Inalienability of Sovereignty in Medieval Political Thought 9780231884310

Discusses the practical and theoretical influence of the idea of inalienability of sovereignty upon the growth of the na

180 119 16MB

English Pages 206 [216] Year 2019

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
Preface
Contents
I. The Theory of Inalienability: Its Chronological, Geographical, and Theoretical Limits
II. The Concept of Office and Its Responsibilities
III. The Ecclesiastical Theory of Inalienability
IV. The Lay Theory of Inalienability: The Crown
V. The Decretal Intellecto and the Coronation Oath
VI. The Theory of Intellecto and Contractual Agreements
VII. The Continuity of Office and State
VIII. Revocation and Restraint on the Basis of Inalienability
IX. Conclusion
Bibliography
Index
Recommend Papers

Inalienability of Sovereignty in Medieval Political Thought
 9780231884310

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

Inalienability of Sovereignty in Medieval Political Thought

NUMBER

591

C O L U M B I A STUDIES IN T H E SOCIAL SCIENCES EDITED BY T H E F A C U L T Y OF POLITICAL SCIENCE OF C O L U M B I A

UNIVERSITY

PETER

N.

RIESENBERG

Inalienability of Sovereignty in Medieval Political Thought

COLUMBIA U N I V E R S I T Y PRESS NEW

YORK

1 9 56

COPYRIGHT

19 J 5

BY

FIRST PUBLISHED

PETER

IN

BOOK

PUBLISHED GREAT B R I T A I N , INDIA, BY

AND

IN CANADA,

CUMBERLEGE:

OXFORD UNIVERSITY BOMBAY,

LIBRARY

RIESENBERG

PAKISTAN

GEOFFREY LONDON,

N.

FORM

PRESS

TORONTO,

AND

OF

KARACHI

CONGRESS

CATALOG CARD

NUMBER

J6-542J MANUFACTURED UNITED

STATES

OF

IN

THE

AMERICA

1956

TO MY PARENTS

Preface

THE EMPHASIS in this study is upon the legal and political aspects of the theory of inalienability, not upon the theological. Hence, with but a few exceptions, no attempt has been made to examine the vast body of medieval theological literature. And, although German private law presents analogies to the concepts developed under Roman law, since we are here concerned with the effect of the theory of inalienability upon the growth of the national monarchies, and since German politics moved rather towards decentralization during the late Middle Ages, the theory of inalienability in German law is not discussed in the present work. Since 1953, when the research for this book was completed, several works have appeared which touch very closely upon the subject of inalienability. Notable among these are Professor Ernst Kantorowicz's article in Speculum to which reference is made in my text, and the work of Professor Marcel David, La souveraineté et les limites juridiques du pouvoir monarchique e e du IX au X V siècle (Paris, 1954). As its title indicates, M. David's book is necessarily concerned with many of the issues treated here. Rather than punctuate my notes with repeated reference to his work, and considering both our substantial agreement and difference in emphasis, I have decided merely to refer to his volume here in this fashion.

Preface

viii

Many persons and institutions have been very kind to me during the preparation of this study. Columbia University's grant of a Cutting Traveling Fellowship and the Fulbright Program o f the State Department made possible several years* work and travel in Europe. The officials o f the Vatican Library, the Bibliothèque Nationale, and the various state libraries in Rome and Florence were at all times most co-operative. In the United States, besides the New York Public Library and the libraries of Columbia University and Union Theological Seminary, I have been fortunate in using the collections at Harvard and Princeton. Long ago Professor Benjamin N . Nelson introduced me to the questions of alienation and renunciation in the civilians. And more recently Professors Austin P. Evans, Gaines Post, Theodore Silverstein, David Smith, and Anne Trinsey, and Mr. Benjamin Linder, read the manuscript at various stages in its preparation and were good enough to put me right on many issues. Throughout my work on the subject Professor Lynn Thorndike has been especially rigorous and thereby helpful. Miss Vergene Leverenz of the Columbia University Press has aided me with both encouraging words and good advice; and my student, Frances King, has devoted much time to the preparation of the index. T o all these, and to my wife, whose labors as typist and copyist have been great, my deepest thanks. PETER

Suartbwore College March, 195 5

N.

RIESENBERG

Contents

Preface I. T h e T h e o r y of

vii Inalienability:

Its

Chronological,

G e o g r a p h i c a l , and T h e o r e t i c a l L i m i t s

3

II. T h e C o n c e p t of Office a n d Its Responsibilities

22

I I I . T h e Ecclesiastical T h e o r y of I n a l i e n a b i l i t y

48

I V . T h e Lay T h e o r y of I n a l i e n a b i l i t y : T h e C r o w n

81

V . T h e Decretal Infellecto

and the Coronation O a t h

V I . T h e T h e o r y of Intellecto

and C o n t r a c t u a l

Agree-

ments

129

V I I . T h e C o n t i n u i t y of Office a n d State V I I I . R e v o c a t i o n a n d R e s t r a i n t on the Basis of

113

145 Inalien-

ability

161

IX. Conclusion

176

Bibliography

179

Index

195

Inalienability of Sovereignty in Medieval Political Thought

I

The Theory of Inalienability: Its Chronological, Geographical, and Theoretical Limits

and theoretical influence of the idea of inalienability of sovereignty upon the growth of the national monarchies during the late Middle Ages is the major focus of this study. During the thirteenth century Roman and canon lawyers developed the idea that there were certain rights and functions which a kingdom had to exercise if it was to exist and flourish. Simultaneously they stressed the concept of the king not as dominus in the absolute legal sense of the word, but rather as guardian, curator, of the office and responsibilities entrusted to him. Since the king was but a temporary official in a position of trust, he might not alienate the essential functions of his office to the prejudice of the state. Gradually other theories, each the result of its own peculiar history, entered into sympathetic relationships with the concept of inalienability. Most important among these were the concept of the Crown, canonist views upon obligation to the public welfare, and civilian private law concepts of an individual's inalienable rights, all of which were applied by publicists to their immediate purpose: the establishment of a sound theoretical basis for the independence and further growth of the national states. The theory of inalienability of sovereignty, however, was not restricted in its use to the nationalist writers. Developed as it was upon the

T H E PRACTICAL

4

The Theory of Inalienability

two great laws of Christendom, it was also claimed by the proponents of the Empire as their own. They, in fact, regarded the use of the theory of inalienability by the monarchist writers as an improper arrogation of their own ideas. In 1275, reports the English lawbook Fleta, all the kings of Christendom met in council at Montpellier, declared prescription to be invalid against royal power, and in another statement of ecumenical scope, ruled that previous alienations made by rulers in prejudice of the rights and lands of their Crowns were initially invalid and must be recalled.1 One historian describes this passing mention of a world conference as a legend,2 and this indeed it is—in its reporting of a meeting which never took place; and also, more loosely but perhaps more importantly, in the sense that Fleta gave dramatic reality and authority to an idea which had been developing for at least a century: the theory that the kingdom was dependent for its identity upon the preservation of certain inalienable rights and privileges which generally were treated as a theoretical sum and were not 1 This passage is not unfamiliar to historians of English law and constitutional history, nor to those of medieval political theory. It was first noted in modern scholarship, I believe, by John Selden, Ad Fletam dissertatio (ed. and trans. Darid Ogg, Cambridge, 1925), p. 189. He gives other references to such alienations in the Middle Ages, citing the Sielr partidas, and the decretal Intellecto ( X . 2, 24, 33) of Honorius III, the comments upon which form a major part of medieval thought on this topic. He does not find mention of the conference in the writings of the medieval and Renaissance jurists, a finding which I would confirm. What the author of Fleta may have had in mind was the Second Council of Lyons, 1274, to which wera invited all the rulers of Christendom, including Michael Paleologus. Cap. X X I I of the decrees of the council is entitled " De rebus ecclesiae non alienandis," and is a general prohibition against alienation of church property. For the text, see I. D. Mansi, Sacrorum conciliorum nova et amplissima collectio (31 vols., Florence, 1759 9 8 ) , XXIV, 9Î-96. It was later included by Boniface VIII in the Liber sextus ( J , 9, 2 ) , and, according to Hefele-Leclercq, Histoire des conciles (Paris, 1914), VI, i, 199, was directed against the institution of avouerie which placed protection of ecclesiastical property in lay hands, an action which gradually led to complete separation. At the outset it might be well to stace that the spelling and punctuation of foreign language texts will be given as printed in the early editions. 2 Adhémar Esmein, Cours élémentaire d'histoire du droit français (9th éd., Paris, 1 9 0 8 ) , p. 328.

The Theory

of

Inalienability

5

differentiated. The ruler was entrusted with the power of office for the span of his life, and had to pass it on undiminished, if not strengthened, to his successor. Medieval as well as classical Roman law considered the ruler's sum of authority as an abstraction, the imperium, and in this was seconded by contemporary philosophical theory which held that the imperium had to retain its essential characteristics, if indeed it was to justify its name and definition. Hence it was the common belief that the ruler should not and could not diminish the effective scope of his office and pass on less than the sum of authority requisite for proper executive action. The successor had to enjoy the complete imperium if he was fully to rule. Until the time of Fleta, probably the early 1290s,3 the idea had appeared in documents of limited scope, for the most part in commentaries and glosses upon passages in the books of the canon and Roman law. Although, as will be made clear, it was part of a body of interrelated concepts of public law formulated by the theorists of the two laws, this was the first time that it received anything like dramatic application to all Europe. That such a statement should have been made is itself surprising for th» conscious ?pplicition of s'.»ch an ; dei implios corsciousness of individuality which we hesitate to ascribe to the monarchies of the thirteenth century. Moreover, this entire pattern, a seamless cloak of interwoven political concepts, is all the more difficult to grasp because it was formulated as public law at a time when the lines of demarcation between the spheres of private and public law, as they are known today, were extremely shadowy and hard to define. The exact nature of the governmental rights and functions to be protected is likewise vague. The civilians and canonists to whom we owe the elaboration of a theory of sovereignty were 3 N . D e n h o l m - Y o u n g , " W h o W r o t e TUtal " English Historical Review, ( 1 9 4 J ) , 1-12. ( T h e English Historical Review will h e r e a f t e r be cited is t h e American Historical Rci iew as A.H.R.)

LVIII E.H.R.,

6

The Theory

of

Inalienability

not always precise on this point. Concerned with high-level abstractions, they did not treat the specific royal or imperial privilege, but rather such generalized phrases as " iura coronae " or " honor coronae." To some extent their imprecision may be explained by the fact that still, in the late thirteenth and throughout the fourteenth century, the legists were in large measure dealing with the rights of a feudal society. Their legal education was in part based upon the Liber feudorum, which formed a course of study in the university curriculum; but beyond this, they were bound by a terminology charged with traditional meanings. So, although as servants of the national monarchs or the emperor they were concerned to build a new or protect an old system, they had yet to use words which linked them with the society they were trying to refashion. This vagueness, however, cannot all be ascribed to education and tradition; as we shall see, it was to the advantage of the theorist to keep his terms broad to allow for internal expansion. Basic to our discussion, therefore, must be an attempt to determine just which rights—that is, in essence, functions—were in question. When the legists used such phrases as iura coronae and iura maiestath they did so in more than one sense, and basic to any use was their ultimate reliance upon their conception of the term iura regalia. To attempt to define with accuracy the degrees of essentiality of a prince's regalia is a profitless task. Frederick I and his advisers drew up a list at Roncaglia in 115 8 which codified for a moment the developments of the preceding centuries. At that moment the jeudisti and the schools took up the question, and by the end of the Middle Ages commentators agreed on but one point: in placing their estimates of regalian rights in the hundreds. 4 Modern authorities have sought to 4 Georges Blonde], " E t u d e sur les droits regaliens et la c o n s t i t u t i o n de Roncaglia," Melanges Paul Fabre (Paris, 1 9 0 2 ) , p. 2 3 7 ; A n t o n i u s de P e t r i compiled a list of 408 regalia! See also the gloss of Charondos Lc C a r o n t o La somme mralc (Paris, 1 6 1 1 ) ,

The Theory

of

Inalienability

7

avoid the problem, tried to fall back upon the selection of Barbarossa, or have attempted to synthesize from the medieval confusion some few essential rights which would add up to sovereignty. 5 Despite this confusion, a hierarchy is perceivable. Lucas de Penna (ca. 1325—90) listed several very special functions for the emperor: the power to make universal law, to interpret a law equitably, to wage war, to create new taxes, and to sell property in which he had at least a half interest. 6 Most imp. 65 8. T h e proceedings at Roncaglia are themselves f o u n d in the Monumenta Germaniae histórica. Le gurrt. Sectio IV. Constitutiones et acta publica Imperatomin et Regum ( H a n o v e r , 1893 et seq.), I, 247-48 ( h e r e a f t e r cited by t h e term Constitutione*). A n d r e a de Isernia, Constitutiones regni utriusque Siciliae, gìossis ordinariis, cominentariisque (Lyons, 1 5 6 0 ) , lib. III. tit. 1, speaks of the t e r m regalia as " nomen generale, fiscalía et patrimonialia comprehendens, quae omnia regis d i c u n t u r . " 5 For various views on t h e regalia see Blondel, " E t u d e " ; F. O l i v i e r - M a r t i n , Histoire Ju droit français Jes origines à la revolution ( M o n t c h r e s t i e n , 1 9 5 1 ) , p. 3 0 3 ; W i l l i a m N e w m a n , Le domaine royal sous les premiers Capétiens (Paris, 1 9 3 7 ) ; P. Viollet, Histoire des institutions politiques et administratives de la France (3 vols., Paris, 1 8 9 0 - 1 9 0 3 ) , II, 1 8 5 - 8 6 ; W a l t e r U l l m a n , " T h e Development of t h e Medieval Idea of Sovereignty," E.H.R., L X I V ( 1 9 4 9 ) , 1 - 3 4 ; Samuel Chevallier, Le pouvoir royal français à la fin du XIII' siècle: Les droits régaliens (Laval, 1 9 3 0 ) ; H . Koeppler, " F r e d e r i c k Barbarossa and t h e Schools of Bologna," E.H.R., LIV ( 1 9 3 9 ) , 577-607. 6 Lectura (Lyons, 1 5 8 6 ) , t o C. 12, 35, 14. But even t h e strongest supporters of t h e monarchies did not allow, theoretically, all the i m p o r t a n t privileges t o t h e kings. Paul F o u r n i e r writes t h a t in t h e early years of t h e f o u r t e e n t h c e n t u r y even such a m o n a r c h i s t as Petrus J a c o b u s denied t h e king the privileges t o levy taxes, coin monies, a n d t o revoke concessions of immunities made by the emperor t o t h e clergy in t h e past: " La ' Monarchia ' de D a n t e et l'opinion française," Bulletin du jubilé du comité franc, cath. pour la célébration du VI' centenaire de la mort de D.A., fase. III (Paris, 1 9 2 1 ) , 168-69. I t should also be noted t h a t when Lucas speaks here on '* universal law " he means it in an already atrophied sense. T h e emperor was t o m a k e universal law f o r t h e E m p i r e — w h a t was left of i t — a n d t h e kings f o r all subjects in their realm. See, f o r example, the Tractatus super jeudis et bomagiis, cap. X I I , of Johannes Blanosc. This is cited by Francesco Calasso, I glossatori e la teoria della sovranità (2d ed., Milan, 1 9 5 1 ) , pp. 118 et seq. Calasso uses this passage t o point u p the naturalis jurisdictio pertaining t o t h e king. This passage deals w i t h t h e relationship of t h e inhabitants of the k i n g d o m to t h e king: " Set q u a m v i s in potentate regis ita quod iure homagii regi non sint astricti, sunt tamen in potestate regis iure naturalis iurisdictionis q u a m rex habet in regno, n a m v e r b u m potestatis pluribus modis aeeipitur . . . nam in hominibus Omnibus regni sui habet I m p e r i u m . . . . N a m sicut omnia sunt imperatoris q u a n t u m ad iurisdictionem, c u m sit m u n d i d o m i n u s , sic omnia, que sunt in regno sunt regis q u a n t u m ad iurisdictionem . . . . "

8

The Theory of Inalienability

portant of these, of course, was the power to make law. Another great privilege ascribed by the medieval lawyers to the highest public authorities was that over life and death . . . the original sense of the merum imperium. Obviously, there were certain of the regalia which counted above the others. One historian of the meeting at Roncaglia finds the emperor stressing these rights: the power to appoint local territorial rulers, control of the ways of communication, the exclusive right to coin, control of the mines and the revenues of judicial processes, regulation of loans upon taxes, and the right to command or rebuild a fortress wherever one had existed before. 7 Another historian, writing of sovereignty at the beginning of the fourteenth century, after some century and a half of legal speculation, sees the legal aspects of sovereignty in the imperial or royal ability to enforce the penalty for crimen leasae majestatis, issue universally binding laws, create notaries, legitimatize bastards, and, in the case of the emperor, to sit as a court of appeal in judgment on the sentences of kings. 8 These were the most vital governmental privileges; yet, in particular discussions of inalienability of sovereignty they are rarely specifically mentioned. W h a t the theorists were summoned to protect were iura, majestas, or dignitas without qualification. Texts in the discussion show that the legal loss of the most important of these functions was invariably denied, or permitted only after the lapse of infinite time or under the most pressing circumstances. In other words, the highest imperial and royal functions were those denied alienation.® But there is U n f o r t u n a t e l y , Calasso does not go into the reasons for the iurisJictio of the king being called naturalis. I venture that the explanation will be seen in the concepts of kingship developed in this paper. 7 Blondel, " E t u d e , " pp. 246-47. ® Ullman, "Medieval Idea of Sovereignty," p. 3. 0 See the constitution of Frederick II (1231) reaffirming the law of Rogerius; in Huillard-Bréholles, Hhtoria diplomatic-a Frederici secundi sire comtitutionei, privilégia mandata . . . et documenta t jria (7 vols, in 12, Paris, 1 852—59), IV, 119: " Scire volumus principes nostros, comités, barones, archiepiscopos, universos episcopos,

The Theory

of

Inalienability

9

something more in the very fact that the terminology is invariably both abstract and vague. The legists knew what they were doing when they wrote a blank check, so to speak, for the proponents of centralized government. Not one or even several specific rights were to be protected—though of course these would benefit as the general view was applied to each specific case; rather, the theory was always to stretch to cover newly won powers. So, when viewed by the opponents of centralization, the mantle of protection had a serious defect: once stretched, it never regained its original, theoretical shape. The protection now always remained, to be used by the proper man at the proper moment. Such employment of the theory might be made by a strong king such as Edward I, or by the supporters of a weak one, say, Charles VI. The political results varied, but one effect was common to both: a reassertion of the fundamental theory of inalienability in contemporary terms. No claim is made, however, that the theory of inalienability is the dominant or uniquely causative factor of any national movement or constitution. It was important primarily in the way it gave strength to and was integrated with other ideas;