding of truth preservation in the appropriate kind of structure – the internal logic of the structure – not validity simpliciter. And if one really defines validity as truth-preservation in all interpretations, then, given the plurality of formal logics on which mathematical structures may be based, the logic will amount, as near as makes no difference, to the null logic: no inference is valid. Such would clearly make validity useless for evaluating the validity of ordinary arguments, and so cannot be right. A second way to challenge the distinction between truth and truth-in-astructure might be as follows. That validity is about truth preservation is, in 128
For a fiction in which the internal logic is a paraconsistent logic, see the short story ‘Sylvan’s Box’, Priest (1997a).
62
Philosophy of Mathematics
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
the sense we have been dealing with, a banal claim. It is an equally banal claim that truth, whatever it is, is determined by reality. And isn’t reality just another structure? So reasoning about truth is simply a variety of reasoning about truth-in-a-structure. In some sense, I suppose, reality is a structure, or at least, has a structure. But it’s not just any old structure. It is highly privileged. I ask you whether it is true that there were more people at Trump’s presidential inauguration than at Obama’s. I don’t need to tell you that I want an answer that corresponds to reality. One way to see the point is this. We have both been reading Conan Doyle’s The Hound of the Baskervilles. We argue about whether Holmes used a Colt revolver. I say he did. You say he used a Smith and Wesson. Of course, neither of us thinks that our claims are literally true: Doyle’s text is just a fiction. We are both tacitly prefixing our claims with ‘In The Hound of the Baskervilles...’. We just omit this because, given the mutually understood context, it is unnecessary. Now, by contrast, if I ask you whether Trump’s crowd was bigger than Obama’s, and you say, ‘No, the crowd was much smaller’, I don’t have to understand you as saying ‘In reality, the crowd was much smaller’; and if you did, the prefix would be entirely otiose. Reality, then, is not simply a structure, on a par with other structures. The distinction between truth-in-a-structure and truth simpliciter, then, stands; and this distinction bars the way from mathematical pluralism to the logical pluralism in question.
4.4 Non-Classical Logic Let us turn to our third topic. The distinction between the preservation of truth in a structure and validity is relevant to another claim that has recently been made. Williamson (2018) has argued that the application of mathematics in science provides a strong argument for the correctness of classical logic. The argument is essentially as follows. Pure mathematics is based on classical logic, and therefore deploys the classical notion of validity, including essentially inferential moves that fail in a sub-classical logic. The fact that mathematics has been so successfully applied in science therefore speaks strongly in favour of the classical notion of validity, and against a non-classical notion – or at the very least, an advocate of a nonclassical notion of validity owes us an account of this successful application. He puts the point as follows:129
129
Williamson (2018), p. 399. His italics.
Mathematical Pluralism
63
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
The hardest test of logic is mathematics, which constitutes by far the most sustained and successful deductive enterprise in human history. With only minor exceptions, mathematicians have freely relied on classical logic, including principles such as the law of excluded middle, A ∨ ¬A. They unquestioningly accept classical reasoning in proofs. When deviant logicians reject a classical principle, they face an obvious challenge: what does this mean for mathematics? Where does this leave theorems whose proofs rely solely on the principle?
The claim that pure mathematics is based on classical logic is not, of course, one that a mathematical pluralist will grant; as we have seen, there is perfectly good pure mathematics that uses a non-classical logic. But Williamson clearly has applied mathematics in his sights. However, as the account of the application of mathematics of the last section shows, this does little to help his case. Williamson is assuming that one must take the inferences involved in applying mathematics to be valid. That is, they preserve truth simpliciter. But they do not: they involve the preservation of truth-in-a-structure, for the structures in question. In itself, this shows nothing about validity. As we have seen, that is a different matter. If, when we reason about what holds in the structure A, we use the inference A ⊢ B, we endorse the claim that ‘In A, A’ entails ‘In A, B’. This does not imply that A entails B. ‘In A, C’ is neither necessary nor sufficient for C. (If, as I shall note in a moment, for two hundred years, physics, in the form of the infinitesimal calculus, used a paraconsistent inference procedure because of the use of infinitesimals, Williamson would not, I am sure, infer that paraconsistent logic was correct. He would, I presume, take an infinitesimal to be some kind of felicitous computational, ideal, or approximating object.) Even more to the point, the premise of Williamson’s argument, that the mathematics that has been applied ‘has relied on’ classical logic, is untenable. For a start, it is anachronistic. Mathematics has been applied for millennia, and classical (aka Frege/Russell) logic was invented only just over 100 years ago. Of course, mathematicians reasoned before that; but the reasoning was informal and did not answer to any formal logic. What’s more, at times, applied mathematicians clearly flouted the principles of classical logic. For example, the reasoning that was applied in the infinitesimal calculus from its discovery/invention till the nineteenth century could not have endorsed Explosion, since it assumed that infinitesimals behaved in a contradictory fashion.130 Of course, we now know how to formalise this bit of mathematics using classical logic. Maybe it is even true 130
See Brown and Priest (2004) and Sweeney (2014).
64
Philosophy of Mathematics
that all the mathematics that has been applied can be formalised using classical logic, but that tells us little. It can be formalised in other ways too. For example, the whole of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory can be understood using the paraconsistent logic LP.131 Moreover, once one leaves the domain of the natural sciences, it is now common for non-classical logics to be deployed. Linguists frequently appeal to logics with truth value gaps to analyse presupposition, and to fuzzy logics to analyse things like gradable adjectives.132 Moreover, this says nothing of the use by logicians and linguists of non-classical logics to analyse self-reference. Finally, even if it were the case that, historically, only mathematics based on classical logic had ever been applied, it might fairly be claimed that this is entirely accidental and due to the fact that the varieties of non-classical mathematics had not yet been developed. As the example of linguistics shows, non-classical logic is now being applied. Even if one were to concede that mathematics based on non-classical logic has not thus far been deployed in the natural sciences, it is quite within the bounds of possibility that it will be. If it is found to give the right results, it will be. The application of mathematics and its history is therefore of little help to the defender of ‘classical’ logic.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
4.5 Conclusion So much for a somewhat whistle-stop tour of some logical issues. This brings the Element’s discussions to a closure. Of necessity (given the word limit on Elements in this series), it has been relatively swift. There is much more to be said about the issues traversed; and I have no doubt that much more will be said by logicians and philosophers of mathematics. But I hope that the Element has at least laid out clearly the basics of mathematical pluralism and thus laid the ground for future discussions. All that remains is to say a few concluding words.
131 132
See, for example, Priest (2006a), 18.4, and Priest (2017), sect. 11. See, for example, Gregory (2015). As the book’s blurb says: ‘This book will take linguistics students beyond the classical logic used in introductory courses into the variety of non-standard logics that are commonly used in research’.
Postface
Like it or not, the plurality of mathematics seems to be a fact of contemporary mathematical life. Ours it is to make sense of this fact. One can, if one wishes, declare that there is one true mathematics (ZFC?) and that the rest is all mistaken. Such would seem to be a procrustean position of desperate proportions. Mathematical pluralism, as I have sketched it, is, I hope, a much more plausible view than this. There is a genuine plurality of pure mathematical practices, each with its own set of rules. As Wittgenstein says:133 I should like to say: mathematics is a MOTLEY of techniques of proof.— And upon this is based its manifold applicability and its importance.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Moreover, we may legitimately pursue any of the practices. All pure mathematical animals are equal. Though, of course, in terms of intrinsic interest, richness, beauty, application, and so on, there will be significant differences. Some of these animals will always be more equal than others.
133
Wittgenstein (1967), p. 84e. His capitals.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
References Avron, A. (2010), ‘A New Approach to Predicative Set Theory’, pp. 31–64 of R. Schindler (ed.), Ways of Proof Theory, Heisenstamm: Ontos Verlag. Balaguer, M. (1995), ‘A Platonist Epistemology’, Synthese 103: 303–25. Balaguer, M. (2018), ‘Fictionalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato .stanford.edu/entries/fictionalism-mathematics/. Beall, J. (1999), ‘From Full Blooded Platonism to Really Full Blooded Platonism’, Philosophia Mathematica 7: 322–5. Bell, J. (2008), A Primer of Infinitesimal Analysis, 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bell, J. (2022), ‘Continuity and Infinitesimals’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/continuity/. Benacerraf, P. (1965), ‘What Numbers Could not Be’, Philosophical Review 74: 47–73. Berto, F., French, R., Priest, G., and Ripley, D. (2018), ‘Williamson on Counterpossibles’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 47: 693–713. Brady, R. (1989), ‘The Non-Triviality of Dialectical Set Theory’, pp. 437–71 of G. Priest, R. Routley, and J. Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Munich: Philosophia Verlag. Bridges, D. (2013), ‘Constructive Mathematics’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mathematicsconstructive/. Bridges, D., and Richman, F. (1987), Varieties of Constructive Mathematics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brown, B., and Priest, G. (2004), ‘Chunk and Permeate, a Paraconsistent Inference Strategy; Part I, the Infinitesimal Calculus’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 22: 379–88. Bueno, O. (2011), ‘Relativism in Set Theory and Mathematics’, pp. 553–68 of S. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Bueno, O., and Colyvan, M. (2011), ‘An Inferential Conception of the Application of Mathematics’, Noûs 45: 345–74. Carnap, R. (1950), ‘Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4: 20–40; reprinted as pp. 205–21 of Meaning and Necessity: a Study in Semantics and Modal Logic, 2nd ed., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
References
67
Chakravartty, A. (2017), ‘Scientific Realism’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientificrealism/. Clarke-Doane, J. (2022), Mathematics and Metaphilosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Colyvan, M. (2001), The Indispensability of Mathematics, New York: Oxford University Press. Colyvan, M. (2019), ‘Indispensability Arguments in the Philosophy of Mathematics’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mathphil-indis/. Cotnoir, A., and Weber, Z. (2015), ‘Inconsistent Boundaries’, Synthese 192: 1267–94. Crosilla, L. (2019), ‘Set Theory: Constructive and Intuitionist ZF’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/set-theory-constructive/. Curry, H. (1951), Outlines of a Formalist Philosophy of Mathematics, Amsterdam: North-Holland. Da Costa, N. (1974), ‘On the Theory of Inconsistent Formal Systems’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15: 497–509. Davies, E. B. (2005), ‘A Defence of Mathematical Pluralism’, Philosophia Mathematica 13: 252–76. Doherty, F. (2017), ‘Hilbert on Consistency as a Guide to Mathematical Reality’, Logique et Analyse 237: 107–28. Dummett, M. (2000), Elements of Intuitionism, 2nd ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press. Eklund, M. (2019), ‘Fictionalism’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fictionalism/. Enderton, H. (1977), Elements of Set Theory, New York: Academic Press. Engeler, E., and Röhrl, H. (1969), ‘On the Problems of Foundations of Category Theory’, Dialectica 23: 58–66. Field, H. (1980), Science without Numbers, Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2nd ed., 2016. Field, H. (1989), ‘Introduction: Fictionalism, Epistemology, and Modality’, ch. 1 of Realism, Mathematics, and Modality, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. French, S. (2019), ‘Identity and Individuality in Quantum Theory’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford .edu/entries/qt-idind/. Friend, M. (2014), Pluralism in Mathematics: A New Position in Philosophy of Mathematics, Dordrecht: Springer.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
68
References
Gregory, H. (2015), Language and Logics: An Introduction to the Logical Foundations of Language, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Hájek, P., and Haniková, Z. (2003), ‘A Development of Set Theory in Fuzzy Logic’, pp. 273–85 of M. Fitting and E. Orłowska (eds.), Beyond Two: Theory and Applications of Multiple-Valued Logic, Heidelberg: Springer. Hallett, M. (2013), ‘Zermelo’s Axiomatization of Set Theory’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/zermelo-set-theory/. Hamkins, J. (2012), ‘The Set-Theoretic Multiverse’, Review of Symbolic Logic 5: 416–49. Hamkins, J. (2020), Lectures on the Philosophy of Mathematics, Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press. Hamkins. J. (2023), ‘Skolem’s Paradox’, Infinitely More, https://www.infi nitelymore.xyz/p/skolems-paradox. Hamkins, J., and Yang, R. (2013), ‘Satisfaction is Not Absolute’, arXiv: 1312.0670, https://arxiv.org/abs/1312.0670. Hatcher, W. (1982), The Logical Foundations of Mathematics, Oxford: Pergamon Press. Hellman, G., and Bell, J. (2006), ‘Pluralism and the Foundations of Mathematics’, pp. 64–79 of C. Waters, H. Longino, and S. Kellert (eds.), Scientific Pluralism, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Holmes, M. (2017), ‘Alternative Axiomatic Set Theories’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ settheory-alternative/#AckeSetTheo. Horsten, L. (2017), ‘Philosophy of Mathematics’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/philosophy-mathematics. Hylton, P., and Kemp, G. (2019), ‘Willard Van Orman Quine’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ quine/. Iemhoff, R. (2013), ‘Intuitionism in the Philosophy of Mathematics’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/intuitionism/. Irvine, A. (2015), ‘Principia Mathematica’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/principiamathematica/. Jacob, P. (2023), ‘Intentionality’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/intentionality/. Koellner P. (2009), ‘Truth in Mathematics: The Question of Pluralism’, pp. 80–116 of O. Bueno and Ø. Linnebo (eds.), New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics: New Waves in Philosophy, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
References
69
Koellner, P. (2010), ‘Independence and Large Cardinals’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ independence-large-cardinals/. Koellner, P. (2013), ‘Large Cardinals and Determinacy’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ large-cardinals-determinacy/. Knuth, D. (1974), Surreal Numbers, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Kroon, F., and Voltolini, A. (2023), ‘Fictional Entities’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ fictional-entities/. Kunen, K. (1980), Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs, Amsterdam: North Holland. Levy, A. (1979), Basic Set Theory, Berlin: Springer. Maddy, P. (1997), Naturalism in Mathematics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Maddy, P. (2007), Second Philosophy: A Naturalistic Method, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Marquis, J.-P. (2014), ‘Category Theory’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/categorytheory/. McCarty, D. (1991), ‘Incompleteness in Intuitionist Mathematics’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32: 323–58. Miller, A., and Sultanescu, O. (2022), ‘Rule Following and Intentionality’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford .edu/entries/rule-following/. Mortensen, C. (1995), Inconsistent Mathematics, Dordrecht: Kluwer. Mortensen, C. (2010), Inconsistent Geometry, London: College Publications. Mortensen, C. (2017), ‘Inconsistent Mathematics’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mathematicsinconsistent/. Moss, L. (2018), ‘Non-wellfounded Set Theory’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nonwellfoun ded-set-theory/. Petersen, U. (2000), ‘Logic without Contraction and Based on Unrestricted Abstraction’, Studia Logica 64: 365–403. Pincock, C. (2004), ‘A New Perspective on the Problem of Applying Mathematics’, Philosophia Mathematica 12: 135–61. Pincock, C. (2014), ‘How to Avoid Inconsistent Idealizations’, Synthese 191: 2957–72.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
70
References
Posy, C. (2020), Mathematical Intuitionism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Priest, G. (1973), ‘A Bedside Reader’s Guide to the Conventionalist Philosophy of Mathematics’, pp. 115–32 of J. Bell, J. Cole, G. Priest, and A. Slomson (eds.), Proceedings of the Bertrand Russell Memorial Logic Conference, Denmark 1971, Leeds: University of Leeds. Priest, G. (1997a), ‘Sylvan’s Box’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38: 573–82; reprinted as §6.6 of Priest (2005). Priest, G. (1997b), ‘Inconsistent Models of Arithmetic, I: Finite Models’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 26: 1519–25. Priest, G. (1998), ‘Number’, pp. 47–54, Vol. 7, of E. Craig (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London: Routledge. Priest, G. (2000), ‘Inconsistent Models of Arithmetic, II: The General Case’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 65: 223–35. Priest, G. (2003), ‘On Alternative Geometries, Arithmetics, and Logics: A Tribute to Łukasiewicz’, Studia Logica 74: 441–68. Priest, G. (2005), Towards Non-Being, Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2nd ed., 2016. Priest, G. (2006a), In Contradiction, 2nd ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press. Priest, G. (2006b), ‘Logical Pluralism’, ch. 12 of Doubt Truth to be a Liar, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Priest, G. (2010), ‘Quine: Naturalism Unravelled’, pp. 19–30 of M. Dumitru and C. Stoenescu (eds.), Cuvinte, Teorii si Lucruri: Quine in Perspectiva, Bucharest: Editura Pelican. Priest, G. (2013a), ‘Mathematical Pluralism’, Logic Journal of IGPL 21: 4–14. Priest, G. (2013b), ‘Indefinite Extensibility: Dialetheic Style’, Studia Logica 101: 1263–75. Priest, G. (2014), ‘Revising Logic’, ch. 12 of P. Rush (ed.), The Metaphysics of Logic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Priest, G. (2016), ‘Logical Disputes and the a Priori’, Logique et Analyse 236: 347–66. Priest, G. (2017), ‘What If? The Exploration of an Idea’, Australasian Journal of Logic 14(1): Article 4, https://ojs.victoria.ac.nz/ajl/article/view/4028/ 3574. Priest, G. (2019a), ‘From the Foundations of Mathematics to Mathematical Pluralism’, pp. 363–80 of S. Centrone, D. Kant, and D. Sarikaya (eds.), Reflections on the Foundations of Mathematics: Univalent Foundations, Set Theory and General Thoughts, New York: Springer. Priest, G. (2019b), ‘Gödel’s Theorem and Paraconsistency’, in E. Almeida, A. Costa-Leite, and R. Freire (eds.), Lógica no Avião, http://lna.unb.br/lna _n01_01_gpriest.pdf.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
References
71
Priest, G. (2021a), ‘Logical Abductivism and Non-Deductive Inference’, Synthese 199: 3207–17. Priest, G. (2021b), ‘A Note on Mathematical Pluralism and Logical Pluralism’, Synthese 198: 4937–46. Priest, G. (202+a), ‘How Do You Apply Mathematics?’, Axiomathes, forthcoming. Priest, G. (202+b), ‘Logic as Applied Mathematics: With Application to the Notion of Logical Form’, to appear. Priest, G., Berto, F., and Weber, Z. (2022), ‘Dialetheism’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ dialetheism/. Priest, G., Tanaka, K., and Weber, Z. (2022), ‘Paraconsistent Logic’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/logic-paraconsistent/. Quine, W. (1951), ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, Philosophical Review 60: 20–43; reprinted as ch. 2 of From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Reck, E., and Schiemer, G. (2019), ‘Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/structuralism-mathematics/. Reicher, M. (2019a), ‘Alexius Meinong’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meinong/. Reicher, M. (2019b), ‘Non-Existent Objects’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nonexistentobjects/. Russell, G. (2019), ‘Logical Pluralism’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logical-plura lism/. Sambin, G. (2011), ‘A Minimalist Foundation at Work’, ch. 4 of D. DeVidi, M. Hallett, and P. Clarke (eds.), Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy, Vintage Enthusiasms: Essays in Honour of John L. Bell, Heidelberg: Springer. Shapiro, S. (2004), ‘Foundations of Mathematics: Ontology, Epistemology, Structure’, Philosophical Quarterly 54: 16–37. Shapiro, S. (2014), Varieties of Logic, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stei, E. (2023), Logical Pluralism and Logical Consequence, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sweeney, D. (2014), ‘Chunk and Permeate: The Infinitesimals of Isaac Newton’, History and Philosophy of Logic 35: 1–23. Takeuti, G. (1981), ‘Quantum Set Theory’, pp. 303–22 of E. Beltrametti and B. van Fraassen (eds.), Current Issues in Quantum Logic, New York: Plenum.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
72
References
Tal, E. (2020), ‘Measurement in Science’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/measure ment-science/. Tennant, N. (2017), ‘Logicism and Neologicism’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logicism/. Van Atten, M. (2017), ‘The Development of Intuitionist Logic’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/intuitionistic-logic-development/. Warren, J. (2015), ‘Conventionalism, Consistency, and Consistency Sentences’, Synthese 192: 1351–71. Weber, Z. (2010), ‘Transfinite Numbers in Paraconsistent Set Theory’, Review of Symbolic Logic 3: 71–92. Weber, Z. (2012), ‘Transfinite Cardinals in Paraconsistent Set Theory’, Review of Symbolic Logic 5: 269–93. Weber, Z. (2021), Paradoxes and Inconsistent Mathematics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Weber, Z. (2022), Paraconsistency in Mathematics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Weir, A. (2019), ‘Formalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/formalismmathematics/. Wigner, E. (1960), ‘The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences’, Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics 13: 1–14. Williamson, T. (2018), ‘Alternative Logics and Applied Mathematics’, Philosophical Issues 28: 399–424. Wittgenstein, L. (1953), Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Wittgenstein, L. (1964), Philosophical Remarks, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Wittgenstein, L. (1967), Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press. Zach, R. (2023), ‘Hilbert’s Program’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hilbert-program/. Zalta, E. (2016), ‘Frege’, in E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/frege/. Zalta, E. (2023), ‘Mathematical Pluralism’, Noûs, https://onlinelibrary.wiley .com/doi/full/10.1111/nous.12451.
Acknowledgments
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
This Element is dedicated, with pleasure, to Hartry Field and Stewart Shapiro, two dear friends and fellow philosophers of mathematics, with much thanks for many happy years of agreement and disagreement.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
The Philosophy of Mathematics Penelope Rush University of Tasmania From the time Penny Rush completed her thesis in the philosophy of mathematics (2005), she has worked continuously on themes around the realism/anti-realism divide and the nature of mathematics. Her edited collection The Metaphysics of Logic (Cambridge University Press, 2014), and forthcoming essay ‘Metaphysical Optimism’ (Philosophy Supplement), highlight a particular interest in the idea of reality itself and curiosity and respect as important philosophical methodologies.
Stewart Shapiro The Ohio State University Stewart Shapiro is the O’Donnell Professor of Philosophy at The Ohio State University, a Distinguished Visiting Professor at the University of Connecticut, and a Professorial Fellow at the University of Oslo. His major works include Foundations without Foundationalism (1991), Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology (1997), Vagueness in Context (2006), and Varieties of Logic (2014). He has taught courses in logic, philosophy of mathematics, metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of religion, Jewish philosophy, social and political philosophy, and medical ethics.
About the Series
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
This Cambridge Elements series provides an extensive overview of the philosophy of mathematics in its many and varied forms. Distinguished authors will provide an up-to-date summary of the results of current research in their fields and give their own take on what they believe are the most significant debates influencing research, drawing original conclusions.
The Philosophy of Mathematics Elements in the Series Paraconsistency in Mathematics Zach Weber Mathematical Anti-Realism and Modal Nothingism Mark Balaguer Plato Was Not a Mathematical Platonist Elaine Landry Mathematics and Explanation Christopher Pincock Indispensability A. C. Paseau and Alan Baker Lakatos and the Historical Approach to Philosophy of Mathematics Donald Gillies Phenomenology and Mathematics Michael Roubach Philosophical Uses of Categoricity Arguments Penelope Maddy and Jouko Väänänen
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009091640 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Number Concepts Richard Samuels and Eric Snyder The Euclidean Programme A. C. Paseau and Wesley Wrigley Mathematical Rigour and Informal Proof Fenner Stanley Tanswell Mathematical Pluralism Graham Priest A full series listing is available at: www.cambridge.org/EPM