128 27 14MB
English Pages 272 [285] Year 2019
Knowing and History
Also by Michael
S.
Roth
Psycho-Analysis as History: Negation and Freedom in
Freud
Knowing and History Appropriations of Hegel in
Twentieth-Century France
Michael
S.
Roth
Cornell University Press Ithaca and
London
Copyright
©
1988 by Cornell University
All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review, this
book, or parts thereof, must not be reproduced in any form
without permission
in writing
from the publisher. For
infor-
mation, address Cornell University Press, 124 Roberts Place, Ithaca,
First
New
York 14850.
published 1988 by Cornell University Press.
International Standard
Book Number 0-8014-2136-5
Library of Congress Catalog Card
Number 87-47870
Printed in the United States of America Librarians: Library of Congress cataloging information ap-
pears on the last page of the book.
The paper in this book is acid-free and meets the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources.
For Laurence
Contents
Preface
ix
Acknowledgments Introduction. Between Part One.
xiv Crisis
From Humanism
and Closure
i
to Being: Jean Hyppolite
1.
Heroic Hegelianism
2.
Logic in History and the Problematic of
3.
From Humanism
19
Humanism
Part
17
46 66
to Being
Two. After the End: Alexandre Kojeve
81
4.
Absolutes and History
5.
Desire, Dialectic, and History
6.
No Guarantees:
83
Irony and the End of History
94 125
Part Three. Progress and the Elmination of Sens: Eric Weil
8.
From Certainty to From Uncertainty
9.
Styles of Delegitimation:
7.
Participation to Nostalgia
Afterword.
147 149 165
187 leuze,
and Foucault
Nietzsche, De-
189
Contents
Appendix. Participants in Kojeve's
Seminar at the Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes, 1933-1939
225
Bibliography
228
Index
251
Preface
From
the 1930s through the postwar period in France,
Hegehan
phi-
losophers such as Jean HyppoUte, Alexandre Kojeve, and Eric Weil
turned to history as the source of truths and criteria of judgment.
They explored how
philosophy of history could serve as the foundation for understanding the modern world and for providing insight into
how
a
that world might be changed for the better.
They
forged
connections between history and knowing as a means of confronting
key theoretical problems and of engaging contemporary political concerns. All three began publishing in the 1930s, and Hyppolite and Weil taught philosophy in France after World War II. Kojeve, leader of a famous seminar on Hegel in the 1930s, continued to write philosophy after the war but spent much of his time working for the French government on problems of economic development. By the mid-i9sos, however, all three thinkers had withdrawn from the historical in search of a reflection.
more
secure, or
more
hopeful, subject for
Hegelian historicizing declined with the loss of faith in
seemed to undermine even the thought of heroic or radical political change, and the development of sophisticated methodologies of the synchronic in linguistics, anthropology, and cybernetics legitimated a retreat from the meaningfulness of history. Contemporary events
the historical.
have chosen to study the Hegelians because their work illuminates power and the limitation of the philosophic approach to history. In the development of their philosophies, moreover, we can see one I
the
of the crucial transformations in
modern
intellectual history: the shift
Preface
concern with questions of significance to a concern with questions of use or function, from "What does our history mean? " or "How can we make sense of our past?" to "How does our history work?"
from
or
a
"How
is
our past put together?" This
interpretations of our past
shift
which generate
moves us away from
stories that
can guide and
legitimate our actions, and toward analyses (or even deconstructions) that
show how
particular versions of our past serve specific interests,
powers, or desires. The still
not
clear, as
implications of this transformation are
full
they form part of our cultural present.
My
study of
the French Hegelians is intended to clarify the significance of the contemporary retreat from questions of significance (especially, though not exclusively, in France), by providing some of the material
necessary for situating our cultural
moment
in relation to its intel-
lectual antecedents.
This book, then,
is a
re-collection of the Hegelian approach to his-
tory and of the transformation within the
Hegel. of
It
modern appropriation
thought which has fallen by the wayside over the
last
of
mode
should not be read as an expression of nostalgia for a
twenty-five
years as structuralism and poststructuralism have challenged the phi-
losophy of history and even the usefulness of making meaning out of historical change.
The questions
that Hyppolite, Kojeve, and Weil
posed to personal and political history are not our questions, and analysis of their
work
is
my
not intended as an advertisement for their
style of philosophizing. Yet
I
trust that
a history of the present insofar as
what follows
will be read as
an understanding of our connections
with and differences from this style contributes to our ability to make sense of the questions we choose and refuse to pose in order to make meaning out of change over time.
The is
intellectual historian
who
turns to the history of philosophy
confronted immediately with difficult methodological and profes-
sional problems. Perhaps the
most important
of these are difficulties
inherent in any study of the development of culture, most of which
have to do with the relative autonomy of the object of study. One must always try to steer a course between the parallel pitfalls of isolation and reduction. If one treats the cultural object or field as and contemporary sigfully autonomous, then the wider cultural
—
—
nificance of the object or field can be lost.
cance of the object or
If
one locates the
signifi-
field solely in its sociocultural relations,
then
Preface
import or point dissolves as it is replaced by expression of something, or someone, else. its specific
its role
as an
problem has usuterms of the text /context relationship. Whether this relationship was never more than a mere presupposition of mtellecIn the historiography of intellectual history, the
ally
been seen
in
tual history, as
Hayden White has
asserted,'
it
seems
clear that
we
can no longer simply appeal to a "balance" between text and context. Even the terms of such a compromise are now fully ambiguous: What is
a context
if
not a more or less arbitrarily selected group of texts
that refer to events or persons
made
relevant to the primary texts
My is not that nothing outside the text," which has about the same claim on us as "there is nothing outside the void." Instead, the question under consideration? "there
point in raising this question
is
points to the fact that in the study of history, the Real
presented to us as mediated by texts.' best
way
Much
What we want
is
always
to find
is
the
of reading these texts.
on intellectual history in recent years has focused on ways of reading.^ Hermeneutics and semiotics with varying degrees of psychoanalysis and Marxism added to the mix seem to be the techniques most favored in contemporary metahistorical discourse. Their respective foci on content and form have been enhanced by the cross-fertilizations of anthropology and linguistics, both of which have taught intellectual historians to look for meaning in places where otherwise they might not of the interesting theoretical writing
—
—
have strayed. The form of the present work can best be characterized as "historical/internalist." This description does not mean that my analysis of the philosophers' texts excludes side" their work, only that
I
all
consideration of referents "out-
have concentrated on the temporal and
1. Hayden White, "Method and Ideology in Intellectual History: The Case of Henry Adams," in Modern European Intellectual History: Reappraisals and New Perspectives, ed. Dominick LaCapra and Steven L. Kaplan (Ithaca, N.Y., 1982), 281. 2. See, for example, Fredric Jameson, The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a
Socially Symbolic Act (Ithaca, N.Y., 1981), 82, 100-102. 3. See LaCapra and Kaplan, Modern European Intellectual History, and LaCapra,
Rethinking Intellectual History: Texts, Contexts, Language (Ithaca, N.Y., 1983), and History and Criticism (Ithaca, N.Y., 1985); Robert Darnton, "Intellectual and Cultural History," in The Past before Us, ed. Michael Kammen (Ithaca, N.Y., 1980); and Hayden White, Tropics of Discourse (Baltimore, Md., 1978).
Preface
thematic development of the
aimed
would be fair to say that the work" in contradistinction
texts.
to explicate the "life of
It
of the philosopher." Intellectual historians
''life
I
have
to the
have usually taken
individual biography as the mediation between particular ideas and
the culture in
which they
are produced.
Although
this
occasionally produced a brilliant picture of a cultural
approach has
moment,
it
has
often resulted in a trivialization of the problematics explored in the
book I have with the French Hegelians without the mediation provided by biography and have adopted a discourse that aims to speak with them at the same time as it addresses our own texts, or else in their excessive personalization. In this
tried to enter into a dialogue
concerns. In so doing,
have on occasion reflected their concerns
I
against the background of important changes in contemporary French culture, but only in order to illuminate the
there
is
a "position"
behind
my own mode
historical /internalist approach to culture
work
of the Hegelians.
of discussion,
it is
If
that a
need not be an oxymoron.
Anyone who writes on modern French intellectual history does so shadow of the great wave of theoretical activity in the human
in the
sciences in France over the last thirty years. Indeed,
I
first
chose this
topic because the French Hegelian philosophers had developed a radical
historicism that was in direct conflict with the succeeding gen-
eration's antihistoricist stance. Here,
I
thought, was the chance to
understand, perhaps obliquely, structuralism and what follows by
movements were reacting against. Instead, found move away from historicism had already begun with Hyp-
seeing what these that the
polite, Kojeve,
I
and Weil
absence in this book, of the
it
at the
may
end
of the 1940s.
If
there
is
a felt
be the lack of any detailed exploration
connection between Hegelianism and the development
of struc-
turalism and poststructuralism. Although not a systematic study of this connection, the last chapter
attempts to explain
how
Nietzsche
replaced Hegel as the locus of philosophic authority in France in the 1960s, and
how
this
replacement was in part effected by Gilles Dework of Michel Foucault. The use of Nietzsche
leuze and informed the
against a so-called metaphysical history
some
was an eventually unsuc-
problems the Hegelians confronted, problems that remain relevant to the projects of both Foucault and Deleuze. The retreat from for some, the advance over the humanist percessful attempt to avoid
—
xii
of the crucial
—
— Preface
was a crucial conmodes of thought. Yet until and nonhumanist approaches becomes
spective essential for the Hegelians in the 1940s dition for the evolution of structuralist
the itinerary of these anti-
—
it seems to me unwise except for programmatic purposes attempt to delineate their historical interrelations. I might add also
clearer,
to
that
it
seems
to
—
me unwise — except for the tactical purposes of certain
individuals to assume that these anti- and nonhumanist approaches have in any way been proved or legitimated by something called philosophy or theory. Certainly, the trope of sophistication makes it difficult to
pretend otherwise, but a history of the academic impor-
lies beyond the bounds of this study. That said, the reader may still find that the present work suffers from a nostalgia for the humanism that "deconstruction" has made depasse. As far as I can tell, this book contains no implicit humanist agenda that would entail a return to earlier notions of the subject. Nevertheless, 1 trust it will become clear that 1 have re-collected the historicist /humanist problematic of French Hegelianism because I think it can speak to present concerns with how and why we make meaning out of change over time. That is, 1 believe that a faithful account of the development of the work of Hyppolite, Kojeve, and Weil can enrich our historical understanding of the cultural present. The other shadow thrown across my study of the French Hegelians is that of Hegel himself. I make no attempt to determine if the French "got Hegel right." 1 treat French Hegelianism as a mode of philosophizing and do not evaluate its interpretations and translations in
tance of that trope
relation to the ificationist
German
"original." For
impulse that
lies at
someone who
retains the ver-
the origins of professional historiog-
would not be a complete waste of time, but it IS not mine. However, insofar as the Hegelian tradition has fed off the negation of a rigid distinction between history and philosophy, my work can be located within that tradition. In researching and
raphy, such a project
writing this book,
I
have
tried to be
mindful
areas and of the exigencies of both disciplines.
developments in both hope that what follows
of I
will speak to the concerns of historians and philosophers; indeed, to
us who have a stake in change over time.
all of
how we
give
meaning and direction
to
Acknowledgments
I gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the Council for European Studies at Princeton University, the French Government Fellowship Program, the Social Science Research Council, and the Whiting Foundation, whose combined support enabled me to spend
two years
in France.
ships have helped
More
me
recently, Scripps College research fellow-
return to France and have freed time for revi-
The American Council of Learned Societies Post-Doctoral Fellowship for the Study of Modern Society and Values supported the sions.
research for the final chapter of the book and gave
put
it
me
the time to
Nancy Burson has shown remarkable and competence in typmg the manuscript.
in final form.
kindness,
Before going to Paris in 1981
I
patience,
benefited from the intellectual stim-
ulation and support of the history department at Princeton University.
The freedom
of intellectual inquiry
which
preserves against the
it
combined with a rigorous critical spirit to promote an openminded but fairly skeptical community of ideas. I am grateful for having had the opportunity to ever-rising tide of professional specialization
participate in
My work
is
it.
in France
was made more
amiable contact with French scholars.
fruitful 1
and more enjoyable by
express
my debt
to
Raymond
book and discussing them with me. The personal generosity and warmth of each man adds to the loss one feels in their deaths. I am most grateful to Claude Lefort for his help throughout my stay in France
Aron and
especially to Michel Foucault for reading drafts of this
Ackn o wJcd^m en ts and for his criticisms and comments on all stages of this project. Eugene Fleischmann shared with me his detailed knowledge of Hegelian philosophy and opened new perspectives for me on philosophy and history. I am grateful to him for his encouragement and shall always value his friendship dearly. The sections on Alexandre Kojeve and Eric Weil would not be what they are without the help I received from Nina Ivanoff, the legatee of Kojeve, and from Anne Weil and Catherine Mendelssohn, the wife and sister-in-law of Weil. Anne Weil gave generously of herself at the end of her life, and like so many others I keep a fond memory of her strong, sensitive spirit. The openness, intelligence, and generosity of these women have been equaled only by their kindness. An earlier version of this book was read by Victor Gourevitch, Jerrold Seigel, and Sheldon Wolin, who gave me detailed comments on early drafts and talked with me at length and in depth about the interrelationship of politics, philosophy, and history. Professor Gourevitch first introduced me to Hegel and Kojeve when I was an undergraduate at Wesleyan University, and he has responded with patience to my questions about history and philosophy ever since. At Princeton, Carl Schorske has also listened to these questions and suffered through my repeated attempts to work out answers to them. His criticism and support vastly improved my work, and his teaching remains
for
me
By continuing
a
model
of pedagogy.
to reveal to
me some
wife, Laurence Roth, has contributed
of the
meanings
more than she
of destiny,
realizes to
my my
understanding of knowing and of history. Although these meanings are rarely very clear, they are never,
I
begin to see, unimportant.
Michael Claremont, California
S.
Roth
Knowing and History
Introduction:
Between
One
Crisis
and Closure
of the truisms of the history of
French philosophy
is
that
it
was the importation of German philosophy, specifically of phenomenology, which loosened the rigid, academic orthodoxy of the neoKantians. This truism, like so many other philosophical myths, comes to us from existentialists, who early on began to think of themselves as historical figures. Perhaps the best story
we have
about the young Sartre who, sitting in a cafe (where
in
tiiis
regard
is
else?), listens to
Raymond Aron's story about how in Germany (where else?) they can make philosophy out of a cocktail.' The human element will come back into French philosophy, so goes the moral of the story, when existentialism becomes the guardian of a radical humanism and keeps its
philosophical lamp on everyday
When
Sartre left for
Germany
life.
in 1933,
however, the French aca-
demic philosophical orthodoxy had already begun to change. Although the stimulus for some of these changes provided by Husserl and Heidegger was far from negligible, the impact of Hegelian philosophy in France was a crucial component of the new ground (or new groundlessness) of philosophy which emerged in the postwar period. The normal discourse of academic philosophy was changing, if not unraveling, by the 1930s, and the French reading of Hegel was a major force in that decomposition." The protean character of He1. 1
Given
in
Simonc de Beauvoir, The Prime
of Life, trans. P.
Green (London,
1963),
12. 2.
For useful summaries of Hegel interpretation in France from the nineteenth cen-
tury through the mid-twentieth, see Iring Fetscher, "Hegel in Frankreich," Antares
3
Introduction
gelianism added to the importance of the philosophy, because in France Hegelianism was ahgned with critical intellectual move-
among them surrealism, Marxism, and existentialism. In most forms French Hegelianism was a vehicle for confronting the historical, for thinking about the connection between history and ments, of its
knowing.
The
work
1 examine in detail in this book was published in symbol for the resurgence of Hegelianism. Jean Wahl's Le malheur de la conscience dans la philosophic de Hegel was in many ways a book about crisis, a book about history, even though the Great Depression would not reach France for some years after the stock market crashed in New York. Instead of focusing on the conditions of rationality or on the bases for the development of scientific knowledge, Wahl examined the centrality of alienation and longing to any form of historical progress. The crisis may be in one's personal life or in one's community, Wahl asserted, but the experience of crises is a necessary component of their progressive resolution. The other forms of French Hegelianism I examine briefly in this chapter those of Alexandre Koyre, surrealism, and Marxism also stress crisis in one form or another. The surrealists, in many ways
first
1929, a fine
—
—
Wahl, make history the object of philosophical reflection in order the irremediable element of alienation or diremption in psychological and social life. In contrast, Koyre and the Marxists have a
like to
show
on these forms of crisis. Koyre is interwhich Hegelianism passes from historical disphilosophical closure as a system. The Marxists, of course,
different reason for focusing
ested in the
junction to
way
in
are also keenly concerned with historical disjunction. For them, the
Hegelian notions of mediation and dialectical change are important not because they resolve crisis in a system but because they point to the closure that can occur through radical historical action.
Jean Wahl and Alexandre Koyre Wahl's Le malheur de la conscience marked a beginning of the Hegel renaissance in France. Wahl aimed consciously to introduce
Hegel to the French, and he did so from the perspective
of the phi-
(lys^l ^-iS; lacqucs d'Hondt, Hcy,cl ct I'lit'^elianismc (Pans, 1982); and Lawrence Pitkethly, "Hesel in Modern France" (Ph.D. diss., London School of Economics, lyysl-
Between Crisis and Closure losopher's early works,
and 1907.' Because
which had hccn puhhshcd in Germany Wahl's hook hecame
of this perspective,
in a
90s point 1
French reading of Hegel. To the extent that Hegel had been studied in France previously, he was read as the author of the Logic and of the System and represented at once the two great sins of philosophical pride and intellectual abstraction: "pride," because he rejected Kant's view that philosophy should follow the sciences and instead thought of philosophy as the supreme science to be followed by other disciplines; "abstraction," because to construct the grand machine of the System, Hegel seemed to omit all properly human elements. Wahl's book took a wholly different tack toward Hegel, for he wrote Le malheur de la conscience after having considof departure in the
ered Kierkegaard's existentialist critique of the System."* In Hegel's early texts
Wahl found
a
budding
existentialist, a
copain
who would
have identified with Kierkegaard's fear and trembling, and with the anxiety that many of Wahl's readers felt at the beginning of the 1930s. Wahl's Hegel, then, is not the creator of a comprehensive philosophical method that can account for all entities in this world. On the contrary, the dialectic is first "an experience by which Hegel passed from one idea to another."^ Wahl shows his reader the theologian behind the scientific philosopher and the romantic behind the rationalist.
Rather than summarize Wahl's book,
I
here point out only
its
major
themes, those which played a role in French Hegelianism generally and in the work of Jean Hyppolite in particular. The first and most important of these themes is the idea of the "unhappy consciousness." Readers of the Phenomenology will recognize this concept as an important part of that work, but for Wahl the idea became emblematic of the Hegelian project and of modern personal and historical existence as a whole. Simply put, the unhappy consciousness is the awareness that
all
human development
is a
product of alienation,- that
is,
personal growth and historical progress take place by virtue of a rad-
3.
By Dilthcy,
ichen
in "Jugendgeschichte Hegel,"
Akademie der Wissenschaften
(Berlin,
Abhandhmg
der koniglichen preuss-
and H. Nohl, Theologische fugendschriften 1907). Hegel's [ena Realphilosophie did not become available until 1931 and (1905),
1932.
Modern France," 382. conscience dans la philosophie de Hegel (Paris, All translations of quotations are my own unless otherwise specified.
4.
As Wahl
5.
Jean Wahl, Le
1929), 9.
said in an interview with Pitkethly, "Hegel in
malheur de
la
Introduction ical separation of the subject
ment
from what
it
desires.
Human
develop-
making the connection between the For the unhappy consciousness, though, the
bridges that separation,
subject and
its
other.
always divided and always longing for reconciliation. Wahl thinks that the dialectic in all its forms can be understood best from this existential /romantic base. The contradiction between
person
thesis
is
and antithesis, and the mediation
(or
mediator) that brings
about a synthesis, he understands as abstractions from the funda-
mental experiential basis
of
human
alienation, despair
and hope. The
reconciliation or synthesis that does take place should produce nei-
ther a system nor a science; instead, fati.
Wahl claims not
it
results in
wisdom and amor
that Hegel's early philosophy ends only with a
romantic longing after a lost unity but that attempts at unification always begin from the experience of this longing. He does not deny the rationalist goal of Hegel's project, but he underlines the romantic inspiration at the core of that project.'^
This emphasis on the unhappy consciousness leads Wahl to consider the role of a concept of history in Hegel's thought. History
is
upon which the quest for reconciliation takes place most the vehicle through which reconciliation is achieved. In
at least the field
and
at
either case,
how
if
we
to achieve
it,
are to
then
know anything about this reconciliation and we have to grasp change over time as triumph
over alienation and separation. History itual progress,
and Wahl
is
the story of moral or spir-
sets the structure of that story
by giving
prominence to the unhappy consciousness. Progress is therefore achieved at severe cost, for alienation and separation are the necessary conditions for history truly to continue
— that
is,
for
man
not to sink
into the oblivion of repetition.
Consolation for the unhappy consciousness
is
the belief that history
will continue, the belief that the story of spiritual progress
makes
sense in the end because in the End, reconciliation will come. Change
over time
is
configured as progress because reconciliation
as the goal of history.
This
is
is
figured
the guarantee that the unhappiness of
Good News that the story of history The Hegelian "cross of the an ultimate homecoming in which the
separation will not be in vain, the is
written in the language of eternity.
present"
is
only a sign of
subject and its objects will be one. 6.
For Wahl's interpretation of
what he saw
as the concept of a "sacred history" in
Hegel, see especially Le malheur, 147, 186, i99n, 2^1, 248.
Between
Crisis
For Wahl's Hegel, then, history has a crucial heuristic than a determining
and Closure
role,
one/ As we come
to
though more
a
understand the
change over time, we gain insight into both the specific diremption of modern man and the necessary connection between all human development and a fundamental unhappiness. Yet structures of personal and collective experience exist that an understanding of history cannot account for and that make such an understanding possible in the first place. To apprehend change over time as progress, and to understand the price paid for our personal and collective advancement, Wahl's Hegel tells us we must look beyond the merely temporal. There we will find a guarantee that change over time has meaning and direction. Wahl's writing on Hegel is part of what Wahl later referred to as the movement toward the concrete.^ By viewing Hegel as a philosopher concerned deeply with history, not just with logic, Wahl was taking steps toward a philosophy that would not only concern itself coherence and continuity
in
with the conditions of possibility for a rational thinking based on experience but also focus on making sense of the stuff of experience as it changes. Wahl's Hegel helps the reader see that experience, when properly viewed, constitutes historical progress.
Wahl turned
to history at a
time
when
the contemporary world
especially shook confidence in progress. France had
emerged
victo-
rious from the Great War, but even a relatively simple notion such
seemed problematic by the end of the 1920s. The nation was having enormous difficulty with the path of progress marked out by modern industrial capitalism, and French thinkers were questioning how the nation could become fully modern without losing its as "victory"
Wahl's Hegel provides an account of history that emphasizes and alienation, elements familiar to Wahl's readers. He also reasons to hope that these elements of crisis, although the stuff
identity.
conflict offers
of historical experience, are not definitive.
are independent of historical
The reasons Wahl provides
change and allow us to affirm our con-
fidence that history leads beyond crisis to a form of closure.
Like Wahl, Alexandre Koyre attempted to introduce Hegel to the
French in large part by translating and commenting on Hegel's early texts. For Koyre, however, these texts did not reveal a romantic or '^
7.
Ibid., 173.
8.
Jean Wahl, Vers le concret (Paris, 1932).
9.
Koyre influenced Hegel studies in France largely through his courses on the Ger-
— Introduction
an existentialist thinker as opposed to the systematic philosopher of the Logic and the Encyclopaedia. On the contrary, Koyre saw the
mature work, as an indication of what needed to be systematized. Without the System, Koyre believed, Hegel's "experiences" the term is Wahl's would have no interest early texts as continuous with the
—
—
for us at all.'"
This
is
not to say that Koyre denies the importance of the unhappy
consciousness in Hegel's work. Koyre, too, emphasizes that philos-
ophy grows out
of alienation
and the painful experience
For him, philosophy enters a society
when
of separation.
traditional avenues for
when the meaning becoming increasingly unclear. Philoso-
unifying diverse beliefs and practices are blocked, of the
common
phy
born of disintegration, but as a result of this heritage it seeks harmony in reason as a replacement for the lost
is
language
is
a totalization, a
coherence of
faith.
the effort to
make
heterogeneity.
On
Thus
the impulse toward totalization
is
not simply
the world conform to a principle that allows no the contrary, the experience of
crisis,
the
felt ab-
what gives rise to philosophy, "that which produces and realizes reason." The object of this production is closure but not, and not to be confused with, a homogenein a significant sence of wholeness,
ous
is
— — whole, the coherence of a system."
Whereas Wahl's Hegel ultimately seeks reconciliation in the promise of divine mediation between subject and object, Koyre's Hegel looks to Reason for the coherence that is felt as a painful absence in the life of the individual or of the community. When Koyre's Hegel looks to Reason, he looks to humanity, to history.
If
Wahl's inter-
is existential and theological, then Koyre's Hegel is historand anthropological. For Wahl, that is, the story of progress is written in the language of eternity, whereas for Koyre that story
pretation ical
makes sense only man
if
it
is
told in
human — temporal
or historical
tradition of speculative thought at the Ecolc des Hautes Etudes, and also by three major articles published in the i9^os: "Rapport sur I'etat des etudes hegeliennes en France" (19^0), "Note sur la langue et la terminologie hegeliennes" (1931), and "Hegel a lena" (19 ^4). All three articles are reprinted in Koyre's Etudes d'histoire de la pensee philosophique (Paris, 1961, 197 1). Koyre is not a Hegelian philosopher but rather is stimulated by Hegel's |ena texts, which became available in the early 1930s. Some of the differences between his emphasis and Wahl's can be ascribed to the fact that these texts were not available when Wahl wrote his study. 10. Koyre, "Hegel a lena," Etudes, 151 and n. i. 1
1.
Ibid.,
I
SS-
Between Oisis and Closure discourse.'' Koyrc's reading
is
based on a detailed consideration of
Hegel's conception of time. Hegel's great originality, Koyre is
in
tells us,
developing a concept of time which gives primacy to the future.
The meaning
now
of a
is
contained in
of that future to the past of the a conception of
human
its
future and in the relation
now. Hegel gives
time, because
us, first
we humans
determine our present by our orientation
and foremost,
are beings
who
— hope, expectation, work—
toward the future and by the connection we see between that future and our past. Thus Koyre's reading of Hegel, although it does not ignore the influence of religious thinkers on the philosopher's development, focuses on the secular, historical, and humanistic thrust of his work. Koyre concludes: all, a human time, the time of man, himself this what he is not and is not what he is"; the being who denies himself in what he is in favor of what he is not, or is not yet; the being who, starting from the present, negates it, attempting to
Hegelian time strange being
is,
above
who
"is
accomplish himself in the future,
who
lives for the future, finding there,
or at least searching there, for his truth; the being this constant transformation of the future into the
who
exists only in
"now," and who stops
when there is no longer a future everything has already when everything is already accomplished. And it is because Hegelian time is human that it is also dialectical, since because it is one
being the day
.
.
.
happened,
and the other
it is
essentially a historical time."
For Koyre's Hegel, history has of things
human
is
nection of a present to of the
more than
a heuristic value.
a product of our ability to
human means
its
future and to
Knowledge
understand the con-
its past.
Indeed, knowledge
understanding the place of the
human
in the
closure provided by the total development of history.
12.
Wahl and Koyre, hkc Hyppolite, Mcrlcau-Ponty,
Ko)evc, and Weil, at
some
point
identify history and progress and give primacy to the future in their analysis of historical
my
I follow them by using "history" to refer change over time. I do not here consider whether an idea of history independent of any notion of progress has been (or could be) coherently established, although my final chapter displays the difficulties that two postmodern writers encounter in leaving behind the problematic of progress. IV Ibid., 177. Although Koyre was in no sense a Heideggerian philosopher, the concept of time that he found in Hegel had significant similarities to the analysis of time in Scin unci ZcAt. Heidegger himself saw in Hegel's philosophy a notion of temporality very much opposed to his own: see Sein unci Zeit, sec. 82.
thinking. In
discussion of the Hegelians
to future- or goal-orientcd
7
Introduction
French Hegelianism attempted to steer a course between the positions that Wahl and Koyre developed. Hyppohte would pose to Wahl questions about the real value of history and of human action as such, given
its
dependence on an atemporal, nonhuman End. Although he
privileged "history" in his
own
reading of Hegel, Hyppolite never
fully accepted Koyre's anthropologism. of
any suprahistorical dimension was,
The primacy of a future devoid for Hyppolite, the
primacy
of
uncertainty, a threatening uncertainty that history alone can neither
guard against nor dissolve. Kojeve, on the other hand, would follow in the footsteps of Koyre, embracing Koyre's anthropologism, as well as his analysis of Hegelian time. For Kojeve, however, the absence of a suprahistorical guarantee for a configuration of history as progress did not result in uncertainty.
On
the contrary, history itself offered a guarantee of universal
nificance once occur.
By the
it
became
late
clear that nothing substantially
sig-
new would
1940s Kojeve was trying to articulate this clarity
within an ironic discourse. Weil, too, started with the radical anthropolization of Hegelian
thought which
is
in accordance
with Koyre's analysis
of time.
Unlike
comes with givuncertainty was a crucial
Kojeve, however, Weil accepted the uncertainty that ing primacy to the future. For Weil, this
component of a culture that had renounced violence in favor of discourse. By the 19SOS, though, Weil was looking for a framework for this uncertainty, a guarantee that the renunciation of violence was not in vain. Here we see shades of Wahl, although Weil's turn was toward a neo-Kantian understanding of morality. Although both Wahl and Koyre became important figures in French intellectual life, their early studies were far from the work being done in mainstream French academic philosophy. On the contrary, their writings were among the first breakthroughs against a general hostility toward Hegel that dated back to the philosopher's own time.'^ After World War I academic philosophy in France was dominated by a transcendental idealism, or neo-Kantianism, whose main proponent was Leon Brunschvicg. For Brunschvicg, all of traditional metaphysics worth saving could be reduced to a theory of knowledge, and history specifically
et Vhe^elianisme, 49-54- The exceptions to the rule of hostility Michael Kelly, "Hegel in France to 1940: A Bibliographical Essay," Journal of European Studies II (1981), 29-52.
14.
d'Hondt, He^cl
arc underlined by
Between
was important
for
Crisis
and Closure
philosophy insofar as one could see scientific prog-
it. Progress in science was the model for all forms of advancement. The chief obstacles to scientific and spiritual development, for Brunschvicg, were egocentric judgments or unfounded prejudices. By
ress in
the 1930s, however, such obstacles, important though they might have been on an abstract level, hardly seemed the most threatening elements on the historical horizon.'^
Many
Wahl
students in the 1930s agreed with Koyre and
neo-Kantian approach to history through
a
that the
study of the development
thought missed the crucial components in the world. In the 1930s competing political forces were fighting to define progress, of scientific
but the crucial arena of this fight had
Simone de Beauvoir complained
little to
do with epistemology.
that the neo-Kantian perspective ig-
nored the "adventure of humanity," while Sartre and Merleau-Ponty agreed that the epistemological approach was a form of "high-altitude thinking" that failed to confront the concrete world. "^
was in Germany they found a philosophic movement which seemed to be born of the desire to make sense of that world. The phenomenology of Husserl and its existentialist development by Heidegger attracted many young philosophers from France, most notably Sartre, MerleauIt
Ponty, and Aron. Koyre himself studied philosophy in Heidelberg
and the discussion in Heidegger's Sein und Zeit of Hegel's understanding of temporality was a crucial aspect of the background for Koyre's article on the same subject. By the 1930s Koyre was coeditor of Recherches philosophiques, an annual journal whose central aim was to introduce German philosophy to the French. In Germany, and later in France, the development of phenomenology and existentialism was a rebellion against the neo-Kantian reduction of philosophy to epistemology. Husserl's call to return to "things themselves" and Heidegger's ontological investigations of being-in-the-world were attempts to open philosophy to questions '^ that the problems of scientific knowledge did not traditionally raise. before
coming
to Paris,
15.
See Rene Boirel, Brunschvicg: Sa
16.
Simone de Beauvoir, Memoirs
1959), 243,
and Jean-Paul
vie,
son oeuvre
(Paris, 1964), 31.
of a Dutiful Daughter, trans.
Sartre, Situations, trans. Benita Eisler
].
Kirkup (New York,
(Greenwich, Conn.,
1965), 158. 17. The debate between Cassirer and Heidegger at Davos in 1929 revealed the extreme differences between the style and substance of neo-Kantianism and existential phenomenology. I return in Chapter 2 to Heidegger's contribution at Davos.
Introduction of Hegelianism in France was a facet of this opening philosophy insofar as the French Hegelians saw scientific knowing
The resurgence of
one aspect of the development of Spirit, one way in which was made by humanity. Whereas the neo-Kantians consigned most of history to the domain of the irrational, the Hegelians saw
as only
history
history as the development of Reason in France, history
itself.
Thus, for the Hegelians
became important not only
as the temporal con-
tainer of scientific progress, but also as the fundamental of our effort to
The French fined to
make
dimension
the world our own.
was not conthe academic world but had an important place in more revival of interest in Hegelian philosophy
overtly political domains. Surrealists and Marxists both turned to
Hegel in order to redirect their political concerns.
Surrealism
The
surrealist
movement seems
at first
glance hardly a propitious
place to look for the Hegelian interest in history as a forgotten of philosophy.
The
domain
rejection of the historical in favor of the instinc-
tual, of history in favor of
automaticity, were crucial facets of the
remark in du surrealisme (1930) is emblematic: "I have more confidence in this moment, now, of my thought, than in everything that one would have declared a completed work, a human life having achieved its goal. ... In matters of revolt, none of us should need any ancestors."'"^ Despite this effort at a radical break from the current of history, however, surrealists were led, by their desire to
surrealist rebellion against the real in the 1920s. Breton's
the Seconde manifeste
alter the course of the entire river, to a study of Hegel.
The
came to Hegel after having immersed themselves The study of Freud or, perhaps more accurately, personal
surrealists
in Freud.
—
experiences with certain psychoanalytic texts richer sense of the irrational
—gave
and the daemonic,
of
be the underside of repressive, bourgeois cultural
these artists a
what they took
life.
to
In a word, they
thought they had discovered the reservoirs of desire untapped by mod-
18.
n6.
Andre Breton, Manifcstes du surrealisme,
ed. (ean-facques
Pauvert (Fans, 1972)
Ik'twccn Crisis and Closure
ern capitalist society.''^ Freud and other depth psych()h)gists
have known ahout these wells
must
were too attached to the security of the surface or conscious Hfe to permit any seepage let alone the floods demanded by the surrealists of the irrational into daily life. The surrealists did not have such attachments and so were ready to open the gates to the sources of energy and power. By the late 1920s, however, surrealists were asking themselves how they were going to channel the waters of desire so as to change the forces that had managed to repress desire so well. Freud was content of instinct also, hut they
—
—
to point out the opposition
the
mechanism used
than helpful. But
between desire and
how
to
change social reality so as to bring the down what Freud seemed to think
opposites together?
How
was
not a natural, conflict?
a necessary,
if
and to identify and he seemed less
reality
to maintain that opposition,
to break
For answers to these questions Breton turned to Hegel, whose Logic
he read as an almost heroic attempt to think through the reconciliation of opposites.
The
dialectic for Breton
was
a technique for bring-
ing together apparent irreconcilables."" Hegel
seemed
to offer
an
opportunity to escape the nihilism or narcissism that was the major legacy of "life in the depths." Breton hoped that the power of the
Hegelian dialectic to overcome Freudian dualisms would allow the surrealists to reconnect to political
life,
to
pump
desire into a history-
yet-to-be-made.
The
is well-known and emphasize only that Hegel seemed to offer the surrealists a bridge from the world of instinct to the world of politics. Hegel's promise was to connect psychology with history, to integrate the subjective realm of the individual with the objective realm of social action. Breton, moreover, did not think that Hegel himself had fulfilled his promise in his mature work. Like Wahl, and unlike Koyre, Breton claimed that the experience of the dialectic had
story of the failure of this reconnection
need not be recounted
here."'
I
19. See Anna Balakian, Surrealism: The Road to the Ahsohite (New York, 1959), loo-ioi; Maurice Nadeau, Histoire du surrealisme (Paris, 1964), 20, 76, 157, 186; and
Breton, Manifestes, 28, 48, 146-147, 165. 20. et
See Balakian, Surrealism, 108, and Ferdinand Alquie,
humanisme
existentialiste," in
L'homme,
le
monde,
"Humanisme
surrealiste
I'histoire (Paris, 1948), is3-
21. See Nadeau, Histoire du surrealisme, and Robert S. Short, "The Pohtics of Surreahsm, 1920-1936," Journal of Contemporary History i, no. 2 (1966), 3-25.
II
Introduction to be isolated
from the avortement colossal of the System in order most important contributions/^ Breton, like young
to grasp Hegel's
French Marxists, saw the dialectic as a technique
for
the possibilities of revolutionary change, while he
System
thinking about
condemned
as a reactionary attempt at totalization or closure.
had begun shortly
critique of totalization
has been repeated
many
after Hegel's death,
the
Such and
a it
times since 1945."
Marxism The surrealists were, of course, only a small group within the fragmented French political scene of the 1920s and 1930s. The deep disappointment with the fruits of the victory of 19 18, and the quest for some form of national identity in the face of rapid international industrialization helped push French political life away from a consensus of the center. On the one hand, the international socioeconomic order built after the war and against the Russians was culturally repulsive to both leftists and rightists, for whom it was a form of modernization that meant Americanization. On the other hand, a refusal to participate in this order could
mean
the further decline of
France on the world scene, so that the nation would lose not only its power but its respectability. Political radicalism feeds on such times,
and there appeared
much
a plethora of
Marxist groups devoted
at least as
to theoretical speculation as to political action.
French Marxism was, of course, stimulated greatly by the revolution in Russia. For
many
great experiment, but
it
intellectuals, the revolution represented a
was not
at all clear
how
the results of this
experiment were to be relevant to French politics. The Russian revolution aroused at once hope and fear; hope, because it pointed to the possibility of radical, even heroic, change; fear, because even a revolutionary
movement could become
22. Breton, Manifcstcs, 23.
On
its
repetition of
148-149.
the connection between surrealism, Marxism, and Hegelianism
see Martin Jay,
Hahermas
slavish in
Marxism and
m
France,
The Adventures of a Concept from Liikdcs to 276-299. Jay focuses on Henri Lefebvre. For a more
Totality:
(Berkeley, Calif., 1984),
detailed account of Lefebvre and his context, see Fred Burkhard, "Priests and Jesters:
Henri Lefebvre, the 'Philosophies' Gang, and French Marxism between the Wars" (Ph.D. diss.. University of Wisconsin, Madison, 1986).
12
— Between
Crisis
and Closure
formulas inappropriate to the particular conditions of French political life.-'
During the twenties and
thirties,
some
as well as the discovery of
new
translations of Marx's work,
of his early
manuscripts, further
stimulated theoretical work in French Marxism. Between 1925 and 1940 the complete works of Marx and Engels were published in French
an inexpensive, popular form. More important for our purposes, the 1844 manuscripts were published, piecemeal, between 1929 and 1937. These texts highlight the connection between Hegel and Marx, showing both Marx's debt to Hegel and the struggle of the later thinker to free himself from the burden of influence. One cannot, however, in
Marx
known, and there is some "no real reading of Marx was possible in France until after the Second World War."''' Here I merely point out that the question of the relation between Marx and Hegel, though even among communists it can hardly be described as a mainstream concern, was indeed raised and discussed in France before 1939"^ works
describe these early truth to
Mark
of
as well
Poster's assertion that
The point is important, because in the Marxist treatment of Hegel we can see some of the same themes as in the interpretations of Wahl, Koyre, and Breton. The Revue marxiste, which was dedicated to introducing Marx and Marxist themes into French intellectual life, published a series of articles on Marx's "method" in which Hegel had a prominent place. The author, Charles Rappoport, followed an orthodox communist line in separating what he called Hegel's method the dialectic from his System. The latter, he affirmed, is reactionary
—
insofar as
it
reifies a particular stage in the
and subordinates social of that stage.
Thus
reality to the
the Idea
society of the philosopher
development
of the Idea
supposedly universal rationality
was used
to justify the status
who produced
quo
of the
the System. Nevertheless,
Rappoport emphasized, with the dialectic Hegel introduced a "rev-
24.
This
IS
Intellectuals
Mark
one of the major themes
(New York,
of
David Caute,
Communism and
the French
1964).
Marxism
in Post-War France (Princeton, N.J., 1975), one that is compatible with existentialism. Compare with Jay, Marxism and Totality, 276-299. 26. Indeed, Jay's Marxism and Totality shows that the relation between Marx and Hegel has been an issue for Western Marxism across Europe at least since Georg Lukacs's History and Class Consciousness was published in 1923. 25.
Poster, Existential
42. For Poster, a "real reading" is
13
Introduction
olutionary principle of change and transformation" into philosophy, a principal that,
when wed
to materialism
by Marx, has progressive
implications for social change. Hegel introduced the idea of move-
ment
in the Logic,
and
this notion
was the foundation
of a scientific
socialism that would put the social world into movement."^ Marx, the reader
is
told,
subordinated the idea of any status quo to the
exigencies of social reality
itself. If
tually
becoming
demands were in contrawould have to change, even-
these
diction with the status quo, then society
a fully developed, socialist reality.
A
second noteworthy connection was made between Hegel and Marx during the interwar period by means of the concept of alienation.
The publication of some of the 1844 manuscripts in 1933 and 1937 seemed to clarify the importance of the idea of alienation in Marx's thinking. The scientificity of the dialectical materialism of Capital was undercut by the straightforwardly humanist concerns of these early texts. (It was the discovery of Hegel's early texts that had allowed Wahl to highlight alienation in his Le malheur de la conscience, and in Marx, too, the alienation discussed in early work seemed to make the thinker more "concrete" and historical even "relevant.") Marxist commentators emphasized that Marx's idea of alienation was even more historical or less spiritual, less abstract than Hegel's. The emphasis was their way of, so to speak, keeping John the Baptist from becoming more important than Jesus.
—
—
—
Rather than divide neatly along political
some
lines, or
even along a
major readings of Hegel underlined particular aspects of his project to show their importance for contemporary concerns. As with most readers of Hegel (and Marx) theological versus secular axis,
of the
during this period, Wahl, the surrealists, and the Marxists saw the early texts as representing the good Hegel,
whereas they viewed with
suspicion or condemnation his mature work, which was less easily applied to the concerns of the 1930s. Koyre was the exception in this regard, not because
because he
he denied the importance of the early works, but
— in good Hegelian fashion — attempted to integrate them
with the philosopher's project as
a
whole. This
is
not to say that
Koyre's reading was less "presentistic" than that of other tators.
27. (iT,;
commen-
Alexandre Kojeve would bring out the contemporary thrust of
Charles Rappaport, "La mcthodc marxistc," Revue marxiste i (1929), no. ^i7-'524; no. s, ss^-S^i; quotation from l^(^. 2, is4-iivre as an
we can
assess
example
of a
how
helpful
it
is
to think of Foucault's
French Nietzscheanism and
how
that
oeuvre refigures the connection between history and knowing. In the
Royaumont Colloquium
of the
summer
of
1964 Foucault
delivered a lecture on Nietzsche, Marx, and Freud. In this talk he
examines what he elsewhere calls a new episteme, a new way of knowing and thinking about the world. This way is the path of interpretation. Of course, interpretation existed well before the nineteenth century, but then it aimed at the discovery of resemblances. In the nineteenth century, and in particular in the work of Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud, there arises again "the possibility of a hermeneutic."" This possibility is based on an awareness of the reflexivity of interpretation and an increased attention to the meanings of the surface of signs (their interconnections) rather
than a probe into their depths
(their references). It is
particularly the reflexivity of interpretation
32.
Foucault, "Lc rctour dc
33.
Foucault, "Nietzsche,
185.
202
la
— the idea that an
morale," Les nouveUt's, 28 June-s July 1984, p. 40. et Freud," in Cahiers de Royaumont (Paris, 1967),
Marx
Styles of Dclcgitimation
interpretation can best be understood by turning interpretive strate-
—
back on the interpretation itself which leads Foucault to the Second major characteristic of nineteenth-century hermencutics: "Interpretation finally became an infinite task."^' For these thinkers,
gies
the task
infinite
is
because no secure origin or goal acts as a standard
meanings.
for judging
Foucault notes that for Nietzsche, there
As
is
no
meanmg. more funMeaning comes
origin of
interpretation tries to get beneath signs to something
damental,
discovers only
it
more
interpretations.
through the imposition of interpretations.^'^ Signs, then, are not prior to interpretations; instead, signs are
interpretations:
always already the product of
"Beginning in the 19th century, beginning from ,
Freud, Marx and Nietzsche, it seems to me that the sign is going to become malevolent; I mean that there is in the sign an ambiguous and even suspect means of willing evil, and of 'malveiller.' That is insofar as the sign is already an interpretation which does not present itself as such. Signs are interpretations which try to justify themselves,
and not the
meaning
a secure
mysterious
Marx
—
also.
inverse."""^ In a
world without beginnings, without
to search out, the goal of interpretation
Interpretation for Nietzsche
—as
always incomplete, and a total hermeneutic
is
"experience de la folie" than lectical thinking
becomes
Freud and
for
is
closer to
to "absolute knowledge. "^^ Dia-
it is
had erred in trying
to attribute positive
meaning and
direction to the play of meaning. ^^ In contrast to this appropriation
something more secure, and in contrast to the and thus a possible systematization of their relationships— Nietzsche, Marx, and Freud leave us with an hermeneutique qui s'enveloppe sur elle-meme, of interpretation for
semiologist's faith in the existence absolue des signes
—
34. Ibid., 187. 35.
Ibid., 190.
36.
Ibid., 191.
37.
de la
188-189. In 1964 Foucault
Ibid.,
folie.
still
held fast to the notion of a pure experience
For a critical appraisal, see Jacques Dcrrida, "Cogito et histoire de
la folie,"
in L'ecriture et la difference (Paris, 1967), coll. "Points," 51-97- Derrida's critique
originally
made
on madness, see Pierre Macherey, "Aux sources de VHistoire de la folie: 471-472 (1986), 753-774. Nietzsche, Marx et Freud, 191. See also Foucault's resistance to adding Flegel
early views
Une 38.
was
in a lecture given in 1963. For a historical treatment of Foucault's
rectification et ses limites," in Critique 42, nos.
to the trilogy in the discussion following the article, p. 194.
203
Afterword
an endless interpretation without foundation and without
goal. For
Foucault, this legacy defines the current period and, of course, his
own
interpretation of
The problem .
tations,
is;
I
it:
of the plurality of interpretations, of the
believe,
made
war
of interpre-
by the very definition
strictly possible
of the
which goes on to infinity, without there being an absolute point beginning from which it is judged and is decided upon. Thus, the interpretation,
following: the fact that
moment where we
we
are destined to be interpreted at the very
must know it. This plethora which profoundly characterizes
interpret; all interpreters
of interpretations is certainly a trait
Western culture now.'""
Seven years
after the lecture at
Royaumont, Foucault returned
to
Nietzsche in an essay that defined his historical practice for the rest of his life. In "Nietzsche, la genealogie, I'histoire," Foucault showed what was at stake in adopting a Nietzschean perspective, if not method, on the past instead of either the traditional historiographical or the "metaphysical" mode of comprehending historical change. Foucault begins his description of genealogy where his previous
discussion of interpretation
left off.
Genealogy
the minutiae of history, not of great deeds.
and
It
is
an examination of
rejects the
"metahis-
deployment and instead concentrates on the play of interpretations, o^ primal disparity and not bedrock essence."*" In fact, Foucault tries to steer genealogy between two dangerous points: Fiegelian philosophy of history and conventional historiography. The Hegelian philosophy of history "metaphysics" in Foucault's essay looks for an essence beneath historical events. Rather than of ideal significance
torical
of indefinite ideologies"
—
—
seek out the meaning that links
all
events in a coherent whole, the
genealogist recognizes irremediable diversity and discontinuity. Ge-
nealogy thus depends on a notion of hermeneutics, because
it
supposes, the primacy of interpretation over the sign. That
is,
genealogist expects that the past will contain only tions,
more
pre-
the
interpreta-
and he or she does not seek out a basic truth or essence to serve w^re the
as a standard of transhistorical judgment: "If interpretation
39.
Ibid.,
195-196.
(Paris, 1971), 146.
204
—
^
40. Foucault, "Nietzsche, genealogie et I'histoire," in
Hommage
a Jean Hyppolite
Styles of Dclcgitimation
bringing slowly to light of meaning buried in the origin, then only
metaphysies eould intepret pretation
is
the
violent"^
the^
becoming
of
humanity. But
if
inter-
or surreptitious appropriation of a system of
no essential meaning) in order to impose a bend it to a new will, to force its participation in a different game, and to subject it to secondary rules, then the devel-, opment of humanity is a series of interpretations."'" Whereas the metaphysical (Hegelian) historian searches for a sens de I'histoire, the Nietzschean genealogist makes use of a sens historique. The division between these two terms is the chasm that for Foucault separates traditional historiography or philosophy and his own work. The search for a sens de I'histoire has been animated by a desire to give meaning and direction to the present by finding its development in the past. In a crucial sense this practice is always one of rules (which in itself has
direction, to
legitimation.
To know
contemporary "progressive."
the direction of history
is
;cl on, 1,2, 39, 40; and Marx, 34 personal authenticity freedom, 46 Sartre vs.
vs. collective
communists
on, sH
struggle for recognition
in,
Weil on, 166; withdrawal
lo^-ios
of individ-
176 Individual and culture (Hyppolitc/ Heual, 167, 172,
gel ), 36
Individual and state, SS-S6, 68-69, 75 Individual and Universal, 39, 43, 4s, si Individualism, in existentialism, 48, S9 Intellectual(s)
Kojeve denounces, 106, 107,
1
30-1 31,
135
Nietzsche on, 192
158, 180, 184, i8s Interpretation(s) (Foucault /Nietzsche),
202-206, 209 Introduction a la lecture de Hegel (Kojeve, ed. Queneau), 84n, 94-124 Isolation, 152-153, 156, 158. See also Alienation; Separation, as necessary lameson, Frederic, 74, 75, 75n, 1830, 186 Jaspers, Karl, 30, 85
lesus of Nazareth, 25
Judaeo-Christian tradition, aid problem of suffering, 25
Judging action criteria for. See Criteria for judging Kojeve and, 113, 120-121 Marxist view of history and, 52, 54, 5 5
Judging consciousness, dialectic of (Hyppolite/Hegel), 40-41
88-93 Esquisse d'une phenomenoloi^ic du droit, 109-110, I 34 Essai d'une histoire raisonne de la philosophie paienne, 1 37- 1 38 and Heidegger, 85, 89-92, 97n, 102103, 108, io8n,
Kant,
1
17
and Hyppolite, contrasted, 102, io2n, 105 irony in, 141, 144, 145, 173, 180, 190 and Koyre, contrasted, 8, 96-97, 119 and Marx, 89, 89n, 93, 97n, 102-103, 117-1 18
and Nietzschcanism, 223 reviews of Queneau and Sagan, 135 his seminar on Phenomenology 124, 134; Merleau-Ponty and, 47, 96; participants (lists), 225-227;
Weil and, 151 on Soloviev, 85-88, 91, 108 Strauss and, 126-134 and Weil, contrasted, 152, 154, 156, 162, 163, i63n, 169, 174, 177-178, 180, i8on, 181, 183
See also under Criteria for judging; Definitive reality; Desire(s); End of history; EndstatC; Equality; Finitude, human; Freedom; God; Historicism; Intellectual(s); Master/ slave dialectic; Posthistorical condition; Recognition, desire and struggle for; Relativism; Risk and desire for recognition; Satisfaction of desire; Self-consciousness; Violence: necessity of Koyre, Alexandre, 2, 5-7 and Hegelianism, 5-6; on early Hegel works, 14-15 and Heidegger, 9 Hyppolite and, 8 Kojeve and, 8, 95, 96-97, 119
and Wahl, 88,
monism, 90-91, 97n
(1933-1939), 48n, 84, 84n, 94-96,
universal vs. specific (Foucault), 211212, 213-214 Interest in history (Weil), 151-154, 157,
Kandinsky, Vasily,
vs.
early writings, 84-89; short reviews,
8,
9
92n
Immanuel
Hyppolite/Hegel and, 73 Kojeve and, 123, 127, 137, i38n on philosophy and science, 3 on violence, i5 5n Weil and, 150, i55n, 176, 180, 181182, 190 Kierkegaard, Soren Aabye, 3
Lacan, Jacques, 96, 112
Language Foucault on limitation(s)
of,
209
Hegel's: Hyppolite and, 46; Kojeve and, 89, 96-97 Heidegger on, 61-62, 64, 77
Hyppolite and, 46, 66-67, 73, 79-8o;
257
1
6
Index Language (conf.) as connection between
logic
and
existence, 72 Weil and, 151, 152, 172 Lenin, Nikolai, 24
Hegel), ss-56 and violence vs. nonviolence (Merleau-Ponty), 51-52
Logic (Hegel) Breton and, 1 Hyppolite on, 69-70, 71, 72-73
Koyre and, Lenin and,
24,
movement
(concept) in, 14
6
i2on
and Phenomenology, 56-57, 58-59, 69-70, 189
58-59
Wahl
and, 3 Logic of history
individual in, as issue in postwar France, 59 Merleau-Ponty on, 52, 53-54, 57, 122 Longing for reconciliation or salvation
Hyppolite/Hegel on, 44
Wahl
on,
2,
4
See also Certainty and
its loss (Weil):
nostalgia for certainty Loss, problem of, 25, 45. See also Certainty and its loss (Weil) Love, 25, 1 1 5-1 1
Lukacs, Georg, i2i-i22n History and Class Consciousness,
Madness (Foucault), 203nn, 208 Man-God, concept of, 86, 87, 115 Marx, Karl Foucault on, 202, 203 in French translations, 13 and Hegel; French perception of, 13, 14, i2on; Hyppolite on, 34-35; Merleau-Ponty on, 54n Kojeve and, 89, 89n, 93, 97n, 102of),
34-35
Marxism and history (Merleau-Ponty), 50-54 Kojeve and, 93, 102-103, 105, 116, I i9-i2on, 1 21-122 Marxism and Marxists, French and alienation, 39 and events of 1968, 21 in
258
10,
12-
prominence
of (postwar),
33-34
Master/slave dialectic basic dynamic of, 100- loi Bloody Battle stage, 102, 103-109 Deleuze/Nietzsche on, 196 dilemma of master, loo-ioi, 108,
109-110 Kojeve's treatment, 85, 99-119, 215 Reign of the Master stage, 102, 109115 Triumph of the Slave stage, 102,
115-119 Weil and, 162 Meaning and direction in history Cassirer on, i54n Deleuze/Nietzsche on, 200 diminished attention to (1950s1970s), 175, 183 Foucault on, 215 Hegelian negation and, 197 importance of problem (postwar France), 46
necessity of forgiveness for belief
in,
43 as suprahistorical (Merleau-Ponty), 56
Weil on, 149, 151-155, 158, 159, 163, 168, 169, 170, 180, 181, 182-183, 185; in society, 167
See also Sens
Meaning
121
Kojeve and, 93 and Merleau-Ponty, 5i-52n Lyotard, fean-Frangois, 189
103, 108, io8n, 1 17 on suffering (necessity
2,
189 Hyppolite and, 29-30, 33-35 Kojeve and, ii9-i2on 14,
Liberalism and liberals and totalitarianism (Hyppolite/
Sartre and,
and existentialism, 189 and Hegelianism (French),
vs.
function, x
Mediation, divine, historical
4, 6.
See also Supra-
dimension
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 9, 29 and Foucault, 54-55 and Hegelianism, 47-48 and Heidegger, 64 Humanisme et terreur, 47, 48-55, 56, 57, 64, 76, 122, 205 and Hyppolite, 48 and Kojeve's Hegel seminar, 47, 96 on logic of history, 52, 53-54, 57 political stance of, 48,
48n
Monism, anthropocentric
(Kojeve), 90 Moral individual vs. hero, 40-4 1; Heidegger and, 6465; Hyppolite and, 73-74,- MerleauPonty on, 49 views history (Weil), 177, 181, 182 Mysticism
Hegel and, 42n; Hyppolite on, 43, 66 Kojeve and, 84, 86 Soloviev and, 86, 88
7
Index Narrativc(s), historical (Weil), is4, 184-
i8s
Natural 97 n Natural
v.s.
historical (Kojcvc/Hcj;cl),
vs. human (Kojcvc/Hcgcl), Strauss on, 126-127
Nature and history (Strauss on Kojeve/Hcgel), 126-127 -Hobbes on, 10^ mastery over: Kojeve on, 116-117, 128; Weil on, 166, 167, 169 ontological bases for (Heidegger, Ko-
90 philosophers and (Strauss), 132 Sartre on {vs. action), 59 Schelling vs. Hegel on, 21 sens de I'histoire as successor to (Foucault), 206 Nazis (National Socialists) and Nazism communists (French) and, 29-30, 5 jeve),
as
enemy
of progress, 122
French and, 5 3 Weil and, i64n Need, triumph over (Weil), 178 Negation, capacity for, 117, 198 Negativity
Deleuze/Nietzsche on, 197, 199, 200, 214 Foucault /Nietzsche and, 220 Hyppolite/ Hegel on: and freedom, 28, 4S; as history, 26, 73
"problem of" (Hegel), 2s Neo-Kantian philosophy, French affected by Hegelianism (1930s), 1-2, 9,
intellectuals, 192; tion(s),
19,
189
dominates French philosophy (1920s), 8-9 Heidegger's impact on, 60 and history (Hyppolite), 26 Sartre and Merleau-Ponty on, 9 Weil and, 149, 150, 154 Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 183, 190-208 as authority in France,
xii,
191, 19 in,
221 Deleuze's interpretation, 186, 192201, 222; critiques of, i93nn; and Foucault's interpretation, con-
219-220; on genealogy, i96n; vs. Hegel, 192194; on pluralism, 195-196 Foucault's interpretation, 193-194, 202-208, 214-215, 218-219; and Deleuze's reading, contrasted [See above under Deleuze's interpretation); on genealogy, 204-207; on trasted, 192, 194, 202,
on interpreta-
202-204
French Hegelianism and, 221-223 and Heidegger, 190; Foucault on, 202 Kojeve and, 29n Nihilism Deleuze/Nietzsche and, 197, 200, 1
201 dialectical thinking
and (Deleuze),
196 history as protection from, 195 Kojeve and, i 35
Merleau-Ponty and, 5 3 Weil and, 176-177, iKi, 185 1968 protests, in France, 211, 21 in Nizan, Paul: Chiens de gardes, Les, 107 Nonviolence. See Violence Nouveaux philosophes, 186
Pan-logicism, 26, 37 Pan-tragedism, 35, 37, 39, 72 Parmenides, 137 Parti
commumste
Communism
frangais (PCF). See
and communists,
French Past finding
meaning and direction in: Deleuze/Hegel on, 200; Foucault/ Nietzsche on, 205-206; Weil on, 1 51-154. See also Meaning and di-
rection in history history as means of perceiving sens in, 22-23, 195 Hyppolite /Hegel and Jaspers on, 30 interest in, reasons for (Weil), 151-
152,
157-158
interpretation of (Foucault/ Nietzsche), 202-204, 206 and reconciliation (Hegel), 30 transcended, in confession and forgiveness, 41 Phenomenology (Hegel) Hyppolite and, 19-20, 26, 35-37, 4045, 69-70, 99 Kojeve and, 84, 90, 94-96, 99; Heidegger and, 108 and Logic, 56-57, 58-59, 69-70, 189
58-59 37n Weil on, 152; and his Logique, i58n Phenomenology, German, 9, 60, 85, 89 Sartre and,
Wahl
and,
3,
Philosopher(s) as "best of men" (Strauss), i28n Kojeve's schema of, 137, i37-i38n
and
politics:
Strauss on,
Kojeve on, 129-13 1; 1
31-132
259
1
Index Kafka on, 125 Kojeve /Soloviev on, 87, 92 and self-consciousness (Kojeve),
Philosopher(s) {cont.) and violence (Weil), 156-157 Philosopher's task Hegel on, 22, 168
Heidegger on, 60-61 Hyppolite on, 80 Kojeve on, 83, 93, 129-131 neo-Kantians on, 26-27 Strauss on, 131- 132 Weil on, 149, 159, 168, 175 Plato, 137, i38n Pluralism (Deleuze/Nietzsche), 195196 Political action
detachment from, 107, 130-131, 167, 172, 176-177 Foucault on: and change, 216; shared tradition and participation in, 212 Heidegger abstains from, 60 philosophers and: Kojeve on, 129131; Strauss on, 1 31-132 philosophy of history as legitimation of, 24-25, 48, 64 revolutionary. See Revolutionary political action violent. See Violence Weil's philosophy of, 165-176 See also Power, political
Pompanazzi, Pietro, 149 Poster, Mark, 13, 59, 94
Postmodernism, 144-145, 183 x, xii, 79, 186 Power, political Foucault on: its effect on individual
Poststructuralism,
Habermas on, 219; and impossibility of community, subjects, 216;
212; and knowledge, 209-210, 211, 213; legitimation of, 205, 209-21O; and truth, 210, 2 ion, 214 philosophy of history as legitimation
24-25
of state vs. individuals', 75
and values, separated (Hyppolite/ Alain), 67
Power, will
to,
198-199, 210
Prison (Foucault), 210 Progress
Deleuze/Nietzsche on, 196-197, 199, 201, 222, 223 as failure (existentialists),
32-33
fascism and Nazism as enemies
of,
122-123 Hyppolite on, 23-24, 39, 44, 55, 77 Hyppolite /Heidegger and, 71, 77
260
Wahl/ Hegel
on, 4-5, 6
Weil and, 169-170; faith in, 182; Kojeve, 174; vs. sens, 150 Progress and history as distinct concepts, 7n
vs.
existentialists and, 32, 33
Heidegger and, 63 Hyppolite /Hegel on, 31-32, 79 Kojeve /Hegel and, 8, 111-112 Nietzsche on, 23 Proletariat, theory of, 51-52, 75 Propaganda, political (Kojeve), 118 Psychoanalytic theory, lo-ii, 33, 77, 1
Purge 7
12 trials 5,
(Moscow,
1930s), 49, 51,
205
Queneau, Raymond, 94-95,
96, 135,
223
Raison impersonelle, 49 Ranke, Leopold von, 206 Rappoport, Charles, 13-14 Reality, definitive (Kojeve), 120-121,
Posthistorical condition (Kojeve), 135, 138-1 39, i63n, 223
of,
143 Strauss on, 131 and values (Hyppolite/Alain), 68
122
Reason "cunning of" (Hegel), 120; Kojeve and, 135; Weil and, 164 development of, as history (Hegeli41-42, 44, 45, 195; and, 52 and progress (Hyppolite /Hegel), 55 and reconciliation (Hegel), 168; Koyre and, 6 ans), 10, 39, 40,
Marxism
Weil on: and competing histories, 152; openness to, 153, 180; satisfaction of, 160-161; and violence, 150, i54n, 155-158 Recherches philosophiques (periodical), 9, 85, 89, 91-92, 1 50-1 5 Recognition, desire and struggle for Deleuze/Nietzsche and, 198 Hyppolite /Hegel on, 38, 39, 58 Kojeve/Hegel on, 97, 99, 107, 113, 134; and class conflict, 103; in master/slave dialectic, 100, loi, 102, 103-105; mutual, 112; philosophers and, 130; in politics, 223; life for, 99; Strauss and, 126, 128; sublimation of, 112, 113,
risking
Index 1 1 6- 1 17; universal, Weil and, 162
117, 126, 128;
Reeonciliation as goal of history (Wahl/ Hegel),
4,
6
Kojeve on, 98; End of history and, 112, 117, 118, 139; and freedom, 112, 113, 8; in master/slave dialectic, 100, IOI-IO2, 109, IIO; Weil and, 77-1 78 1
I
Hegel on: past and, "jO; thmking and, 62n Hyppolite/Hegel on, 26, 27, ^y, 41, 5 5 -
on humanism, 58-59 Satisfaction of desire
Jesus as emblem of, 25 and struggle for recognition (Kojeve),
1
Strauss and, 126, 128, i^i, 178 Satisfaction of Reason (Weil), 160-161,
177 Schelling, Friedrich
Wilhelm Joseph
von, 21, 22, 86, 87
Weil on: and "Absolute," 160; discussion and, 171; and meaning and direction, 168; quest for sens and, I S3; revolt against, 163
Redemption existentialists reject, 31 Hyppolite/Hegel on, 25-26, 28, 29, 39, 40-41, 42, 73 Jesus and, 25 Weil and, 174 Reflection and reflective individual,
91-92, 129-130 Reflexivity of interpretation (Foucault/ Nietzsche), 202-203 of the Master stage of master/ slave dialectic, 102, 109-115
Reign
Relativism Kojeve and, 88; historicism and, 123, i23n, 124, 125, i2sn, 127; Strauss and, 127, 133 Merleau-Ponty and, 49-50, 51, 57
Repression (Foucault), 2i7n Revolutionary political action
communists (French) and, 57 Merleau-Ponty supports, 47, 50-51, 54 as solution to problem of alienation 53,
(Marxists), 39
Revue marxiste
(periodical), 13
Rickert, Heinrich, 88
Risk,
and desire
for recognition (Ko-
jeve), 99, 107,
no, 113
valorization of, 106, 107 Rorty, Richard, 32n, 78, 2o6n
Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 31
Royaumont Colloquium
(1964),
202 Russian revolution (French Marxists and), 12-13 Sagan, Fran^oise, 135 Sartre, Jean Paul, i, 9, 29, 46, 191 and Heidegger, 60, 63, 74
Johann Christoph Friedrich von: "Die Weltgeschichte ist das Weltgericht," 5 5n, 106, 127 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 133 Science Schiller,
anthropocentric jeve), 90,
monism and
(Ko-
9on 149-
crisis of loss of faith in (Weil),
150 philosophy should follow (Kant), 3
progress in, as concern of philosophers, 9 Self-consciousness Hegel on, 91
Hyppolite on, 73, 129 Kojeve on, 129, 142-144, 145-146; and human desire, 98; in master/ slave dialectic, 102, 105, ii2; Strauss vs., 132 Weil on: history as ascent to, 162; in moral philosophy, 176
Semiotics and semiology Foucault, 203, 204, 2o6n, 211 and Hyppolite and hope, 77-78
22n and change over time, 44
Sens, 22,
de I'histoire
vs. historique (Foucault/ Nietzsche), 205-206, 210-21 1, 222 in Divine, 43, 43n
Kojeve on, 93, 120, 163, 169 in past experience: historicity (Jaspers), 30; history as
and
means
of
perceiving, 22-23, I95; as issue in
postwar France, 47 Weil on quest for, 149, 158, 159, 175, 182; as category of philosophy, 161 destruction of, vs. progress, ;
150; as duty, 183, 185; and exploration of past, 1 51-154; and loss of certainty, 159, 160, 165; opens up history, 168-169, 173; and society's
values, 174; and (the) state, 170, 173-174; and violence, 156, 157,
261
1
Index Sens
critique of historicism, i23n
{cont.)
163, 172-173. See also
and direction
Meaning
in history
Separation, as necessary, 4, 6, 24, 25. See also Alienation; Isolation Sexuality, history of (Foucault), 216-
218
and interpretation (Foucault),
Sign(s),
203, 204 Significance (as major concern), shift to
function/use, as concern, x
Hegelianism and, 190 Hyppolite and, 29, 67, 175 Kojeve and, 85, 140, 142, 175 Weil and, 183
Structuralism ascent of (19505), 175 Foucault and, 208 and Hegelianism, x, xii, 79 and Weil, 186 Struggle contradiction leads to (Hyppolite/He-
Silence, 129, 133 Slave ideology (Kojeve), 113, 11 3n,
gel),
114-
116 Slave /master dialectic. See Master/ slave dialectic Society, 166-168. See also Community;
in master/slave dialectic (Kojeve),
100, loi, 102
philosophy
primacy
of,
of,
107
in political history
for recognition. See Recognition, de-
108
sire
Speaking 213
37
Deleuze/Nietzsche and, 201
(1930s), 24
State(s)
Soloviev, Vladimir, 8s-88, 91, for others (Foucault), 212,
and struggle
for
Subjectivity
and freedom (Sartre), 58-59, 63 Heidegger on, 63, 66; vs. Hegel's con-
Spirit (Hyppolite/Hegel)
and consciousness, 23-24 and moral/historical reconciliation,
cept, 63
Hyppolite/Hegel on,
37, 38, 56
Suffering, necessity of
41
Hyppolite/Hegel and,
and negativity as history, 26 and Reason, 41-42
Kojeve and, 102
Standards for judging. See Criteria for judging State(s)
criticism of (Hegel), 20s Hyppolitc/Hegel on: conflict with, S6; individual and, SS-S6, 68-69, 75; in political redemption, 27,
SSU; recognition derived from, 39; reconciliation with, SS Kojeve/Hegel on: Greek \'.s. socialist, ii6n; replaces Church, 116 resistance to (France, 1968), 21
Weil on, 173-174; his definition, 170; educative function, 170;
tions
rela-
among, is6n
Strauss, Leo, 9s, is8n
Hiero,
129
commentary on Xenophon, On Tyranny [Ko]- (discussion, 171 -172, 17 3; and Reason, ISO, i54n, 155-156, 164; renounces in favor of discourse, 8, 156-158, 157, 163, 172-173; tainty, 172
Totalitarianism Hyppolite/ Hegel and, 56
Trimuph
to,
Vcync, Paul, 213, 2i3n Violence Kant on, ssn
7n, y, 97, 119
Merlcau-Ponty and, Weil and, 169
for, vs.
history as asctnt
i
6211
Time, Hegelian Heidegger and,
1(19
and Hegel, contrasted, 168 Hegel et I'etat, i56n and Hyppolite, contrasted,
a I'his-
102, io2n,
105 and Kojeve, contrasted, 152, 154, 156, 162, 163, i63n, 169, 174, 177-178, 180, i8on, 181, 183 at Kojeve's seminar on Hegel, 151 Koyre's course on Hegel, 95 Logique de la philosophie, 150, i54n, 155-161; and Hegel's Phenomenoat
logy, i58n and Marx, contrasted, 161 his moral philosophy, 165, 176-
186 neo-Kantian perspective of, 150, i55n, 176, 180, 181-182, 190
263
Index Weil, Eric (conf.) Philosophic morale, 150, 165,
176-183 Philosophic politique, 150, 165, 166176 his political philosophy, 165-176; and moral philosophy, 179-180
and Strauss, contrasted, 168-
Wisdom,
desire for (Strauss /Kojeve),
128
Work gel),
37
of
dom, 94n;
free-
of slave, 100, loi, 102,
109, III, 113
History, concept and goal of; Interest in history; Isolation; Meaning and direction of history; Progress;
9on Weil on:
264
(Hegel),
Kojeve on: and death, io2; and
Marx
Reason; Reconciliation; Satisfac-
man"
II in
history; Happiness, reasonable;
Violence
78n, 140, 207n,
Will to power, 198-199, 210 Windelband, Wilhelm, 23
as "essence of
"Valeur et dignite du recit historiographique," 183-186 See also under Certainty and its loss,-
tion of Reason; Sens-, State;
xi,
2i7n
contradiction leads to (Hyppolite/He-
169 his theory of history, 158-164
Community; Discussion; End
White, Hayden,
on, Kojeve's interpretation,
89-
as rejection of coherence, i64n; society values, 167 World War I, 24, 32
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Roth, Michael
S.,
1957-
Knowing and
history.
Bibhography:
p.
Includes index. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770History— Philosophy. Hyppolite, Kojeve, 1902—Influence. Alexandre, Jean. Weil, Philosophy, French — 20th century. Title. 1968. 2.
I.
183
1
4.
3.
5.
D16.9.R68
Eric. 6.
1988
ISBN 0-8014-2136-5
I.
87-47870
901 (alk.
paper)