Habermas and the Dialectic of Reason 9780300156898

In his magnum opus, Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, the distinguished philosopher Jurgen Habermas presented his ide

255 78 11MB

German Pages [284] Year 2022

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Recommend Papers

Habermas and the Dialectic of Reason
 9780300156898

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

Habermas and the Dialectic of Reason

HABERMAS and the DIALECTIC OF REASON

DAVID INGRAM

Yale University Press New Haven and London

Copyright© 1987 by Yale University. All rights reserved. This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that copying permitted by Sections 107 and 108 of the U.S. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press), without written permission from the publishers. Designed by Nancy Ovedovitz and set in Palatino type by Eastern Graphics. Printed in the United States of America by BookCrafters, Inc., Chelsea, Michigan. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Ingram, David, 1952Habermas and the dialectic of reason. Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Habermas, Jiirgen. 2. Habermas, Jiirgen. Theorie deskommunikativen Handelns. 3. Sociology-Philosophy. 4. Rationalism. 5. Social action. 6. Communication-Philosophy. 7. Functionalism. I. Title. 1987 301' .01 86-22394 B3258.H234I54 ISBN 0-300-03680-9 (alk. paper) The paper in this book meets the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources. 10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1

For Julia

Oer Ethiker muB immer von neuem zur Welt kommen. Der Kunstler ein fur allemal -Karl Kraus, Vom Kiinstler, in Werke, ed. Heinrich Fischer (Munich: Kosel Verlag, 1952), vol. 3, p. 239. Engel (sagt man) wuBten oft nicht, ob sie unter Lebenden gehn oder Toten. Die ewige Stromung reiBt durch beide Bereiche aile Alter immer mit sich und ubertont sie in beiden -Rainer Maria Rilke, Duino Elegies, ed. J. B. Leishman and Stephen Spender (New York: Norton, 1939), p. 24.

CONTENTS

Preface 1. The Historical Foundations of the Theory of Communicative Action

2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11.

Rationality, Reality, and Action Understanding and Language Weber's Theory of Rationalization From Lukacs to Adorno: Rationalization as Reification Discourse on Modernity: A Philosophical Interlude From Purposive to Communicative Action in the Social Theories of Mead and Durkheim System and Lifeworld Talcott Parsons: Systems Theory From Parsons to Weber and Marx The Theory-Practice Problem Revisited Abbreviations Notes Bibliography Index

xi

1 19 32 43 60 75 104 115 135 148 172 189 191 243 255

PREFACE

ince 1978, the year in which Thomas McCarthy's pioneering study The Critical Theory of furgen Habermas was published, no major synaptical treatment of Habermas' s work has appeared. To appreciate the significance of McCarthy's endeavor, one need only recall the relative ignorance of German philosophy among Anglo-American thinkers at the time-one compounded in Habermas's case by his dense style and seeming obliviousness to the needs of potential readers, most of whom were unfamiliar with the broad range of problems, disciplines, and figures presupposed in his work. McCarthy's main achievement was to provide English-speaking readers with an accessible, sympathetic, yet critical introduction to Habermas's thought. There would be no need to attempt another explication of Habermas' s thought in English were it not for the changes that it has undergone during the past eight years. Of course, much of what is contained in McCarthy's commentary is still valid, and much of Habermas's work prior to 1978 sheds light on his most recent research. It is also clear, however, that the scope of issues and arguments has been expanded-mostly in response to the growing mass of secondary literature-to include new topics in aesthetics and poststructuralism, as well as problems in first-generation critical theory that had hitherto been neglected. Most important perhaps, the conception of critical theory that began to emerge in Habermas's writings in the late seventies marked a departure from the earlier program of ideology critique. That this new development has not yet been fully appreciated in the English-speaking world is to be attributed presumably to the fact that none of his most recent works- Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns (1981), Moralbewusstsein und kommunikatives Handeln (1983), Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne (1985), and Die neue Unubersichtlichkeit: Kleine politische Schriften V (1985)-has yet been translated in its entirety.

S

xi

Preface The aim of this study is twofold: to provide a brief commentary on Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns (hereafter abbreviated Theorie) and to evaluate it in the light of Habermas' s more recent writings on modernity, politics, and aesthetics. There are several reasons for the first undertaking. Not only does Theorie advance the first major defense of Habermas' s program in its entirety, it also constitutes a major reassessment of its function. Critique of ideology is supplanted by a holistic criticism of social reification, a shift that is related to a global reappraisal of first-generation critical theory and deficiencies in the philosophy of consciousness. What emerges is the clearest statement yet of Habermas's philosophy of communication and the bilevel lifeworld-system model of society implicated in it. Theorie also represents an attempt on Habermas's part to settle his differences with the classical sociological tradition. Indeed, one can legitimately read it as a grand synopsis of the entire sociological tradition extending from Marx to contemporary ethnomethodology and cybernetics. No major school of thought is ignored, and commentaries on such towering figures as Weber and Parsons comprise virtually self-contained, booklength studies in their own right. These magnificent forays into the history of social theory (Theoriegeschichte) are interspersed with digressions (Zwischenbetrachtungen) in which Habermas develops his own theory in response to the possibilities and limitations of the tradition as a whole. I cannot hope to capture in a brief study the richness of a book whose scope spans more than eleven hundred pages, but I would like to think that I have succeeded in outlining its major contours and summarizing the not inconsiderable secondary literature. As for the second undertaking, I believe that Habermas's conception of rationality is far more complex than most of his critics have realized. Habermas has conceded for some time now that reason can no longer be grounded transcendentally, as if it were necessary for the possibility of human experience and communication. But it is only very recently that he has acknowledged that reason, such as it exists for modern man, is aesthetic as well as communicative. Theorie presupposes a holistic conception of rationality that cannot be adequately articulated by a formal notion of procedural justice, one that implies an intuitive integration and dialectical harmonizing of substantive values. If I am not mistaken, Habermas' s conception of aesthetic rationality constitutes a significant effort to reinvest his theory with hermeneutic content, thereby bridging the gap between discursive reflection and lived experience that has bothered so many of his critics. With regard to hermeneutic methodology, the dialectical mode of presentation is a trademark of some of Habermas' s earlier monumenxii

Preface tal studies, most notably Zur Logik der Sozialwissenschaften (1967) and Erkenntnis und Interesse (1968). Like many German philosophers who have come under the influence of hermeneutics by way of Hegel, Habermas realizes that the concepts that inform current debates in the human sciences possess meanings that have evolved historically and contain their own sedimentation of past interpretations. Unlike theories in the natural sciences, social theories draw their categories and problems from everyday concerns and therefore stand in a particularly intimate relationship to their subject matter. The validity of a general theoretical paradigm is never decided solely on the basis of empirical evidence but is in part determined by its capacity to encompass the distinct interpretative contributions of the tradition in ways that give rise to new possibilities of meaning for society today. It is my hope that this book will address the needs of the novice as well as the veteran Habermas scholar. For the benefit of the former I have included an introductory chapter designed to acquaint the reader with the pertinent issues and influences shaping Habermas' s thought from 1960 to 1970. I have not hesitated to refer to the earlier writings or to remarks by commentators and critics in clarifying the present argument. In general, however, my policy has been to locate the more detailed aspects of my exegesis as well as critical asides of lesser import in the notes and to confine my own critical observations to the concluding sections of each of the four main subdivisions. Finally, I make no claim to absolute interpretative originality. My own vision owes much to the work of Thomas McCarthy, Fred Dallmayr, Richard Bernstein, and scores of others, cited and uncited. Where I differ from them is chiefly in my stress on the aesthetic dimensions of Habermas's thought. It is impossible to acknowledge all those who have helped make this book possible. But first I must express my deepest gratitude to my wife, Julia Ingram, to whom the book is dedicated, for providing an intellectual sounding board for many of my ideas. Special thanks are also due to Fred Olafson, mentor and friend, whose unflagging support helped me to survive my darkest moments as a graduate student, and to Herbert Marcuse, who spent many hours patiently explaining Hegel to me. Among those whose comments have been most helpful in revising the manuscript are Fred Dallmayr, Benjamin Gregg, and Richard Bernstein. I am also indebted to Martha Reinecke and other members of the Philosophy and Religion Department at the University of Northern Iowa, not to mention my students, for their valuable criticism. Special thanks are due to John Downey and Ruth Ratliff of the University of Northern Iowa for research funding during

xiii

Preface the summer of 1983. I am especially grateful to my editor at Yale University Press, Jeanne Ferris, for her enthusiastic support of this project. I am indebted to Cynthia Wells, Jean van Altena, and Meighan Pritchard for their assistance in the production and editing of the book, Betty Seibert and Chris Seres for typing earlier drafts of it, and to Beacon Press and Thomas McCarthy for permission to quote from their translations of Habermas' s work. I would also like to acknowledge Praxis International and The Philosophical Forum, which published some material from this book in article form. A BRIEF OUTLINE OF THE BOOK

This book documents the struggle of a great thinker to come to grips with the central paradox of modern life: the loss of freedom, meaning, and respect for human life. Th~ seeds were planted early, when, as a doctoral student still in his mid-twenties and very much affected by the postwar trauma, Habermas discovered the writings of the early Marx and the early Lukacs. At the time, he was absorbed in writing a dissertation on Schelling's transcendental reconciliation of nature and spirit, which was deeply rooted in Jewish and Christian mysticism and which figured predominantly in the ontological critique of Cartesian dualism advanced by Heidegger. However, the discovery of Marx, Lukacs, and the Young Hegelian critique of speculative philosophy by way of Lowith's masterpiece From Hegel to Nietzsche soon convinced him that the spiritual fragmentation and alienation afflicting the modern age had social rather than metaphysical causes. It was the dawning of this awareness that drew him to the Frankfurt school. As an assistant to Adorno from 1956 to 1959 he immersed himself in the study of Marxist economics, Freud, and the sociological tradition of Weber, Durkheim, and Parsons. The influence of Gadamer's philosophical hermeneutics and Apel's communicative pragmatics in the early and mid-sixties sparked a further interest in the analytic philosophy of language and science, American pragmatism, structural linguistics, and developmental psychology. More important still, it was during this period of ferment that Habermas rediscovered the seminal essays of the Zeitschrift fur Sozialforschung published by the Frankfurt school during the thirties. The need to develop a systematic grounding of societal rationality that would realize the original aim of critical theory while avoiding a dialectic of reason of the sort that later proved so tempting to Adorno and firstgeneration members of the school inspired him to publish in 1979-81 a series of programmatic sketches culminating in a theory of communicative action. I do not intend to examine in detail the various influences shaping xiv

Preface Habermas' s career. 1 The first chapter attempts to sketch in rather broad strokes the maturation of Habermas' s thought from the early to the late sixties, however. After introducing the problem of understanding by way of a brief look at the eighteenth-century quarrel between the ancients and the moderns (Vico, Descartes, Bacon, and Hobbes), I discuss in the following order Habermas's critique of Popper in the "positivist dispute" of the early sixties, his early analysis of the structural transformation of the public sphere, his Hegelian appropriation of Marx, the influence of philosophical hermeneutics and early critical theory on the development of his thought (Heidegger, Gadamer, and Horkheimer), and his first systematic effort to ground social critique in a theory of knowledge-constituting interests. Habermas' s rejection of some of the formulations concerning the relationship between theory and practice underlying Knowledge and Human Interests sets the stage for the remainder of my commentary. I wish to defend the thesis that since the late seventies, Habermas has developed a more sophisticated-and more problematic-way of conceiving this relationship, one that is torn between a discursive conception of practical reason and a conception incorporating intuitive elements. Chapters 2-5 consist of a commentary on Part 1 of Theorie. Chapter 2 lays out Habermas' s theory of rationality and action and briefly summarizes his defense of the evolutionary superiority of Occidental rationality over mythopoeic modes of thought. Winch, Lukes, Popper, Jarvie, and Piaget are among those who make their entrance in this chapter. Chapter 3 expands on the relevance of the preceding analysis for hermeneutic methodology in the social sciences and defends the possibility of objectivity and rationality in interpretation. This defense of hermeneutic sociology, which goes beyond anything Habermas has previously said on the subject, is followed by a section on linguistic philosophy that systematically surveys the contributions of various schools of thought to the development of a theory of communicative action: the speech pragmatics of Buhler, Wittgenstein, Austin, and Searle; the generative linguistics of Chomsky, and the truth-functional semantics of Carnap, Dummet, and others. Here I show how Habermas's recent reflections on the nature of perlocutionary and locutionary speech acts constitute his first significant attempt to justify the primacy of communicative over strategic action. Having established this primacy, Habermas can proceed to argue that the normative expectations regulating ideal speech-reciprocity and freedom from constraint-are implicit in the telos of communication as such and therefore constitute a prima facie refutation of ethical skepticism. Chapter 4 introduces the concept of modern, "rational" society by way of an extended commentary on that solitary thinker who has XV

Preface contributed more than anyone to its problematization, Max Weber. Weber's conception of social rationalization raises questions about the capacity of Habermas' s theory of communicative action to refute his diagnosis of modern society as necessarily tending toward a struggle between opposing factions of value and rationality. Here I present some of Habermas's recent ideas on aesthetic rationality, which seem to suggest a broadening of the category of communication. Chapter 5 continues the preceding discussion in a higher register: the appropriation of Weber's sociology by Lukacs and first-generation critical theory. The synthesis of Weber, Marx, and Freud effected by the first generation had the consequence of naturalizing reification, thereby undermining its original emancipatory intent. This paradoxical identification of reason and domination is traced by Habermas to the subject-object dualism informing the philosophy of consciousness. Toresolve the paradox, he proposes a, paradigm shift of the sort that he himself has already undertaken. Doubts persist, however, as to whether a narrowing of communicative rationality to discourse can succeed where an ontological aesthetic has failed. At this juncture, I have interjected a lengthy excursis on Habermas' s most recent works, Der Philosophische Diskurs der Moderne and Die Neue Unubersichtlichkeit, since they address the preceding concerns from the standpoint of the problematic role of aesthetics in the current debate over the relative merits of modernity and postmodernity. Accordingly, chapter 6 begins with a cursory glance at the major themes in this debate and then summarizes the positions of Habermas on the one side and Hegel, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Derrida, Bataille, and Foucault on the other. The remarkable convergence between Habermas' s communication theory and Schiller's aesthetics is a clear indication, I believe, that Habermas might be willing to extend the concept of communicative rationality to include a prediscursive moment of practical reason (phronesis). Chapters 7-10 continue where chapter 5 left off and are principally devoted to clarifying the distinction made in Theorie between lifeworld and system and to explaining their pathological dynamic. Chapter 7 addresses the contribution of communication to the symbolic reproduction of society: cultural reproduction, social integration, and socialization. Mead and Durkheim are the major figures here, Mead providing the link between communication and identity formation, Durkheim the normative foundation buttressing social solidarity. The next chapter situates Habermas' s differentiation between lifeworld and system within his theory of social evolution and concludes with a brief discussion of some of the secondary literature generated by his reconstruction of historical materialism and a critique of xvi

Preface the residual "intellectualism" implicit in his theory of ego development. Chapter 9 is concerned with Habermas's complicated relationship to the systems theory of Talcott Parsons. After introducing the concept of system and outlining Habermas's earlier debate with Niklas Luhmann, I summarize Habermas' s own lengthy exegesis of the Parsonian corpus. Chapter 10 begins with an analysis of the various interchanges between lifeworld and system and then shows how this model illuminates the social pathologies that Habermas believes to be indigenous to advanced capitalism. Colonization of the lifeworld and the splitting off of elite subcultures are contrasted with the forms of legitimation and motivation crisis discussed in his earlier studies, thereby setting the stage for the dramatic settling of accounts with first-generation critical theory over such diverse issues as bureaucratic socialism, the nuclear family, and mass culture. The final section weighs the strengths and weaknesses of Habermas's diagnosis of advanced capitalism, focusing on the role of radical politics in effecting social change, the limits and possibilities of social democracy, and the potential of critical theory for addressing the peculiar needs of women and workers. The concluding chapter returns to the relationship between theory and practice introduced at the outset and examines the recent change in Habermas' s understanding of the proper function of critical theory. I contend that the transition from ideology critique to holistic criticism is closely related to Habermas's budding interest in aesthetics and his attempt to strike a balance between everyday understanding and discursive critique.

xvii

Habermas and the Dialectic of Reason

CHAPTER ONE

The Historical Foundations of the Theory of Communicative Action

side from its impressive range and mastery of sources, the most striking feature of Habermas' s published work from the past two decades is its sense of moral purpose. In an age when technology and science reign supreme and the life of the individual is increasingly fragmented, this may seem somewhat academic. However, although science and technology can help us to evaluate the consistency of our goals, our chances of realizing them, and the means by which they can be pursued most efficiently, they cannot help us determine which goals are intrinsically worthwhile or even morally obligatory. To clarify ethical questions concerning social justice, political authority, and the good life, Habermas turns not to the methodology of the exact sciences, but to the hermeneutic, or interpretative, methodology of the human sciences (Geisteswissenschaften). The distinction that we make today between the exact sciences, humanities, and the fine arts grew out of the dissolution of the medieval curriculum. Science came into its own with the removal of theology from the academic realm and the discovery of experimental method. In the wake of these developments, Francis Bacon criticized traditional prejudice and ordinary language; eliminated theology, metaphysics, history, and poetry from the study of nature; relegated questions of right conduct to the province of divine revelation; and proposed basing ethics and politics, shorn of any normative predilection, on the method of induction. 1 Bacon's rejection of tradition as a source of moral inspiration in favor of investigation of the laws of nature for purposes of technological mastery had a profound influence on his amanuensis, Thomas Hobbes, who was the first to undertake

A

1

Historical Foundations the scientization of politics. Hobbes essentially redefined the scholastic doctrine of natural law by ridding it of its normative, teleological meaning and reinterpreting human nature in accordance with the principles of Galilean mechanics. In effect, his theory of political sovereignty constitutes a defense of Bacon's assertion that the sole aim of political science is to teach those who wield power "how to frame and subdue the will of men. 112 Several centuries before Bacon wrote his treatises, humanists such as Leonardo Bruni, Leon Alberti, and Vittorina da Feltre had rebelled against the arid metaphysical speculation of the scholastics and had sought to revive academic interest in classical studies, rhetoric, and civic virtue. 3 But it was not until the eighteenth century, after Newtonian physics had made its impact that Giambattista Vico ushered in a new and decisive phase in la querrelle des anciens et des modernes by insisting on the importance of historical understanding for the attainment of true self-knowledge. Vico started out as a Cartesian but later rejected the Cartesian claim that only ideas possessing absolute certainty and demonstrability warrant the title of truth. He attacked this view on both theoretical and practical grounds. He maintained that geometry is known with certitude only because it is based on agreed-upon conventions created by the imagination, not because it conforms to the inner reality of nature-a view that presages his radical thesis in Scienza Nuova (1725) that we can know only what we ourselves have made (verum et factum convertuntur). 4 Knowledge involves understanding the purposes of things, but because God created external nature, only he can understand its true purpose. The natural sciences can explain how reality operates, but not why. But with the languages, myths, institutions, and actions of mankind, it is different, since they are themselves human creations. As an ethicist, Vico saw that analytic rationality could not provide guidance in the areas of life that matter most, since exercise of moral judgment depends on the proper formation of character and the cultivation of common sense, imagination, and memory, and moral education consists primarily in learning the languages, traditions, and exemplary ideals of past cultures. 5 The pedagogical value of understanding as a kind of dialogue with the past was also appreciated by early nineteenth-century German romantics, including Hegel, who elevated dialectical reason (Vernunft) above analytic thought (Verstand). Hegel maintained that it is only by carrying on an interpretative dialogue with past or alien cultures that one is stimulated to reflect on one's own situation and thereby overcome the limits of one's own parochial understanding, thus achieving freedom from traditional constraints. Seen in this light, spiritual for2

Historical Foundations mation (Bildung) is not acquired by way of a skeptical bracketing of traditional assumptions, but through the interpretative preservation and critical enrichment of assumptions already operative. THE POSITIVIST CONTROVERSY AND THE SCIENTIZATION OF POLITICS

The domain in which Habermas has continued the debate between the ancients and moderns is that of the social sciences, the disciplines that, having once claimed undisputed title to the field formerly dominated by classical political thought, now aspire to the status of exact sciences. In the Positivismusstreit of the early sixties, Habermas sought to justify the primacy of a critical social science against the methodological hegemony espoused by Karl Popper and other neopositivists. 6 In seeking to capture the nature of scientific knowledge, Popper had recourse to the covering-law model, which presupposes that the proper aim of any scientific discipline is to predict particular events -to be able to derive a description of any event E from a singular statement of initial conditions C and a conditional law statement of the form, "If (whenever) C, then E." Predictions of this sort are valid if the universal laws from which they are deduced are experimentally corroborated-a notion that Popper sees as best captured in the principle of falsifiability, according to which the empirical value of a general law is proportional to the number of predictions to which it gives rise that could be falsified on the basis of factual observation. A social science based on the covering-law model would therefore refrain from passing judgment on the overall goal of history or of a given society, since neither unconditional teleological predictions nor evaluations are susceptible to empirical falsification. The practical worth of such a social science would be gauged by its capacity to produce behavioral laws permitting the discovery of efficient means for engineering incremental changes in social institutions. 7 Habermas' s rejoinders to Popper focused on both the methodological and philosophical limitations of his position. Methodologically, it has been noted by Weber, Collingwood, and others that statistical uniformities ... "constitute 'sociological generalizations' only when they can be regarded as manifestations of the understandable meaning of a course of action." One cannot explain why a given action has occurred by appealing to how often it happens. One must also appeal to the intentions of the actor. Indeed, one has already begun to explain the intentional causes of an action when one has understood its meaning. 8 Habermas cited William Dray's objections to the coveringlaw model as particularly apposite in this regard. Dray argues that for

3

Historical Foundations a behavioral law to be valid, it must be either so general as to apply to any action whatsoever, in which case it is too trivial to provide sufficient explanation, or so specific that only the action in question counts as an instance of it, in which case it succeeds only by sacrificing its nomothetic generality. 9 In any case, appeal to observed behavior can at most allow an observer to adduce a functional meaning, extending no further than objectively postulated "aims" of biological survival. But actions to procure the basic necessities of life are undertaken in accordance with cultural values that define a standard of living considerably higher than that of mere subsistence. The meaning of an agent's action is symbolically constituted with respect to shared meanings; therefore it cannot be described adequately without some participatory understanding of the network of communicative action sustaining these meanings. But participatory understanding requires that the objectifying, value-neutral standpoint of an impartial observer give way to the subjectively open, value-committed attitude of an interlocutor in a shared practice .10 Although Habermas offers a defense of hermeneutic social science on strictly methodological grounds, he is more concerned to establish an ethical basis for his position. He believes that behavioral social science can "be called upon as an auxiliary science in rational administration" only if it is supplemented by a hermeneutic social science that elucidates the rational ends and interests to be served. 11 He has devoted considerable effort to examining the ethical implications of social engineering and the scientization of political life. Political philosophy as Aristotle understood it was an extension of ethics that aimed to cultivate moral character and to further the attainment of the good and just life. Since Hobbes, however, its scope has gradually narrowed to the technical resolution of social problems, thereby contributing to another-the nihilism wrought by a scientization of life. 12 In his early study Strukturwandel der Offentlichkeit (1962), Habermas traced the emergence of an enlightened, politicized public realm in the eighteenth century and its gradual emasculation under advanced capitalism. Whereas in feudal society the public saw itself as passively representing a divinely preordained political order, with the rise of capitalism a public sphere emerged, composed of private citizens who sought to limit the authority of the state and affirm the principle of public accountability. 13 The state was regarded as legitimate as long as it implemented the general interests of the public under conditions of free association and free speech; thus government proceedings were to be made public, and the press was to be allowed to form and articulate a critical public opinion. 14 Although Habermas recognizes that this liberal phase of the bour4

Historical Foundations geois public sphere was not entirely free of contradictions, in that the great mass of workers and peasants were excluded from membership and private interests often supervened in what was ostensibly a rational articulation of the public interest, he nonetheless appreciates the principle of democratic· self-determination and critical accountability that it embodied. 15 With the development of modern capitalism, however, the conditions that nurtured the bourgeois public sphere -homogeneous class interests and a relatively high level of education and material affluence-disappeared. The intensification of class conflict in the nineteenth century and the concomitant expansion of the press beyond its original bourgeois base were accompanied by both a decline in disinterested discussion and a rise in propaganda wars between competing private interests. 16 The dissolution of public life into naked power struggles between self-interested economic classes presaged the absorption of the market into the protective orbit of the welfare state in the twentieth century. This "refeudalisation of the public sphere" stems from the need of the state to make controversial decisions vital to the management of a class-based economy without fear of public reprisal and to plan policy without regard to public demands for accountability. But this requires depoliticizing the public sphere and making it malleable to the state's designs. This is accomplished by artificially orchestrating public opinion so as to promote the illusion of a profusion of competing interests. The assumption that such interests are rationally irreducible indirectly justifies the right of the state to intervene in the role of arbitratorY It also contributes to the further dissemination of "technocratic consciousness," for, if economic interests cannot be decided rationally, then public policy planning geared toward the technological maintenance of steady economic growth must be directed from above by trained bureaucratic elites. 18 THE MARXIAN AND HEGELIAN LEGACIES

Although Habermas sees Popper's position as symptomatic of the scientific-technological obsession of modern society, he does not advocate a return to the natural law doctrines of classical political philosophy, much less a return to what Popper, thinking of Hegel and Marx, calls historicism. Nevertheless, it is these latter thinkers who supply him with much of the inspiration for his own critical theory. For Marx, the aim of social theory is to enlighten people about their true interests, so that they can plan their historical destinies in a rational manner. Marx believed that the natural life process (Naturwuchsigkeit) of prebourgeois societies, rooted as it is in the dark sediment 5

Historical Foundations of preconscious traditions and parochial prejudices, would gradually be eroded in the process of secularization initiated by the industrial revolution. Still, he was aware that the acquisitive, self-serving behavior of competing entrepreneurs in an unregulated market would produce fortuitous events at the macroeconomic level. The only solution in his view was the revolutionary overthrow of class domination and the establishment of a socialist society spearheaded by an enlightened proletariat. But what Marx envisaged as rational conduct was not the enlightened egoism of Adam Smith but rather presupposed the attainment of a superior consciousness of human sociality. 19 The major obstacles to achieving class consciousness, Marx believed, were ideology, which involves the manipulation of the cultural superstructure for the purpose of legitimating exploitative class relations, and commodity fetishism, which creates the illusion that social relations among persons are natural and invariant. 20 Although Marx believed that labor organizations would engender authentic feelings of solidarity, he was well aware that isolated enclaves of proletarian militancy would be vulnerable to fetishism and parochial prejudice. Subsequently, he came to believe that the critique of political economy which he undertook in Das Kapital was indispensable for raising proletarian class consciousness. By exposing the lie of equal exchange in the production of profit and by showing that accumulation of capital was ultimately contingent on the labor of dispossessed producers, Das Kapital shattered bourgeois illusions of equality, freedom, and justice, as well as the fetishistic reification of society. 21 The critique of ideology was the dominant motif in Habermas's vision of a social theory prior to the present decade. Much of his work during this period involved reformulating Marx's method of ideology critique and recasting the philosophical foundations of his theory of historical materialism. 22 Because he failed to anticipate governmental regulation of the economy, Marx discounted the tenacious hold of authoritarian patterns of thought on individuals in bourgeois society. But the authoritarian personality was later recognized by members of the Frankfurt school, following their discovery of Freud, to have its roots in basic psychological drives. Moreover, their recognition of the inability of the nuclear family to provide strong parent-child role identification, the intransigence of ideology conceived as a mass cultural phenomenon embracing the linguistic base of social consciousness as such, and the transference of legitimation functions from the economic sector to the political sphere in post-liberal capitalism led them to eschew the critique of political economy in favor of

Kulturkritik. Habermas followed first-generation critical theorists such as 6

Historical Foundations Adorno, Marcuse, and Horkheimer in removing the locus of ideology critique from the economy to language and culture. But in so doing, he, perhaps more deliberately than they, sought to recover the seminal inspiration of critical theory in Hegel's philosophy. The early Marx had also returned to Hegel, but in a rather different way. For him, Hegel's account of the master-slave dialectic in The Phenomenology of Spirit brings into relief the moment of self-objectification in which the slave achieves self-confirmation in an external form. Here, Marx believed, was the true basis of practical reason, for every act of self-objectification is simultaneously a reflection on the self objectified, so that the latter is changed along with the object. But every satisfaction of a need generates a new need. Seen in this light, labor overcomes nature's resistance to human fulfillment while making satisfaction of the needs of others a necessary condition for the satisfaction of one's own needs. The entire motivation for Marx's materialism is summed up in the transference of rational Bildung from the ethereal plane of abstract philosophical contemplation-as in Hegel's mature political philosophy-to that of concrete practice. Habermas takes exception to this assimilation of Bildung to labor, claiming that it led to Marx's equation of rationalization with scientific and technological progress. To defend the integrity of critical theory, he turns to Hegel's early Jena philosophy of mind, 23 in which Geist (spirit or social life) is seen as the intersection of family, language, and labor. Whereas language is the primary vehicle of social integration, communication being the medium in which individuals come to share a common moral identity based on reciprocal expectations, labor, the medium of need gratification (desire), enables one to achieve a sense of security with respect to nature. 24 Hegel further addresses the relationship between language and identity in his description of the criminal whose abrogation of an ethical totality leads to the suppression of the moral bond linking criminal and victim and to a later overwhelming compulsion to atone. In Habermas's opinion, the alienation of the criminal from society exemplifies the peculiar "causality of fate" that occurs when the reciprocity between social classes is violated. The ideological suppression of open communication invariably produces identity crises, anomie social relationships, and political strife. Hence the Bildung of humanity is a dual struggle for emancipation: from the material constraints imposed by economic scarcity and the communicative constraints imposed by domination. 25 PHILOSOPHICAL HERMENEUTICS AND CRITICAL THEORY

Gadamer' s philosophical hermeneutics is indebted principally to Heidegger's notion that understanding-here conceived as the disclo7

Historical Foundations sure of meaningful experience, the aperture onto the world through which we have any world worth speaking of-is an integral aspect of human existence (Dasein). Heidegger likens it to projecting a net of familiar meanings in light of expectations. Reading is a case in point: the meaning of each word unfolds in anticipated completion of the sentence, just as the meaning of each sentence unfolds in anticipated completion of the text. The interdependence of part and whole is analogous to the contextuality of practical and perceptual experience. Perceptual phenomena are not disclosed initially as "things" possessing substantive properties such as weight and extension, but as pragmata capable of facilitating or obstructing action. They are thus identified with respect to a meaningful totality of assignments and functions that refers ultimately to the intentions, aims, and interests of the agent. Thus the throwing into relief of a particular idea or interest against a horizon of possible meaningfulness (world) is always relative to practical expectations that are themselves shaped by the cultural presuppositions determining identity. 26 The subject and object of understanding are thus related to one another in a kind of ontological circle. What first seems meaningless or unfamiliar calls forth a special effort of reflection, thereby provoking a revision of expectations. What was at first merely implicit-the preunderstanding of the interpreter and the alien grammar of the subject matter-is made explicit; thus the identity of each term in the relationship is changed. It is as if the subject matter becomes part of the interpreter and vice versa, or, better, as if subject and object are subordinate aspects of a single continuum of meaning (being). 27 Understanding is thus characterized by a kind of historical continuity, or historicity (Geschichtlichkeit), by means of which the cultural heritage that forms part of the interpreter's identity is continually being reinterpreted. 28 Gadamer's Truth and Method (1960), whose controversial critique of scientific method became something of a cause celebre among both radical and conservative German intellectuals opposed to positivism, developed Heidegger's theory of understanding in a way that proved to be particularly seminal for Habermas' s critical program in Erkenntnis. Gadamer's primary aim was to discredit the empathetic model of understanding deriving from the romantic tradition of Schleiermacher, Ranke, and Dilthey. Although this tradition started out as a reaction against the Enlightenment, it discarded neither the subject-object dualism nor the methodological glorification of valuefreedom that were its Cartesian trademarks. Although some of its later exponents, including Weber and Emilio Betti, acknowledged the irrefutable link between values and understanding (Wertbeziehung), 8

Historical Foundations they still held that understanding was a kind of psychological reliving (Nacherleben) of thought processes. Therefore, understanding culminating in the correct "correspondence" between subject and object of interpretation required putting in abeyance one's own cultural presuppositions and immersing oneself in the alien Weltanschauung of the subject matter. 29 Gadamer submits that the subject-object dichotomy embraced by romantic hermeneutics is controverted by the ontological continuity of historical life. Psychological empathy (Einfuhlen) and reenactment (Nacherleben) are confused with true understanding, which involves deciphering the meaning of a nondatable, publicly communicable message. Once the message is understood, it acts as a bridge linking interpreter and text. Far from effacing the interpreter's assumptions and interests, the attempt to reach an understanding (Verstiindigung) brings them into play, generating in the process a critical interplay of questions and answers. Because it is assumed that a text's message is potentially true and coherent, understanding issues is a practical dialectic or mutual critique, whose "truth" is at once the fusion and expansion of distinct horizons (Horizontverschmelzung). 30 By demonstrating that all forms of knowledge and experience are interpretative in the deepest sense, Gadamer' s philosophical hermeneutics undercuts the shibboleth of value-neutrality and presuppositionlessness that lies at the center of positivism. Science does not mirror reality; it interprets it as a measurable spatiotemporal field of matter and energy in accordance with its own methodological assumptions. Habermas is in agreement here; he also sees Gadamer's critique of romantic hermeneutics as explaining why deep ethical currents run through the human sciences. Every successful understanding applies new meaning to the current situation of the interpreter, thereby revealing new possibilities for action. 31 Although in his work prior to the mid-sixties Habermas stressed the dependence of critical reflection on historically situated understanding, he returned eventually to a more orthodox, transcendental approach to philosophizing, of the sort practiced by neo-Kantians such as Rickert, Windelband, and Dilthey. In this reorientation, first articulated by Habermas in his 1965 inaugural address, we detect a concern with system building and critical methodology. This break with philosophical hermeneutics chiefly hinged on dissatisfaction with its deference to tradition. Philosophical hermeneutics assumes that the possibilities of understanding self and society are circumscribed by prevailing tradition, and that although we can question any given cultural belief, such questioning will necessarily be relative to some more fundamental, unquestioned assumption. Hence any 9

Historical Foundations criticism of an entire tradition is precluded. Because of the obvious implication of this posture for ideology critique, Habermas came to reject the ontological identification of tradition and understanding just as strenuously as he had earlier repudiated the positivistic equation of science and knowledge. 32 However, if neither the human sciences, whose primary aim is the preservation of tradition for its own sake, nor the exact sciences, whose principal aim is the technical domination of objective nature, provide adequate models for critical social science, then what science or methodology does? Max Horkheimer addressed this problem in his 1937 manifesto "Traditional and Critical Theory." He saw modern science as a continuation of traditional metaphysics, rather than its negation, for both science and metaphysics construe objective reality as an eternal "given" that comes to be known through disinterested contemplation or value-neutral measurement. Traditional metaphysics, with its system of beliefs mirroring eternal laws, is "uncritical" in two senses in Horkheimer' s judgment: not only does it uncritically accept the status quo, but it fails to examine the validity of its own presuppositions. As for science, its presuppositions are linked to the "advance of the bourgeois period," with its demand for technically exploitable knowledge.33 The emergence of capitalism is not the ultimate raison d'etre of the exact sciences, to be sure; nevertheless, it provides the societal framework necessary for the methodological articulation of what is otherwise an anthropologically entrenched interest in domination. But insofar as that domination is extended over social relations, there arises a counter interest in emancipation, whose corollary is the method of reflection peculiar to critical social science. The latter delimits the validity and scope of particular branches of knowledge while freeing the social agent from the ideological integuments of tradition. 34 The main difficulty facing Horkheimer and other members of the Frankfurt school was that of establishing a legitimating warrant for critical reflection that would be as securely grounded in social life as that for technical knowledge. This has also been a central preoccupation of Habermas, whose efforts have been largely designed to rectify the failures of his predecessors. Habermas maintains that past attempts ran aground largely because they were based on the assumption of a culturally immanent critique of ideology and therefore, like philosophical hermeneutics, could not avoid the pitfalls of historical relativism. Horkheimer's claim that the emancipatory aim can be variously recognized as a "force in history," "an expression of cultural creations," or "goals of human activity . . . immanent in human work" are, in Habermas' s opinion, hopelessly vague and rely entirely 10

Historical Foundations upon the validity of contingent historical interpretations and expressions. 35 KNOWLEDGE AND HUMAN INTERESTS

In his inaugural address Habermas paid tribute to Horkheimer's hypothesis regarding cognitive interests by suggesting that critical theory need not derive its standards from fortuitous traditions but could establish a transcendental warrant for its endeavors that would be universally valid. Three years later he published his first systematic treatise on the subject. Erkenntnis is an ambitious attempt to renew the critique of knowledge first undertaken by Kant and subsequently radicalized by Hegel and Marx. In his Critique of Pure Reason (1781) Kant sought to uncover the necessary conditions for the possibility of experiencing objects. Its critical function lay in confining the valid epistemic deployment of reason to the sensory fields of space and time, its positive intent in refuting Hume's skeptical animadversions concerning causality, substance, and other principles underlying Newtonian mechanics, through a transcendental proof of their objective validity. Habermas's project radicalizes Kant's critique in the direction of Marx's social theory by taking up anew Hegel's phenomenological metacritique of transcendental epistemology. Hegel appeals to the dialectical element implicit in Kant's transcendentalism-that the only meaningful objective reality is that constituted by the knowing subject-in order to refute the idea of a nature existing independently of consciousness. By the same token, he rejects the notion of transcendental subjectivity, because it ignores the conditioning of consciousness by society and history. Because individual consciousness is determined by society and culture, knowledge (of what is) and judgment (of what ought to be) are mutually interdependent. Hegel's metacritique runs aground, however, in its Schellingian postulation of an absolute identity of subject and object. Not only does his concept of absolute knowledge contradict his own account of the open dialectic of experience, but his ontological assimilation of experience to conceptual thought excludes material aspects of social being that condition thought from without. 36 Marx's appeal to labor as an invariant anthropological structure marks a return to Kant's transcendental philosophy and its postulation of an irreducible element of external contingency (nature-in-itself). By stressing that life is conditioned by its own objectifications, Marx initiates the final transition from idealistic metacritique to materialistic ideology critique. Because it must now incorporate reflection on the social evolution of the human species, epistemology must aspire to the rank of critical social theory. 11

Historical Foundations Although Habermas accepts Marx's critique of German idealism, his own use of the category of cognitive interest to tie together action, knowledge, reason, and emancipation is wholly indebted to Kant's notion of a practical interest in reason. Pursuing the penetrating line of inquiry pioneered by Charles Peirce, Habermas argues that scientific method, understood as a procedure for attaining a progressive consensus about reality, ultimately derives its validity from the natural trial-and-error revision of beliefs that accompanies the success or failure of adaptive behavior. 37 When the need for technological enhancement of economic productivity arose during the Renaissance, this feedback circuit was gradually institutionalized in the form of modem experimental science. For Peirce, both the validity and the meaning of scientific knowledge are ultimately traceable to behavior necessary for survival. 38 Habermas maintains that once the instrumental activity necessary for survival is institutionalized under the aegis of science, it becomes a social learning process mediated by a different kind of activity, communication. He regards ordinary communication as an epistemological action-interest framework that founds the hermeneutic methodology of the human sciences. Drawing on Dilthey's post-psychological writings and their hermeneutic appropriation of the Hegelian category of life, Habermas notes that the part-whole circle intrinsic to narrative understanding has its basis in one's personal experience. The stability, coherence, and identity of this autobiography is sustained by acquiring generat intersubjectively recognized categories of meaning that connect one to the community. Underwriting the social sciences is the aim of maintaining a historical continuity of meaning and identity, first and foremost at the level of communal life and second, by implication, at the level of individual biographical life. The survival of a society as a distinct entity possessing its own identity not only depends on securing harmonious interaction among its members based on universally accepted norms, but also requires sustaining a sense of moral purpose over generations, a function for which history and philology are particularly well suited. 39 Operational behavior and communicative action comprise two distinct aspects of social life, corresponding roughly to labor (the instrumental satisfaction of material needs) and language (the establishment through communication of a shared sense of meaning and value). It is because labor and communication make distinct contributions to social life (facts and values) that political and economic domination, the third determinant of social life, can ideologically disturb the formation of culture and tradition below the threshold of linguis-

12

Historical Foundations tic understanding-hence the need for critical theory. The interest governing such theory is explicitly emancipatory in that it aims to strip the social agent of deeply engrained patterns of thought that constrain self-understanding. Unlike the technological interest in controlling nature and the practical interest in sustaining social harmony, the emancipatory interest is not coeval with society; nor does it constitute reality from a particular transcendental perspective. With the advent of modern class society, however, it has increasingly become a survival interest. As Habermas puts it, the interest in emancipation develops "to the degree to which repressive force, in the form of the normative exercise of power, presents itself permanently in structures of distorted communication. " 40 Because technological and moral progress requires unconstrained discourse, there is a sense in which all knowledge is related to an emancipatory interest. Habermas's understanding of this relationship is chiefly indebted to Fichte, for whom a practical decision to free oneself from all unquestioned presuppositions was a necessary condition for achieving insight into the universal conditions of knowledge. Although Habermas criticizes Fichte for his neglect of political struggle, he nonetheless accepts his principal thesis that in emancipatory reflection, our practical interest in becoming free, universal moral agents coincides with our theoretical interest in gaining knowledge about the natural and social conditions that shape us.41 Habermas recommends psychoanalysis as a methodological paradigm for critical reflection, first, because the aetiological profile of neurosis is similar to that of ideological delusion, and second, because the combination of causal explanation and sinnverstehen succeeds in steering a middle course between the objectivism of the behavioral sciences and the subjectivism of a purely hermeneutic approach. 42 On this model, ideological delusion stems from a censoring process in which the need defended against is denied expression in language, action, and culture; but repressed needs continue to influence behavior subconsciously, compelling the neurotic to act compulsively. Similarly, in a society in which individuals no longer feel satisfied with the rewards attendant on fulfilling ideological expectations, all the symptoms of social disintegration (identity crisis) -apathy, alienation, anomie-manifest themselves. In this case sublimation is accompanied by displacement of need gratification to substitutes such as religion, art, entertainment, and economic consumption. Although Habermas agrees with Freud that every society that has existed hitherto has needed to rechannel libidinal drives

13

Historical Foundations away from reproduction in order to satisfy the exigencies of work and consumption, he also believes that the degree of sublimation that is socially necessary in a given society is inversely proportional to its level of material affluence!3 Psychotherapy also appears to strike a good methodological balance between the distancing and participatory approaches of the behavioral and hermeneutic sciences. Although Freud tried to explicate the assumptions inherent in psychoanalysis in terms of a physicalistic tension-reduction paradigm, he later came to realize that classical philology offered a more perspicacious comparison, since it too involved the hermeneutic restoration of a mutilated text. 44 Psychoanalysis aims at restoring the full text of a patient's life by reincorporating repressed contents into the stream of consciousness. Following Alfred Lorenzer, Habermas characterizes this process as a reinsertion of paleo-symbolic contents into public language. In contrast to philological interpretation, which relies on the etymological connection between living and dead language to fill in textual gaps whose meaning has been obscured due to the passage of time, psychoanalysis is called on to dispel misunderstandings whose origin has nothing to do with changes in meaning brought about by the evolution of language, but stems instead from the repression of meaning caused by extralinguistic conflicts. To understand the meaning of a neurotic episode, one must explain its cause, which has its origin in some event in childhood involving a subconscious conflict between the id (the unconscious agency of desire) and the superego (the introjection of parental authority). 45 The theoretical basis of psychoanalytic depth interpretation consists of general interpretations of psychodynamic development that specify lawlike phases (oral, anal, phallic, and genital) of object identification, conflict, and conflict mastery. Like theories in the natural sciences, general interpretations permit the deduction of invariant causal relationships between specific types of conflict and specific pathological modes of conflict resolution. Unlike theories in the natural sciences, however, the lawlike succession of developmental stages retains a hermeneutic and teleological dimension, for the ego is like an actor in a drama, struggling to achieve full moral identity, autonomy, and self-understanding. The reflective integration of concealed motives breaks the pathological link between the repressed motive and a particular behavior. Finally, unlike scientific predictions, general interpretations cannot be demonstrably falsified, since the normal behavior that they predict upon completion of treatment depends entirely on whether the patient successfully completes the process of reflection provoked by the analysis. 46 14

Historical Foundations KNOWLEDGE AND HUMAN INTERESTS RECONSIDERED

Although Erkenntnis continues to stimulate discussion among scholars, Habermas has largely abandoned the attempt to ground critical social theory in cognitive interests. His reasons, some of which are mentioned in his "Postscript to Knowledge and Human Interests" (1973) and in the introduction to the second edition of Theorie and Praxis (1971) do not relate to the soundness of the program, but only its execution. First, there are obvious difficulties in trying to explain the peculiar status of a cognitive interest, which "is not meant to suggest a naturalistic reduction of transcendental logical categories to empirical ones. " 47 It is not an interest that is productive of individual happiness, yet, despite the fact that such interests are implicated in the survival of the species, they do not possess the invariant habitus of biological instincts or drives. "Cognitive interests," Habermas insists, "mediate the natural genesis of mankind with the logic of its cultural development." 48 However, the precise sense in which "human interests ... derive both from nature and from the cultural break with nature" remains obscure. Occasionally Habermas suggests that these interests are inextricably tied to a cultural notion of self-preservation commensurate with the emergence of the emancipatory interest in achieving the good life. But if so, the theory of cognitive interests moves perilously close to historicism and its reduction of the transcendental to the empirical. Moreover, as McCarthy remarks, it is faced with the same conundrums that have plagued German idealism from Kant onward. For, if the interest in technological control constitutes our experience of nature under the auspices of mechanistic science, how can it also be understood as having evolved empirically as part of humanity's natural history? Habermas' s appeal to nature-initself (natura naturans) as a quasi-teleological ground of cultural evolution appears to be wholly speculative and indefensible in view of the nonteleological conditions under which nature, understood as a domain of objects (natura naturata), appears to us. 49 A more serious problem is Habermas' s conflation of philosophical and emancipatory reflection. As K.-0. Apel and Dietrich Bohler have pointed out, it is no more possible to identify an interest in impartial philosophical analysis with a commitment to engage in risky political struggle than to equate transcendental reflection on the necessary and universal conditions of knowledge with the sort of emancipatory reflection apposite to psychoanalysis and ideology critique. 50 In the years since the publication of Erkenntnis, Habermas has conceded that his attempt to ground critical social theory in epistemic interests was flawed by his ambiguous usage of the word reflection. Philosophical

15

Historical Foundations reflection, or rational reconstruction, is a pure form of theoretical knowledge that is motivated by neither technical, communicative, nor emancipatory interests but is "generated within a reflexive attitude."51 As such it abstracts from particular historical contexts and has no immediate practical consequences. This distinction between rational reconstruction and emancipatory reflection coincides with a revision in Habermas' s conception of the relationship between theory and practice. In redefining this relationship, he expanded his original conception of knowledge to include a new taxonomy consisting of two distinctions: between truth and intersubjectively accepted belief and between discourse and action. The former is necessary because universal cognitive interests alone are not sufficient grounds for establishing the possibility of true, rationally justifiable belief (knowledge in the strong sense), however entrenched they may be in forms of.action that "constitute" intersubjectively accepted or objectively valid belief. The intersubjective acceptance of belief means only "that everybody can count on the success or failure of certain actions. The truth of a proposition ... means that everybody can be persuaded by reasons to recognize the truth-claim of a statement as being justified. " 52 Such a distinction, Habermas insists, is a necessary postulate of the sciences. Just as critical theory must distinguish between ideologically induced consensus and authentic solidarity, so too the natural scientific distinction between objective experience and scientific knowledge helps to explain why the commonsense view of reality as a spatiotemporal continuum of sensory things, though scientifically false, possesses a practical validity that is rooted in patterns of operational behavior common to all historical cultures. 53 The distinction between truth and objective validity corresponds to that between discourse and action. Discourse is a form of pure communication that, in a manner reminiscent of Husserl's phenomenological epoche, hypothetically brackets the validity of all existential and normative assumptions for purposes of rational examination. Purged of the external and internal constraints associated with everyday action, it seeks true statements and right prescriptions and is motivated solely by the force of the better argument. By contrast, action is guided by conventional attitudes that are intersubjectively compelling in a dogmatic sense. Thus discourse is bound by counterfactual reasons, action by factual constraints. Using these distinctions, Habermas reinstated the categorical separation of theory and practice by relegating philosophical reflection to the realm of discourse, emancipatory reflection to the therapeutic dialogue between party intelligentsia and rank-and-file membership. Al-

16

Historical Foundations though such dialogue is dependent on the particular historical context, it cannot provide guidance for prospective political action. Thus questions of political strategy remain theoretically undecidable. The willingness of a political constituency to act on the interpretations offered by party intelligentsia furnishes indirect confirmation of critical social theory, though failure to do so, given the potential risks of political praxis, does not falsify it. 54 In retrospect, the difficulties encountered by Habermas in his effort to ground critical theory in cognitive interests led to two major revisions in his thinking. First, the distinction between rational reconstruction and emancipatory reflection corresponded to a new conception of the relationship between history and theory. The "natural history of the human species" presupposed by Erkenntnis was not only epistemologically question-begging, but appeared to bind the validity of critical theory to contingent historical reflection. Since the early seventies, Habermas has attempted to avoid historical relativism by reconstructing the social evolution of human beings on the basis of genetic structuralist studies of the sort undertaken by Piaget and Kohlberg. This approach ostensibly avoids the reduction of developmental structures to actual historical processes. Second, the epistemological grounding of critical theory, though not strictly transcendental in a Kantian sense, was still burdened by transcendental paradoxes associated with the old philosophy of consciousness (Bewusstseinsphilosophie). To avoid these problems, it seemed advisable to locate the validating basis of critical theory in something other than knowledge, nature, or history. Habermas had already announced a way out of the impasse in the inaugural address: The standards of self-reflection ... possess a theoretical certainty. The human interest in autonomy and responsibility is not a mere fancy, for it can be apprehended a priori. What raises us out of nature is the only thing whose nature we can know-language. Through its structure, autonomy and responsibility are posited for us. Our first sentence expresses unequivocally the intention of a universal and unconstrained consensus ... only in an emancipated society whose members' autonomy and responsibility had been realized, would communication have developed into the non-authoritarian and universally practical dialogue from which both our model of reciprocally constituted ego-identity and our idea of true consensus are always implicitly derived. To this extent the truth of statements is based upon anticipating the realisation of the good life. 55

The idea that critical theory finds its justification in communication has been the chief inspiration for Habermas's research since the late sixties. What remained on the agenda was the philosophical reconstruction that would support this contention. If there is a serious 17

Historical Foundations question about the tenability of this project, it is whether it reintroduces the kind of gap between theory and practice that Habermas has always sought to avoid. Little in this program bears witness to the classical conception of the summum bonum. Not only is there no attempt to relate societal happiness to rational discourse, but there is a lingering suspicion that this program is not as critical as it first appears. If rational reconstruction is essentially detached from the immediate concerns of social life, then does it not represent a return to traditional theorizing? The vindication of critical theory from this charge and the reaffirmation of its practical intent is the paramount aim of Theorie. It remains to be seen, however, whether Habermas's monumental effort to elucidate the relationship between reason and historical understanding, structure and process, system and lifeworld, succeeds and, if so, at what price.

18

CHAPTER TWO

Rationality, Reality, and Action

n the foreword and introduction to Theorie, Habermas reminds us of the provisional nature of his undertaking. Although it shares the traditional philosophical aim of subsuming the various realms of thought under a single umbrella, it follows modern philosophy in forsaking absolute knowledge of the whole. It thus eschews the ontological agenda of traditional metaphysics and of contemporary proponents of identity theory, while remaining ever mindful of the subjectivist impasse of Kant's critical philosophy. It continues the line of research pioneered by Habermas in his earlier studies of communication, whose common aim was the defense of practical reason against positivistic abridgement. 1 But, most important, it reformulates the problem of rationality at three levels of analysis. The metatheoretical level situates the relationship between action and reason within a developmental account of rational learning capacities. This proves to be indispensable at the methodological level, where the understanding of meaningful social action is shown to presuppose rational critique. Third, the theory of rationality establishes at the empirical level a critical basis for identifying progressive and regressive features of modern society. 2

I

RATIONAL ACTION

Theorie begins with a provisional conceptual analysis of rationality and its relationship to action and language, premised on the idea that rational action is inextricably linked to argumentation. Since Plato, philosophers have held that the distinction between correct opinion and true knowledge hinges on the role of reasoned justification in permitting us to hold a belief with confidence. Appealing to our im19

Rationality, Reality, and Action plicit understanding of rational action as behavior that is guided by knowledge, Habermas argues that the function of practical reason is to provide arguments supporting the beliefs underwriting decisions to act. This inference is not as straightforward as it might at first seem, for much of the knowledge guiding our actions consists in aptitudes, skills, and competencies-in other words, tacit know-how-that we would have difficulty describing and explaining, let alone justifying. But for Habermas, a considerable portion of habitual knowledge must be susceptible to such explicit, propositional formulation if the action in question is to be seen as rational. A rational action, then, is one about which an agent could entertain rationally justifiable beliefs. Habermas' s paradigm case involves a person who undertakes some goal-oriented action; such action may be highly adaptive, but unless it can be justified in terms of beliefs about means and ends founded on verifiable causal regularities, it cannot be considered rational. 3 Habermas thus reminds us that reasoning proper unfolds within the fundamentally different frame of reference of communication. Whereas persons acting alone are rational to the extent that they efficiently satisfy their private needs, social agents, who are accountable to others, are rational only to the extent that they resolve potential conflicts through argumentation. But willingness to be persuaded by reason implies, among other things, that agreement is constrained solely by the force of the better argument. 4 In avoiding the pragmatist confusion of rationality with instrumental adaptation, Habermas reaffirms the phenomenological insight that the environment to which we adapt is already a linguistically articulated world of shared-and to that extent, public and objective-experience. 5 Of course, some of the beliefs underlying the rationality of our actions are nonfactual. In order to be fully rational, an action must be morally and legally right; it must sincerely express the authentic feelings and desires of the agent and be oriented toward the shared values of the given community. Thus rational action is guided not only by factual beliefs whose claims (Geltungsanspruche) to truth can beargued, but also by normative, expressive, and evaluative beliefs with their claims to rightness (Richtigkeit), sincerity (Wahrhaftigkeit), authenticity (Authentizitiit), and appropriateness (Angemessenheit). 6 It is important to note that the conditions of argumentative discourse vary according to the type of validity being claimed. With regard to a factual belief, we expect arguments to be forthcoming that would convince anyone of its truth. But Habermas insists that such an expectation of universal assent obtains mutatis mutandis in the case of claims to moral, or normative, rightness as well. It would be irrational for me to believe that I ought to perform some act while not

20

Rationality, Reality, and Action believing, ceteris paribus, that anyone else in a similar situation ought to perform it also. I would be applying a general rule inconsistently if, while holding that there were no morally relevant differences between my situation and that of another, I bound myself to a moral precept that I did not recognize as binding for that other person. Here Habermas follows Kant in holding that the deontological force of moral obligation prohibits exceptions, that we are always required to set aside our selfish interests when they conflict with the universal interest. 7 It is noteworthy in light of Habermas's ultimate goal of providing a unitary model of rationality that his two major exceptions to the model of theoretical and practical discourse-therapeutic and aesthetic critique-deviate in important respects from the pragmatic logic of argumentation. In the first, consistency of behavior, rather than argumentation, is the decisive factor in rationally determining the sincerity of a person's intentions; moreover, canons of discourse are just as inapplicable when the person in question is suffering from self-deception. Therapeutic dialogue-psychotherapy in the case of individual neurosis and ideology critique in the case of mass delusion-may appeal to argumentation, but the latter is necessarily circumscribed by the clinical setting, which is fundamentally incompatible with the reciprocity conditions required for an unconstrained, impartial effort to reach agreement. 8 The second, aesthetic critique, although in other respects abiding by the canons of discursive impartiality, departs from the expectations of strict universalizability implicit in theoretical and practical discourse. It is only since 1976 that Habermas has ascribed to art a unique claim to appropriateness, and his decision to do so is somewhat obscured by his tendency to identify art with claims to success, authenticity, and harmony (Stimmigkeit) as well. Aesthetic disputes resist adjudication vis-a-vis objective principles (either cognitive or moral); yet, unlike expressions of a purely personal, sensual gratification, judgments of taste claim an "exemplary necessity and universality." For Kant, this means that aesthetic judgments are instances of a rule grounded in a transcendental sensus communis, or prediscursive a priori agreement; for Habermas, that they are instances of discursive interpretations of the good life-and therewith the needs appropriate to that life in its authenticity and integrity (Stimmigkeit)-with respect to specific cultural values indigenous to given historical communities.9 The irreducibility of aesthetic rationality to the formal pragmatic conditions of argumentative discourse is further reinforced by Habermas' s most recent pronouncements regarding the mediating function of art, which "reaches into our cognitive interpretations and norma-

21

Rationality, Reality, and Action tive expectations and transforms the totality in which these moments are related to one another." 10 This "cognitive" function of art plays a key role in Habermas' s new critical program, as we shall see later. Habermas devotes considerable attention to the presuppositions underlying theoretical and practical discourse, since these provide the most important rationale for social critique. His analysis of argumentative discourse is greatly indebted to Stephen Toulmin's attempt to capture "the force of the better argument" in terms of general structures of consensually oriented dialogue.U Some of these structures involve familiar elements of argumentation: the conclusion to be grounded, the grounds cited in support of the conclusion, the warrant connecting the grounds to the conclusion, and the backing for the warrant itself. This model permits a radicalization of reflection that renders disputes over competing theoretical paradigms resolvable by appeal to practical reasoh, whereas political disagreements over common interests lead in extreme cases to a therapeutic critique of needs. 12 Habermas follows Aristotle's triadic division of argumentation into logic, rhetoric, and dialectic. The most important structures defining theoretical and practical discourse are those extralogical conditions that capture the counterfactual notion of validity, or rational persuasion, since it is precisely these that possess an explicit ethical content. As products of logic, arguments must exhibit both internal and external consistency among interlocutors over the meanings of terms. As a rhetorical process, however, argumentation is governed by formal conditions of procedural justice-what Habermas calls "the ideal speech situation"-by which the rationally motivated attempt to reach agreement is protected from internal and external repression, and everyone has an equal chance to proffer reasons and rebuttals. As a dialectical procedure, argumentation is characterized by a "special form of interaction" in which validity claims can be hypothetically criticized independently of everyday pressures to succeed, so that interlocutors can recognize one another as sincere and rationally accountable. 13 THE MYTHIC VERSUS THE MODERN VIEW OF REALITY

The preliminary analysis of rationality purports to show that the rationality of an action is a function of the extent to which it can be justified. Actions either implicitly or explicitly raise validity claims to truth, moral rightness, appropriateness, sincerity, and comprehensibility. These claims refer to criticizable beliefs that, however tacit, are capable of being articulated in language. Linguistic utterances explic-

22

Rationality, Reality, and Action itly refer to items of experience-facts, norms, intentions, and so forth-that constitute the world in which action takes place. Without agreement about this world, social action would be impossible. Descriptions assert the truth of relations between datable, localizable things in an objective world. Prescriptions assert the rightness of obligations and norms that make up a social world. Expressive utterances assert the sincerity of intentions, desires, and feelings-the dispositions of the speaker's subjective world. And evaluations assert the social appropriateness of the speaker's subjective value preferences. In critically evaluating the rationality of descriptive, prescriptive, expressive, and evaluative utterances, one must have recourse to items of reference in three different worlds. 14 The relation between referentiality and rationality is decisive for Habermas's comparison of modern and mythic ways of understanding. He is especially concerned to show that the modern, decentered understanding of the world uniquely merits the title of rationality, because it makes possible the most extensive and progressive form of learning. This concern is provoked by cultural relativists who argue that occidental rationality merely reflects the peculiar standpoint of scientific culture and is therefore neither preferable to, nor more valid than other forms of understanding. Habermas intends to refute this view by showing that the relativist cannot criticize rationalism without presupposing its superiority. He concurs with anthropologist Evans-Pritchard that the difference between mythic and modern thought is not one of formal logical aptitude. The Azande, Evans-Pritchard notes, are just as capable of drawing inferences and recognizing inconsistencies in reasoning as Westerners. If there is a difference, it resides in the fundamental conceptual grid in terms of which the two interpret the world. 15 Relying on the structuralist studies of "primitive" cultures undertaken by Levi-Strauss and Godelier, Habermas characterizes the mythic world as a seamless totality in which any one item of experience is metaphorically or metonymically associated with every other item through the binary relations of sameness and difference. In the words of Godelier, myth "constructs a giant maze of mirrors in which the opposing images of man and world are infinitely reflected in each other and the relations of nature and culture are continuously separated and united as in a prism." This associative nature of mythic understanding is diametrically opposed to the analytic sundering of objective, subjective, and social domains of reference fundamental to modern rationality. 16 The "confusion," as Habermas puts it, between objective and subjective reality is reflected in the mythic conceptualization of nature as

23

Rationality, Reality, and Action spirit (animism). Natural relations are not subsumed under the category of causality but are conceived as personal relations among unpredictable wills. The inner realm of subjective imagination is projected outward; dreams, for example, are regarded as possessing veridical, prognostic import. Conversely, because subjective and social realities are "naturalized" in such a way as to conceal their human origin, values and codes of conduct remain all but impervious to critical revision. Since personal identity is no more differentiated from society than society is from nature, behavior, too, is rigidly bound to stereotypical patterns whose origin is regarded as being located in the immutable order of the cosmos. 17 The concretizing aspect of mythic thought-that is, its inability to abstract or distinguish general attributes of things from the things themselves-is symptomatic of its associative modus operandi. The confusion of objective and social hature explains, for example, the curious hybrid nature of ritual magic, which combines an instrumental understanding of cause and effect (teleological action) with incantations, invocations, and supplications of the sort found in interpersonal communication. The fusion of semantic and causal relations is evident in even the simplest acts of denotation and explanation: names, for example, are said to possess the powers of the things to which they refer. The ethical and practical implications of concretization are particularly striking. Since intentions and motives are not sharply distinguished from the consequences of actions, instrumental failures are occasions for assessing moral blame. Validity and efficiency remain undifferentiated. In the final analysis, the binary categories of mythic thought must be seen as stemming from the reciprocity structures of kin systems and relations of exchange, from the ambivalence of active agency and passive nature, and above all, from the need to explain away the powerlessness of the individual in the face of a capricious world. 18 As recounted above, the mythopoeic understanding of reality seems deficient and irrational in comparison to our own. Habermas argues that the confusion of domains of reference and the lack of reflexivity inherent in mythopoeic understanding have also been observed in infants and juveniles in so-called advanced Western societies. Although he is cognizant of the concerns voiced by Steven Lukes, Peter Winch, and others who defend the historicist position regarding the dangers of ethnocentrism, he argues that ethnocentrism can be combated only by assuming the superiority of the modern standpoint. Lukes observes that to understand the meaning of behavior requires that one refrain from prejudging it in light of one's own stan24

Rationality, Reality, and Action dards of rationality. But this principle of charity commits one to accepting the standards of natives as no less valid than one's own. Habermas does not dispute the methodological importance of the charity principle; since the meaning of an action is logically related to the reasons for undertaking it, its explication will necessarily appeal to standards of normalcy (rationality) indigenous to that culture. Furthermore, he recognizes that mythic knowledge and standards of conduct may be more functional than their modern counterparts in preserving cultures with relatively simple needs. But these considerations in no way rule out the possibility of ranking forms of understanding logically. 19 The problem confronting the non-historicist is that of coming up with an inventory of criteria that would be ideally valid for all cultures-a futile undertaking according to Winch, whose social theory is inspired chiefly by the linguistic philosophy of the late Wittgenstein, according to whom the limits of one's language determine the limits of one's world. "Language games" delimit acceptable conduct while cognitively filtering possibilities for understanding reality. Insofar as they present differing but similarly valid perspectives of a single reality, they are less like true or false propositions and more like right or left profiles of portraits. Armed with this conception of language, Winch attacks Evans-Pritchard's claim that the modern view of the world is more rational than the mythic view of the Azande. 20 Habermas objects to Winch's analogy between portraits and linguistic world views on the grounds that the cognitive worth of a world view is properly conceived as a function of the number of true assertions that it is capable of generating, rather than its picturing capacity. As Evans-Pritchard notes, the witchcraft of the Azande issues in contradictory oracles that seldom materialize, thereby indicating inadequate criteria for truth claims. When pressed, the Azande themselves admit to finding their oracles dubious, yet such absurdities abound in their world view. 21 Even if it is inappropriate to construe the Azande world view as a quasi-scientific theory that seeks to put forward testable predictions, one can still criticize it, pace Robin Horton, because, by refusing to countenance alternative modes of explanation, it precludes any critical self-evaluation whatsoever and thus prevents any progressive acquisition of knowledge. 22 Winch has responded to these objections by noting that the worth of a world view cannot be measured solely in terms of its capacity to promote instrumental knowledge. It depends also on the extent to which it makes sense of the truly universal, existential experiences of birth, death, sickness, guilt, love, solidarity, and loneliness. A mythic

25

Rationality, Reality, and Action world view possessing an abundance of religious and aesthetic meaning may offer more to its adherents than the disenchanted world view of modernity offers us. To hold the Azande to the standards of logical consistency characteristic of modern thinking is to misclassify their beliefs as explanatory theories and to misrepresent the people as pressing their ways of thinking about witches to a point at which they would be involved in contradictions. 23 Habermas accepts Winch's argument as a valid criticism of the kind of scientistic ethnocentrism that limits rationality to the cognitiveinstrumental domain, but he rejects his identification of happiness (aesthetic harmony) with rationality. Horton, by contrast, operates with a communicative conception of rationality that stresses the importance of critical reflection and dialogical openness for learning. Habermas appeals to this model to show that the relativist is implicated in a kind of bad faith when· the world view defended as no less rational than the modern one does not permit the openness and reciprocity acknowledged to be necessary for real understanding. 24 The contrast between closed and open world views provides the key to Habermas's defense of the superior rationality of the modern view. To be sure, the force of his argument is qualified by the fact that one is committed to recognizing certain standards of rationality only if one takes dialogue and argumentation seriously. The tu quoque strategy, in other words, does not show that the discursive attitude is unconditionally valid. 25 To justify the claim of the modern understanding of reality to universal validity, Habermas must show that it is logically superior in learning potential to mythopoeic and religiousmetaphysical world views. But this task requires nothing less than a systematic theory of social evolution. Habermas's theory takes the observed stages of learning and arranges them hierarchically so that higher phases logically presuppose and incorporate lower ones, thereby constituting a cumulative advance in learning potential. It also distinguishes empirical learning mechanisms and contingent boundary conditions from the sequential logic of structures. Whereas the historical teleologies implicit in, for example, Hegel's philosophy of spirit and some orthodox Marxist interpretations of historical materialism construe historical events as the inevitable, irreversible outcome of a prior developmental logic, Habermas' s theory of social evolution, like Kant's universal history, binds actual developmental advances and regressions to contingent his tori cal praxis. 26 The theory accomplishes two things. First, by assuming isomorphism between phylogenesis (social evolution) and ontogenesis (individual maturation) and accepting the empirical claim advanced by

26

Rationality, Reality, and Action Piaget, Kohlberg, and other structural psychologists that "every child who passes from one (cognitive or sociomoral) stage of thought to the next can be brought by maeutic means to explain why his or her way of judging things is now able to solve given problems better than at the previous stage," 27 it enables Habermas to justify the privileged rationality of modern thought. Second, it provides structural reference points for social critique that explain why modern societies are unable to solve their economic and administrative problems. 28 At this juncture, Habermas is less concerned with elaborating the details of his theory than with articulating its general contours, especially those bearing on Piaget's genetic structural account of child maturation. Piaget's theory concentrates on those structures of thought and action by which children gradually learn to adapt to an objective world of things and to a social world of norms, relationships, and people. Cognitive and moral development involve acquiring the capacity to decenter one's understanding of reality away from an egocentric perspective and see things from another person's point of view. This process of decentration, Habermas contends, also underlies social evolution. Although he is cognizant of the imperfect fit between ontogenesis and phylogenesis, he steadfastly insists that there are "abstract reference points" for comparing ego development and world view development. 29 Indeed, the internally related cognitive, linguistic, and moral-practical"structures of consciousness" that comprise world views are nothing more than repositories of individually acquired learning abilities that have become embedded in culture. 30 Using Piaget's research as a base, Habermas distinguishes four stages of child development. At the symbiotic stage, children are incapable of distinguishing themselves as corporeal subjects from primary reference persons (that is, parents) and the physical environment. At the egocentric stage, they are able to differentiate themselves from the environment but not yet to distinguish between physical and social reality, and they continue to perceive and judge situations solely from their own, body-bound perspective. Once children begin to initiate concrete operations and to distinguish perceptible and manipulable things and events from understandable subjects and actions, they enter the sociocentric stage. By the seventh year they are typically able to distinguish subjective fantasies and impulses from objective perceptions and social obligations. With the onset of adolescence there begins a universalistic stage of development, in which they are able to reflect critically on existing values and assumptions in light of hypothetical alternatives, thereby breaking out of the parochial constraints of tradition. 31

27

Rationality, Reality, and Action Applying this model to social evolution, Habermas speculates that the transition from mythopoeic to cosmological, religious, metaphysical, and modern forms of understanding likewise exhibits a moral and cognitive decentering. The mythic world view collapses objective and subjective reality into a collective, totemic identity in much the same way that objective and social domains of reference merge in the subjective world of the child. With the transition from archaic to developed civilizations (Hochkulturen), a decisive rupture occurs, and narrative accounts are replaced by explanations that can be justified through argument. Monotheistic religions subsume reality under a single, unifying principle, thereby exhibiting a strong impulse toward universalism and logical consistency. Although the Judea-Christian and Greco-Roman heritages gave rise to legal and theoretical innovations that paralleled the moral and cognitive structures typical of the universalistic stage of development, they retained religious and metaphysical residues redolent of less mature, precritical stages. With the advent of modernity, the highest principles (God, Being, or Nature) surrender their status as first principles to the formal principles of discursive reason. 32 RATIONALITY, ACTION AND REFERENCE

We have already noted that a person can be said to act rationally only if he or she is guided by justifiable beliefs of a factual, normative, evaluative, or expressive nature. Validity claims refer beliefs to various domains of reality; claims to truth refer to the world of spatiotemporal objects, claims to rightness and justice to the world of social norms, and claims to sincerity and authenticity to the world of a person's own feelings and desires. The connection between validity claims and objective, social, and subjective domains of reference becomes clear once the types of statements that articulate these claims are examined. Thus, part of the very meaning of a descriptive statement-indeed, that part of it which is explicitly intended-depends on a referential relationship between the statement and some spatiatemporal entity. The relationship between meaning, reference, and intentionality has been of great interest to philosophers since Brentano and has been taken up by Habermas in greater detail in his theory of language. Here it suffices to note that, for Habermas, action-as distinct from mere corporeal movements and operations-is inherently meaningful, because it expresses an agent's intentions vis-a-vis reality. This is important, because some philosophers and social behaviorists have attempted to explain the meaning of action in purely op-

28

Rationality, Reality, and Action erational terms, with no reference to the intentionality, or meaninggiving activity, of the agent. But, severed from an intentional relationship to objective, social, and subjective reality, action loses whatever cognitive, normative, and expressive content would accrue to it and can no longer be evaluated critically. 33 Habermas's discussion of the three worlds, or referential domains, underlying meaningful action was largely inspired by I. C. Jarvie's application of Popper's theory of three worlds to sociology. Popper's distinction of three worlds-of physical objects, subjective events, and objective thought contents-was intended as an ontological distinction among different kinds of entities. The major strength of Popper's model, in Habermas's opinion, is its mediation of the first and second worlds by the third world of objective spirit. The entities that inhabit the third world are symbolic creations in the broadest sense: social institutions, works of art, scientific theories, languages, machinery, and implements. Though they are themselves products of the subjective thought processes of individuals, once they have become embedded in an objective substrate, they take on a life of their own, tacitly harboring problems whose existence is prior to, and independent of, human agency. Insofar as the third world functions as an interpretative nexus of problematic concerns that conceptually structures the perception of objects and the discovery of causal uniformities, the relationship between subject and object is pragmatic and intentional. 34 Jarvie conceives the third world as the "social landscape" on which individuals map out optimal strategies for pursuing ends. The ideal meanings and values that comprise this map provide explicit guideposts, expressible in terms of truth claims, which agents use, more or less consciously, to orient themselves to persons and things around them. When these values and meanings no longer prove efficacious, they are revised in a critical process of truth testing. 35 Although application of the theory of worlds to social life marks an important advance in conceptualizing intentional action, it still conceives the interaction between subject, nature, and objective spirit instrumentally; cultural values are revealed to cognitive consciousness as objectifiable means for facilitating action that may be more or less successful but are neither morally right nor wrong. 36 This objectification of culture, Habermas contends, raises several problems. First, it obscures the distinction between performative and hypothetical-reflective attitudes toward culture. In everyday life, people coordinate their actions around definitions of situations that are taken for granted; only when there is dissension do the underlying meanings and values become objects of conversation. A hypothetical-reflective attitude toward cui-

29

Rationality, Reality, and Action ture may be implicit in everyday communicative action as an ideal limit, but it is approximated only in those institutionalized fields of endeavor encompassing the various arts and sciences. 37 By construing culture as an embodiment of propositional truth claims, Popper's model cannot explain the counterfactual power of culture to compel interaction. Habermas proposes the following emendations to Popper's theory. First, since each world is defined as the intentional correlate of a certain attitude-objectifying, valuating, or expressive-it designates a formal mode of schematization rather than a material classification of an object domain. The objective world of facts is no more to be confused with nature than the social world is to be equated with society or culture. Persons and norms can be regarded either as observable facts to be taken into consideration in a strategic calculation or as meaningful values commanding respect. Second, Habermas advocates a distinction between world (the domain of reference that is explicitly attended to) and lifeworld (the complementary background of preunderstandings). Third, rejecting the cognitive one-sidedness of Popper's model, Habermas refers the elements of the second and third worlds to validity claims other than truth, thereby allowing for legal and artistic, as well as scientific, domains of objective spirit. 38 The neo-Kantian division of validity claims, referential domains, and value spheres elaborated above grounds Habermas's division of social action into communicative, strategic, normative, and dramaturgic types. Like their Weberian prototypes, these categories must be understood as exemplifying certain features of action that normally occur together. Habermas defines teleological action as action undertaken by a single person who seeks to realize some goal. 39 He calls teleological action "strategic" when the decisions and behavior of at least one other person are included in a means-end calculation. 40 Teleological action is rational to the extent that a person calculates the most efficient means for bringing about the desired end. According to this model of rationality, actors in the strategic mode relate to other persons as objectifiable means or obstacles to the attainment of their aims. 41 Habermas characterizes normative action as social action in which the primary intention of the parties involved is to fulfill reciprocal expectations by conforming their behavior to shared norms and values. The pursuit of personal goals may then be overridden by social duties or canons of taste. 42 Those engaged in normative pursuits must also calculate the objective consequences of their actions for others of course. Prima facie, normative action is rational as long as it conforms to socially acceptable standards of conduct, but these standards must 30

Rationality, Reality, and Action advance the general interests of those affected if the action is to be rational in an ideal sense. 43 The third type of action mentioned by Habermas has as its principal aim self-presentation, or the projection of a public image. His introduction of the concept of dramaturgical action is chiefly inspired by Erving GoHman's pioneering use of theatrical role playing to illuminate social encounters. The term role playing here refers less to action in conformity with socially mandated forms of behavior than to the free, selective self-expression of one's own personality. 44 There is a sense in which even the simplest of actions is imbued with the personality of its agent. Conversely, every dramaturgic action is implicitly strategic, intended to elicit a desired response from an audience. In the theater of life it is assumed as a condition of mutual trust that the roles played by the actors are congruent with their true characters. Accordingly, for performances to be rational in a nonstrategic sense, they must be sincere, and the intentions expressed must be authentic-that is, they must not be ones about which the actor could be deceived. 45 The final, communicative category of action is, as one might expect, the most important one in Habermas' s work. Communicative action occurs when two or more persons expressly seek to reach voluntary agreement (Versti:indigung) on their situation for the sake of cooperating. Although persons relating to one another in other kinds of action may engage in communication for purposes of coordinating their efforts, they need not do so with the expressed aim of reaching an uncoerced settlement. Persons acting strategically, for example, may force others to comply with their aims by issuing commands, threats, lies, and other manipulative statements. Likewise, persons acting dramaturgically or normatively may use language without expressly intending to reach agreement over problematic claims. Since these kinds of action are distinguished from strategic action in tacitly presupposing some agreement over mutual expectations, they are sometimes classified by Habermas as subsidiary forms of communicative action. Properly speaking, however, communicative action involves an explicit concerted effort to reach agreement on the entire spectrum of validity claims (simultaneously thematizing all three domains of reference) and therefore transcends the other, more limited and less reflexive, types. Because "stability and univocity are ... exceptions in everyday practice," communicative action is always an immanent possibility. 46

31

CHAPTER THREE

Understanding and Language

ince the Positivismusstreit, the debate over the merits of sinnverstehen as a method of social research has taken new directions. Philosophers of science, led by Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend, and Hesse, have become increasingly disillusioned with the traditional boundaries separating the natural and the human sciences. Taking their cue from hermeneutics, they have argued that changes in scientific paradigms should not be acclaimed as indications of progress toward mirroring a mind-independent reality. Science interprets reality by setting forth data in a prior theoretical language. Because each paradigm describes its subject matter in a language that is incommensurable with other languages, there exists-so goes the most extreme version-no common standard of reality in terms of which the veridicality of competing paradigms could even be assessed. 1 Habermas's critique of positivism, by contrast, sharply distinguishes between natural and human sciences, which, because of their distinct cognitive interests, give rise to very different methodologies. Unlike the natural sciences, the social sciences are doubly hermeneutic, in that they not only subsume data under theoretical languages for purposes of explanation, but also interpret them as a means of gaining access to them. 2 For Habermas, "the same problematic of rationality that we run into in the investigation of sociological concepts of action reappears from another angle when we pursue the question concerning what it means to understand social action. The basic concepts of social action and methodology hang together. "3 The meaning of an action must be made comprehensible in light of the interpreter's own assumptions about rational conduct. Furthermore, it must be supposed that these assumptions about rationality are shared by agent and interpreter

S

32

Understanding and Language alike, for the rationale behind an action is essentially related to the kinds of reasons and arguments that the agent could marshal to justify it as the most appropriate thing to do under the circumstances. Suppose that we are trying to explain the behavior of a stockbroker who is bidding for shares. Such bidding is a means of maximizing gains and minimizing losses and approximates a strategic type of social action in that it considers the decisions of other persons in a means-ends calculation. Given an understanding of the rules governing the stock market that is shared by broker and interpreter alike, the interpreter constructs an ideal train of reasoning corresponding to the broker's action. In reconstructing the broker's rationale, he makes sense of the broker's action by showing that it was the reasonable thing to do under the circumstances. It is important to note that implicit in this process is a phase of critical evaluation, for the course of action undertaken by the broker is compared with the one that would have been undertaken by an ideally rational agent, and only if there is a reasonable correspondence can the action be said to be comprehensible. In the case of what appears to be irrational behavior, the interpreter's own assumptions about the intentions and circumstances underlying the broker's activity would have to be critically reexamined. If the preunderstanding of the situation bears up under close scrutiny, then the interpreter is entitled to judge the action as irrational. Perhaps the broker was remiss in following through the prescribed strategy, bungled the calculation, or neglected to include all relevant factors in making a decision. If expressed intentions do not jibe with behavior, the interpreter may be forced to consider the psychological disposition of the broker, but only after this impasse has been reached. 4 The same process of critical evaluation applies mutatis mutandis to normative, dramaturgical, and communicative types of action. Thus, one explains normative action by showing that it conforms to legitimately recognized norms which express generalizable interests. Should the action violate such norms or conform only to norms of doubtful legitimacy, there would be prima facie reasons for suspecting its rationality. This procedure is slightly more problematic in the case of dramaturgical action, in which the interpreter must first make sure that the action in question is not in fact strategic. Assuming that it is not, its meaning can be garnered from conventional patterns of expression and the person's past behavior. Only if the express intentions of the agent do not jibe with the observed behavior do we suspect that the action is strategic, insincere, or pathologically compelled. 5 It has been assumed that the interpreter and the agent share the 33

Understanding and Language same canons of rationality-a situation that might not obtain if the agent belongs to a different culture. In the case of an agent belonging to a culture that conflates distinct types of action, the would-be interpreter has three options: to refuse to conceive of the action as meaningful and treat it as brute behavior; to recur to depth-hermeneutic, structuralist, or developmental methodologies that attempt to establish an internal link between mythic and modern rationales surrounding psychosexual taboos, binary linguistic codes, or logical phases of learning; to interpret the action as if it were rationally motivated. Only the second option avoids the dual dangers of behaviorism and ethnocentrism. However, the social scientist must relinquish his privileged position vis-a-vis the native speaker when both have the same level of rational competency. 6 The interpreter then becomes a participant in communicative action who is accountable to native speakers/ For the participants of communicative action-including now the interpreter-the meaning of a situation is not arrived at until agreement is reached over the facts of the case, the operant normative expectations of the situation, or the sincerity of the speakers. But even when the speakers agree on terms, there is no guarantee against selfdeception, and hence the peculiar status of the social scientist as both participant and critic. 8 Habermas discusses the problematic role of the participant-critic in conjunction with phenomenological, ethnomethodological, and hermeneutical theories of understanding. Heading the list of theories is the perceptual theory of meaning developed by Hans Skjervheim. Skjervheim attempts to resolve the problem by appealing to a distinction between two kinds of attitudes: an objectifying attitude, which schematizes social life as a field of measurable facts, and a performative attitude, which schematizes it as a network of shared values and meanings. The social scientist, Skjervheim suggests, somehow manages to relate to utterances and actions in both modes simultaneously.9 Habermas does not find this convincing, for not only does Skjervheim fail to explain how the social scientist can achieve this dual stance, but the reduction of an action to an objective sequence of measurable movements and sounds would appear to suppress its meaning altogether. A better solution, Habermas maintains, is to conceive of the social scientist as a virtual participant who relates to two different frames of communicative action simultaneously. Whereas people engaged in communicative action seek mainly to coordinate their individual plans of action, social scientists seek only to understand what is going on. The communicative activity of the scientific community is motivated solely by a theoretical interest in reaching an unconstrained consensus, whereas that of social agents is motivated

34

Understanding and Language by a practical interest to succeed under less than pressure-free conditions. 10 But this account raises another problem, for, in reconstructing the meaning intended by the actors in accordance with ideal standards that are recognized by them only obscurely, if at all, isn't the interpreter twisting it? This caveat identifies the meaning of an action with the psychological intentions of its agent-a view that is challenged by ethnomethodology and philosophical hermeneutics. Ethnomethodology is indebted very largely to the phenomenological sociology of Alfred Schutz, who sought to ground the categories of social science in the everyday world. He correctly saw that the perspective of the disinterested observer is achieved by breaking away from the natural stance of a historically situated member of a society and assuming the attitude of the social scientist, who hypothetically brackets the validity of presuppositions that are normally taken for granted. 11 The problem of clarifying the phenomenological perspective was bequeathed to ethnomethodology, which is the study of the interpretative procedures (ethnomethods) by means of which actors negotiate a mutual understanding of their world. The profusion of incomplete utterances, as well as the high incidence of indexical and deictic terms (I, you, here, now, this, that, and so forth) in everyday conversation testifies to the importance of the lifeworld as the shared background against which utterances take on definite meaning. The continuity of the lifeworld over against the fragility and evanescence of negotiations is itself a product of these creative reinterpretations. However, as an active participant, the sociologist alters the context of social life, destroying the possibility of any neutral understanding. This fact may be used to good advantage when criticizing positivistic assumptions about the objectivity of statistical measurements and questionnaires, but it seems to undermine any hope for elaborating an objective theoretical framework. 12 Some ethnomethodologists, such as Harold Garfinkel, have attempted to remedy this situation by seizing on the structural invariances of speaker-hearer relationships. 13 Garfinkel follows Schutz and Husserl in holding that the individual phenomenologist gains an undiminished understanding of the true meaning of lived experience by suspending the performative attitude. Once the lifeworld of the interpreter's biographical ego has been "reduced" to the status of a purely immanent phenomenon of consciousness, a process of imaginative variation can be made to yield an eidetic intuition of necessary, universal structures. The problems of such a reduction were exhaustively detailed by Habermas in his earlier study of the logic of the social sciences. 14 For our purposes it suffices to note that aside from the enormous methodological diffi35

Understanding and Language culties attendant on bracketing presuppositions and confirming intuitions, the restriction of intentional analysis to the sphere of transcendental consciousness contradicts the cardinal ethnomethodological tenet that meaning is an intersubjective accomplishment grounded in contingent performative contexts. Phenomenological sociology, Habermas concludes, appears to set ideal structure against everyday performance. 15 In Habermas's judgment, it is philosophical hermeneutics that comes closest to articulating the sense in which ideal structures of rationality are located in everyday understanding. For Kuhlmann and Gadamer, understanding can only aspire to the status of an objective undertaking when it is conceived as a process of reaching agreement.16 This process is guided by what Gadamer calls an expectation of perfectibility (Vorgriff auf Vollkommenheit): the assumption that the text is a coherent whole embodyihg an ideal claim to validity. Corresponding to this expectation is the notion of an unlimited speech community representing an ideal consensus toward which all opposing interpretations of a text converge. The relationship between the ideal speech community and its historical permutations is essentially dialectical, everyday conversation activating a process of reflection that elevates it to the level of rational dialogue. 17 Habermas praises Gadamer' s understanding of the way in which ideal structures are reflectively generated within the historical processes they govern but voices reservations about his tendency to subordinate the critical moment opened up by the temporal distance separating the interpreter from the subject matter to the conservative moment of renewing the authority of tradition. He claims that Gadamer regards the interpreter as an actual participant in practical conversation, so that understanding tradition is equated with assenting to its validity and rationality in an ideal sense. By construing interpretation as an application (Anwendung) of a living truth to the practical concerns of the present, the conservative intention underlying the philological preservation of the classics, the juridical extension of legal precedent, and the theological proclamation of biblical authority is elevated to the rank of an ontological principle. 18 ACTION AND LANGUAGE

Although Habermas presents his theory of language as an intervening consideration (Zwischenbetrachtung) in his discussion of Weber's social theory, it is convenient to discuss it at this juncture, since it rounds out the metatheoretical analysis of rationality. Weber's theory of action involves an ambiguity that elucidates some of the problems

36

Understanding and Language associated with contemporary theories of meaning. In Weber's great posthumous work Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft social action is said to include any action that is meaningfully "oriented toward the behavior of others" or involves some reciprocity, such as mutual respect for private property. 19 If reciprocity is taken as the defining feature of social action, then social engagements of a relatively intransitory nature would presuppose at least some communicative agreement, and the meaning of action would accordingly refer to a public accomplishment rather than a private episode in the mind of the actor. However, Weber goes on to illustrate his theory of social action with several examples that are predominantly strategic in nature (including the case of two cyclists trying to avoid a collision). Moreover, his own descending ranking of social action-purposive-rational (Zweckrational), value-rational (Wertrational), affectual, and traditional-stresses the superior rationality of instrumental action, thereby prejudicing the interpretative enterprise in favor of a psychological divination of strategic intentions. The rational approach, by contrast, goes hand in hand with the theory of meaning developed in twentieth-century philosophy of language. 20 The organon model of linguistic signs introduced by Karl Buhler provides a convenient point of departure for Habermas's survey of linguistic philosophy. Buhler's semiotic analysis of language isolated three functions common to all signs: a cognitive function (the sign as symbol of reality), an expressive function (the sign as a symptom of the sender's inner experience), and an appellative function (the sign as a signal aimed at influencing the receiver's behavior). 21 What is required in addition to Buhler's semiotic analysis of isolated sign functions, Habermas maintains, is a syntactic analysis of rules governing the construction of well-formed sentences and a semantic analysis of the relationship between meaning and validity. Habermas believes that the theories of language developed by Carnap, Wittgenstein, Davidson, Dummet, Austin, and Searle have largely succeeded in remedying these deficiencies. Working within the formalist tradition, Carnap identified the sentence, not the isolated word, as the primary vehicle of meaning. He maintained that for sentences to be meaningful, they must satisfy formal rules of grammatical construction. Thus, meaning is held to be a function of the capacity of sentences to designate objective states of affairs. 22 The truth-conditional theories developed by Frege, early Wittgenstein, and more recently Davidson and Dummet are basically inspired by the same idea-namely, that the meaning of a sentence is reducible to the conditions under which it is true. The major contribution of truthconditional semantics is its recognition of the internal link between 37

Understanding and Language meaning and validity. Its major drawback, Habermas contends, is its tendency to assign linguistic meaning exclusively to the cognitive operation, thereby consigning expression and evaluation to the status of strategic devices for influencing behavior. 23 Habermas mentions two important movements that challenge this imbalance. The first, exemplified by Dummet's verificationist theory of meaning, exposes the limits of truth-conditional semantics from within. The old verificationist theory of meaning associated with the Vienna school assumed that the truth conditions of so-called protocol sentences about observable objects were amenable to conclusive testing. Dummet points out, however, that natural language abounds with meaningful statements about temporally and spatially inaccessible events that cannot be verified. He therefore recommends that the verificationist principle be reformulated in such a way that the verification of propositions comes to be seen as involving the proffering of counterfactual reasons. In Habermas's opinion, Dummet tacitly binds verification and meaning to the pragmatic conditions of formal argumentation, in which validity is also seen as a function of satisfying normative and expressive validity claims. 24 The tradition of ordinary language philosophy associated with Wittgenstein, Austin, and Searle is even more radical in its repudiation of classical truth-conditional semantics. For Wittgenstein, the meaning of sentences is tied to their use in everyday speech, or to be more precise, to rules specifying their socially acceptable usage. By tying meaning to rules governing social interaction, he inaugurated the transition from truth-conditional to communicative semantics. 25 Habermas' s universal pragmatics combines the communicative semantics of Wittgenstein, with its emphasis on the intersubjectively criticizable nature of utterances, and the functional semiotics of Buhler, which holds that every sign simultaneously combines representational, performative, and expressive functions. In earlier statements, Habermas sought to clarify this synthesis by appealing to the generative linguistics of Noam Chomsky and the speech-act theories of Austin and Searle. Chomsky attempts to reconstruct the "depth grammar," or necessary and universal formal-syntactic rules, underlying linguistic competence, the latter understood as an innate capacity to produce phonetically and semantically correct sentences. Habermas' s universal pragmatics is intended to carry out a similar program with respect to communicative competence, necessitated by the fact that the conditions for producing meaningful utterances are not reducible to the innate capacities of isolated speakers to form grammatical sentences but also involve mastering the performative 38

Understanding and Language rules of social interaction and the reciprocal role qualifications of speaker and hearer that are part of them. 26 Universal pragmatics aims at disclosing the universals of dialogue that a person must acquire in order to participate in a speech situation. The most important concern the use of performative verbs, which, unlike nonperformative verbs which facilitate the reporting of information, occur only in a speech setting, where they serve the exclusive purpose of proposing a social engagement. 27 Taking the speech-act theory of Austin as his point of departure, Habermas analyzes the kinds of assertion in which performative verbs occur (speech acts) in terms of a first-person expression addressed to a second-person direct object of the form "I promise (assure, request, know, etc.) that," followed by a propositional clause containing a referential term and a predicate. Habermas regards this standard form as properly depicting, if not the typical form of speech acts, at least their essential structure. Unlike Austin, who referred meaning exclusively to locutionary (propositional) content, Habermas endorses the view that the illocutionary, or performative force of speech action, no less than the locutionary content, constitutes a bona fide category of meaning. Together, these levels of meaning comprise a double structure, or dual intentionality, which is inherent in every speech act. At the illocutionary level, speech is guided by a performative attitude oriented toward an intersubjective relationship; at the locutionary level, by an objectifying attitude oriented toward a world of objects. These two levels are reflexively related to one another, the locutionary level referring to objective boundary conditions, the illocutionary level to conditions under which truthful reference and right action are agreed on. 28 Besides incurring social obligations and transmitting information about the objective world, speakers express their intentions. 29 The perlocutionary effects of such expressions of intention serve to coordinate action strategically; they are not announced explicitly in the utterance itself and are entirely dependent on the context. Although social action is often coordinated through perlocutionary effects, Habermas insists that communicative, not strategic, action is the principal medium of cooperation, since perlocutionary effects depend on a prior trust based on communicative expectations. A warning of impending danger, for example, can have the intended effect of frightening the hearer into a certain course of action only if the warning is taken seriously. After noting that speech acts simultaneously raise claims to truth, rightness, and sincerity, Habermas classifies them into four major

39

Understanding and Language groupings (see table 3.1). 30 Regulative speech acts, which explicitly raise a claim to rightness, prescribe, command, or proscribe. Expressive speech acts disclose the speaker's feelings, desires, and dispositions.31 Declarations and statements of intent, though referring to actions in the objective world, fundamentally raise claims to sincerity. Perlocutionary and power-backed imperative speech acts primarily raise claims to success or effectiveness. Unlike normatively authorized commands such as "No smoking on board the plane," which are regulative in nature, genuine commands openly declare the strategic intentions of the speaker in conjunction with some threat. Constative speech acts, which raise claims to truth, represent, describe, assert, or deny some objective state of affairs. 32 Habermas completes his analysis of the pure types of linguistically mediated interaction by relating his taxonomy of speech acts to his theory of social action. 33 The abstractness of his model r~ises serious doubts about its value for empirical research. Speech acts seldom occur in standard form; many are institutionally bound (nongeneralizable); actual conversations often combine strategic and communicative types; and people who are on good terms with one another sometimes forego speech when coordinating their actions. 34 Furthermore, it remains unclear why a formal pragmatic analysis of speech action is needed in the first place. 35 Although Habermas admits that many speech acts, especially those that approximate the institutionally unbound, ideal type, possess a meaning that can be captured literally in standard form, he concedes that there is always a residue of meaning that is exclusive to the particular context. 36 This need not be seen as casting aspersions on the theoretical reconstruction of those formal structures of rationality that govern the lifeworld as a whole. 37 Nevertheless, since it is undeniable that many of our communicative negotiations occur within institutionally bound settings circumscribed by legal sanctions and hierarchies of power, in which speakers are motivated to accept one another's offers on the basis of authority or custom or out of fear of punishment, the assertion that communicative action is logically linked to structures of rational discourse may seem odd. 38 Strictly speaking, institutionally bound speech acts such as arbitrating, contracting, marrying, and christening are either strategic in nature (as in the case of legally sanctioned arbitrations and contracts) or are embedded in ritualistic contexts governed by religious custom and civil authority (as in the case of marrying and christening). Institutionally unbound speech acts, by contrast, constitute a repertory of illocutionary offers that may appear in any context. 39 Unbound regulative, expressive, and constative speech acts, such 40

Table 3.1. Pure Types of Linguistically Mediated Interaction Functions of speech

Types of action

Characteristic speech acts

Strategic Action

Perlocutions Imperatives

Influencing one's opposite number

Oriented to success

Conversation

Constatives

Representation of states of affairs

Oriented to reaching understanding

Normatively regulated action

Regulatives

Establishment of interpersonal relations

Oriented to reaching understanding

Dramaturgical action

Expressives

Selfrepresentation

Oriented to reaching understanding

Action orientations

Basic attitudes

Validity claims

World relations

Objectivating

(Effectiveness)

Objective world

Objectivating

Truth

Objective world

Normconformative

Rightness

Social world

Expressive

Truthfulness

Subjective world

Adapted from Jiirgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1, trans. Thomas McCarthy. Introduction and translation copyright © 1984 by Beacon Press. Reprinted by permission of Beacon Press.

Understanding and Language as claiming to know something, promising, prescribing, expressing a desire, and so on, are those in which speakers premise their acceptance of one another's offers on the mutual expectation that the validity claims raised could be justified rationally. Consequently the rational accountability of everyday speakers is logically wedded to ideal conditions of discourse. This connection grounds Habermas's refutation of ethical skepticism by arguing that unconstrained social interaction carries with it a practical commitment to procedural justice that is not open to voluntary rejection or acceptance. The skeptic engaging in communicative action cannot repudiate this commitment without being convicted of either gross insincerity or outright inconsistency. Classical philosophy from Plato to Hegel regarded dialogic analysis as only one aspect of rationality, the other being an intuitive power of unification. Understood in its universalizing capacity, reason has certainly lost the prestige it once enjoyed as a method of speculative thought. Still, one wonders whether the restriction of rationality to the province of formal discourse is not purchased at the cost of practical reason. As Habermas admits, implicit in practical life is a prediscursive moment of hermeneutical reflection that crosses the formal boundaries separating cognition, action, and expression. It is related to an intuitive know-how, or preunderstanding of life in its totality, that enables us to generate an indefinite number of improvisations on the basis of a finite repertory of general rules. What Plato calls poesis-the metaphorical capacity to discern likenesses between heterogeneous experiences, to subsume diverse particulars under unitary ideas, or, what is the same thing, to generate novel applications out of a prior unity-has much in common with Aristotle's notion of phronesis, the application of general rules of conduct in everyday practice. Both involve art as well as taste-the mimetic emulation of exemplary models of speech and virtue that the Greeks took to be essential for the aesthetic cultivation of character. If this, the most substantial part of our practical lives, is to be accorded the dignity of reason, then Habermas' s provisional analysis of rationality will have to incorporate a countervailing moment of aesthetic reflection. 40

42

CHAPTER FOUR

Weber's Theory of Rationalization

t was with great irony that Weber and first-generation critical theorists concluded that the cage in which contemporary man, bereft of any cosmic meaning and moral dignity and subject to the impersonal whims of bureaucracy, ekes out his monotonous existence, was nothing less than the tragic fulfillment of an aspiration born in an age in which reason was still regarded as the universal guarantor of a kingdom of autonomous subjects. 1 What seems scandalous about this diagnosis today has less to do with its outright dismissal of "scientific progress" -a chimera of which we ought to have been thoroughly disabused anyway by now-than with its sweeping indictment of everything rational. Who, least of all a social scientist professing moral scruples, would dare cast doubt on his credentials as a practicing member of the free, enlightened community of Kulturmenschen? And yet Weber's "deconstruction" of reason-to paraphrase the paradox in contemporary jargon-is far from being the sort of innocent ruse that intellectuals delight in visiting upon themselves pour epater les bourgeois. It is the continuing allure of Weber's critique of rationality for neoconservatives and radicals alike that makes it of such vital concern to Habermas.

I

RATIONALITY

Weber uses the concept of rationality in a wide variety of contexts to refer to certain aspects of action, decision, and systematized world views. 2 As a feature of action, rationality may refer either to the purposive-rational calculation of ends with respect to given preferences (decision rationality) and efficient means (instrumental rationality) or to the value-rational "formulation of the ultimate values governing 43

Weber's Theory of Rationalization action and the consistently planned orientation of its detailed course to these values." 3 Sometimes Weber juxtaposes the cold formalism of pure purposive rationality, which always involves an impersonal and largely quantifiable calculation of consequences, with substantive, highly personal value-rational commitment, which is "determined by a conscious belief in the value for its own sake of some ethical, aesthetic, religious, or other form of behavior, independently of its prospects of success. " 4 However, when discussing the legitimating potential of value-rational, as distinct from affectual (emotionally motivated) and traditional (habitually motivated), types of action, or when addressing the "infinite number of possible value scales" for "substantive goal rationality," Weber strongly implies that pure value rationality consists in the logical deduction of practical maxims from universal-and to that extent formalizable or procedural-principles of equity and justice of the sort articulated, for example, in natural law. 5 It must be noted, of course, that Weber never went as far as to equate either natural law or an ethic of ultimate ends with purely procedural forms of rationality, nor could he have done so, given his unwavering belief in the subjective status of value commitments generally. 6 Rationality becomes a definitive feature of action only after it has been incorporated in personality structures, cultural interpretations, and social institutions/ Rationalizierung ("rationalization") is the term used by Weber to designate the process by which this transformation is brought about. At the risk of oversimplifying, one might say that cultural rationalization denotes a complex ensemble of events encompassing the progressive differentiation, formalization, and grounding (what Weber calls Wertsteigerung, "value intensification") of value-related spheres of activity, the most fundamental of these gravitating around the Kantian triad of truth (knowledge), right or goodness (morality and law), and beauty (art and taste). The distinctive features of secular culture-abstract art, science and technology, individualistic ethics and formal law-represent domains of inquiry that are guided by a single value. Corresponding to the growing emancipation (Verselbstiindigung) of each value sphere from the constraints imposed by their former amalgamation under unitary religious world views is a parallel process of self-reflection whereby each form of inquiry is grounded with respect to its own peculiar principles.8 If experimental method is the purposive-rational quintessence of scientific cognition, universalizability would seem to be the heart and soul of value-rational pursuits in the normative field of ethics, politics, and jurisprudence undertaken in the name of justice. In the West, cultural rationalization was synonymous with the sec-

44

Weber's Theory of Rationalization ularization of the Judea-Christian world view. Weber is careful to point out that secularization encompassed much more than the systematic elaboration of this world view into a consistent cosmology, for the disenchantment (Entzauberung) of nature as a purely objective setting for humanity's redemption vis-a-vis a transcendent ethical deity-the feature that ostensibly sets the Judea-Christian tradition apart from its Asiatic counterparts-already prefigured a differentiation of cognitive, practical, and aesthetic value spheres. Secularization must therefore be construed as the great liberating force that paved the way for modern, "emancipated" society. Just as the development of technology enabled entrepreneurs and administrators to conduct their respective activities on the basis of impersonal calculations independent of religious and moral considerations, so too the liberation of art from the dominion of the Church hastened its entry into the marketplace, thereby permitting untrammeled pursuit of materialistic ideals. By the end of the nineteenth century, !'art pour !'art became the rallying cry for an avant-garde counterculture that had all but rejected naturalistic, market-oriented conventions in favor of abstract styles of expression based on highly refined techniques. 9 But the single most decisive event paving the way for modern society was undoubtedly the separation of ethics and law from one another and from religious custom (Sittlichkeit). By elevating faith above "good works" in the achievement of personal salvation, the Reformation succeeded in translating diffuse inner feelings into what later became an individualistic ethic of conscience and responsibility. Conceptions of moral autonomy also figured in social contract theories of law, for, by shifting the burden of political legitimation from traditional authority to formal procedures of consent, such theories increasingly made the serving of justice an impartial affair. This is reflected in both the delegation of authority for the enactment, application, and execution of statutory law to officeholders who have attained their position through election, appointment, examination, or some other impersonal means and in constitutional limits to the exercise of authority itself. The accountability of office-holders and, therewith, the judgment of their policies in terms of their effectiveness in serving the commonweal, was further augmented by the establishment of democratic institutions embodying rules of procedural justice. 10 The rational core of Judea-Christian culture can be fully articulated only within the institutional confines of universities, academies, and professional organizations, all of which require public recognition. Society undertakes to subsidize these costly ventures only when the potential for rationalization embedded in culture is infused into per45

Weber's Theory of Rationalization sonal motivations and social orders. Corresponding to this phase of cultural institutionalization or social rationalization is a process of differentiation, formalization, and grounding that in many respects parallels that discussed above. In modern-which for Weber means capitalist-society, the economy, the state, and private households are segregated into relatively autonomous domains with their own distinctive values. With the institutionalization of private property and contractual law, a market economy comes into being whose primary organizational unit, the business firm, disposes over purposiverational methods of accounting, management, and production in the calculated pursuit of profit. The organizational core of the modern state, the bureaucratic administration, uses the same techniques of rational accounting and management to secure its monopoly over the use of force in maintaining law and order. Both government and business administration are regulated internally by formal procedures for delegating authority, processing information, and organizing the flow of communication from department to department within an overall economy of efficiency, though in the former the purposiverational exercise of power remains circumscribed by considerations of legitimacy. 11 The nuclear family, by contrast, is the vehicle by which value-rational orientations are instilled in the individual personality. In Weber's view, the most important normative factor shaping the consciousness of Western civilization is the Protestant work ethic, which combines an acquisitive, purposive-rational orientation toward success with value-rational sentiments concerning individual responsibility and familial-occupational loyalty, thereby forming the basis of that "methodical" life-style peculiar to vocationalism. Emerging as a reaction to this ascetic emphasis on self-improvement through hard work is a competing life-style that embodies the hedonistic values commonly associated with an artistic counterculture. 12

THE EMERGENCE OF MODERN STRUCTURES OF CONSCIOUSNESS

The fundamental question animating Weber's inquiry can be formulated accordingly: Why does the developmental logic inherent in all religious world views reach its zenith only in the Judea-Christian tradition? Weber addresses the cultural rationalization of religious world views in his comparative study of the three great world religions: Confucianism/Taoism, Hinduism/Buddhism, and Judaism/Christianity. In keeping with his dual materialist-idealist method of explanation, Weber sought to trace the emergence of these religions back to 46

Weber's Theory of Rationalization the theodicy problematic, which is concerned first and foremost with cosmic justice and key existential experiences centering on human mortality. 13 Weber classifies the major world religions with respect to how they treat the theodicy problem. Judaism and Christianity, exemplifying the theocentric strategy, posit the existence of a personal deityvariously characterized in anthropomorphic and abstract termswho exists independently of the created world. Suffering is interpreted as a fall from grace, salvation as a gift from God. The ethos of the Judea-Christian world view requires action in accordance with divine moral commands. Oriental religions, by contrast, conceive salvation as participation in a cosmic order and eschew action in favor of knowledge, thus resonating more with the life experiences of Mandarin bureaucrats (Confucianism) and beggar monks (Buddhism) than with those of the masses. 14 Weber also classifies world religions with respect to their evaluations of the world. Confucianism and Taoism affirm the "here and now" and therefore advocate a life-style of passive acquiescence to the status quo. Judaism and Christianity and Buddhism and Hinduism posit a dualism between the temporal world and ultimate reality and accordingly advocate active transcendence of the former in thought and action. For Weber, a religion's potential for rationalization depends on its capacity to represent phenomenal reality objectively, as pure nature, or ethically, as a realm of ultimate ends. He contends that only the Judea-Christian world view possesses an internal structure that both sets objective nature against ethical teleology, thereby forcing a turn inward, and represents a transcendent imperative governing the resolution of social conflict. Denial of the world is necessary, but not sufficient, for ethical rationality, and the contemplative "flight from reality" characteristic of the Hindu and Buddhist response to the cleavage between existence and essence is a withdrawal from, not a mastery of, moral conflict. The demythologization of nature and the subsumption of social action under a moral order condition one another. Habermas accepts most of Weber's sociology of religion but regrets its neglect of theoretical intuition as a necessary condition for cognitive rationalization. Weber surmised that religions with cosmocentric, world-affirmative world views possessed the least potential for rationalization, but in fact, it was within the cradle of Greek religion that bios theoretikos was born. Taken separately, neither Greek nor Judea-Christian world views possess the structural prerequisites necessary for ethical and cognitive rationalization. It is Habermas' s belief that it was the confluence of these two world views in Europe during

47

Weber's Theory of Rationalization the High Middle Ages that provided the catalyst responsible for the rise of experimental science and the Protestant workethic. 15 THE LEGAL AND ETHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF RATIONALISM: WEBER'S DIAGNOSIS OF THE PRESENT

Weber's book The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism provides the bridge between the analysis of cultural rationalization given above and the media by which it is invested in social institutions. In it he sought to explain how the occasional profiteering of economic adventurers that had existed throughout history could have become institutionalized in a market system supported by a methodical, vocational life-style. He traced this development to an "elective affinity," or structural attraction, between the ascetic life-style of members of certain Protestant sects and the 'methodical life-style of entrepreneurs, an attraction rooted in the psychological need for confidence in one's own salvation and self-improvement through hard work. 16 In his study of modern law, Weber stressed the parallel emancipation of individual moral conscience from ethical custom. For the first time ever, civil law appears as something posited, the legitimacy of which is tied to notions of sovereign consent (the social contract) institutionalized in democratic rules of procedural justice. It no longer requires the adoption of any particular moral or religious attitude, but only outward compliance with respect to behavior. In other words, it procures a realm of individual freedom in which it is permitted to do anything that is compatible with a like freedom for others. 17 Our sketch of rationalization so far has focused on its liberating effects. Scientists, artists, jurists, administrators, and members of the business community are relatively free to ply their respective trades unencumbered by religious constraints. But although freedom of conscience is now protected from social and political encroachment, it comes to play an increasingly marginal role in everyday life. Even the desire for a meaningful view of the cosmos would seem to have been progressively satisfied by the success of modern science. Yet Weber's diagnosis of modernity reveals precisely the reverse phenomenon: an ineluctable erosion of freedom and meaning. The logical move would be to try to blame these disturbances on factors other than rationalization, but Weber, strangely, declines to take this path. He maintains that loss of meaning in the wake of the disintegration of religious world views into opposed "ultimate ideas" is inevitable, since a logical contradiction necessarily ensues, compelling the corresponding orders of life to "drift into tension with one another." The explanatory poverty of science is merely the most glaring

48

Weber's Theory of Rationalization manifestation of rational differentiation and specialization. As he rather ingenuously remarks, "Wherever rational empirical knowledge has consistently brought about the disenchantment of the world and its transformation into a causal mechanism, a definitive pressure arises against the claims of the ethical postulate that the world is a divinely ordered, that is, somehow ethically meaningful cosmos." 18 If science is incapable of addressing our existential concerns-of answering what, for Tolstoy, is the only important question: What shall we do and how shall we live?-then this must be taken as symptomatic of a deep fragmentation of reason into irreconcilable value spheres. Scientific pleading is meaningless in principle because the various value spheres of the world stand in irreconcilable conflict with each other.... And since Nietzsche, we realize that something can be beautiful, not only in spite of that aspect in which it is not good, but rather in that very aspect. You will find this expressed earlier in the Fleurs du Mal, as Baudelaire named his poems. It is commonplace to observe that something may be true although it is not beautiful and not holy and not good. Indeed, it may be true in precisely those aspects. But all these are only the most elementary cases of struggle that the gods of the various orders and values are engaged in. I do not know how one might wish to decide 'scientifically' the value of French and German culture; for here too, different gods struggle with one another, now and for all times to come. 1'

Intrepidly pursuing this line of argument, Weber concludes that what applies to each of the major spheres of value applies equally well to the sciences; the values of technical efficiency, health, and justice that respectively authorize physics and chemistry, medicine, and jurisprudence "can by no means be proved." In other words, no scientific appeal to facts or consequences can answer the question of "whether the existence of these cultural phenomena have been and are worth while." 20 In the face of scientific demands for rational justification, all values, including those of science itself, are devalued as meaningless. Weber is convinced that the world must "appear fragmentary and devalued in all those instances when judged in the light of the religious postulate of a divine 'meaning' of existence. This devaluation results from the conflict between the rational claim and reality, between the rational ethic and the partly rational, and partly irrational values. " 21 It is not the least bit surprising that the main casualty of the rational devaluation of values turns out to be the ethics of responsibility and its principle of universal reciprocity. The extension of one's "brethren" to encompass the whole of humanity was already undermined by the purposive-rational thrust of the Protestant ethic. "Puritanism,"

49

Weber's Theory of Rationalization Weber remarks, "accepted the routinization of the economic cosmos . . . . This meant in principle to renounce salvation as a goal attainable by man, that is, by everybody. It meant to renounce salvation in favor of the groundless and always only particularized grace (Gnadenpartikularismus)."21 He then shows that the value-rational substance of the Protestant ethic is also incompatible with political, aesthetic, erotic, and intellectual spheres of life. The use of violence in territorial pursuits can no more abide by the tenets of such an ethic than can the demand for artistic freedom in the name of subjective sovereignty, the glorification of the purely sensual, or the cosmopolitan relativization of values by connoisseurs of culture (Kulturmenschen). With the withering away of religious sentiment, Weber believed that the value-rational aspect of a principled ethic would be eclipsed by the purposive-rational demands of ascetic vocationalism. "Limitation to specialized work, with a renunciation of the Faustian universality of man which it involves, is a condition of any valuable work in the modern world; hence deeds and renunciation necessarily accompany each other." 23 The loss of freedom entailed in such renunciation is most telling for the professional bureaucrat, who "is only a single cog in an ever-moving mechanism which prescribes to him an essentially fixed route of march. " 24 Paradoxically, the mechanization and dehumanization of office life in which decisions are imposed from the top down owe their raison d' etre to legal formalization and democratization. As Weber points out, "the position of all 'democratic' currents, in the sense of currents that would minimize 'authority"' -bureaucratic authority included-is "necessarily ambiguous" :25 Equality before the law and the demand for legal guarantees against arbitrariness demand a formal and rational "objectivity" of administration, as opposed to the personally free discretion flowing from the "grace" of the old patrimonial domination. If, however, an "ethos"-not to speak of instincts-takes hold of the masses on some individual question, it postulates substantive justice oriented toward some concrete instance and person; and such an "ethos" will unavoidably collide with the formalism and rulebound and cool matter-of-factness of bureaucratic administration. 26

Though formal law and bureaucracy impose an unfreedom of their own-and it need hardly be mentioned that Weber was acutely sensitive to the "injustices" perpetrated on "the propertyless masses" by a system of formal law-any attempt to reinstate "popular justice" based on substantive ethical principles of social democracy "crosses the rational course of justice and administration just as strongly. as the 'star chamber' proceedings of an 'absolute' ruler. 27

50

Weber's Theory of Rationalization Bureaucracy may be the most obvious example of the renunciation exacted by rational asceticism, but it is not the driving force that sustains it. For, lurking behind the "specialist without spirit" (Fachmenschen ohne Geist) is the proverbial "sensualist without heart" (Genussmenschen ohne Herz), and herein is revealed that mutual affinity between ceaseless toil and insatiable consumption that is so pervasive in capitalist society. The irrational confluence of asceticism and consumerism is brilliantly captured by Weber in the memorable denouement of the Protestant Ethic: The Puritan wanted to work in a calling; we are forced to do so .... In Baxter's view the care for external goods should only lie on the shoulders of the saint "like a light cloak, which can be thrown aside at any moment." But fate decreed that the cloak should become an iron cage .... Since asceticism undertook to remodel the world and to work out its ideals in the world, material goods have gained an increasing and finally inexorable power over the lives of men as at no previous period in history. Today the spirit of religious asceticism-whether finally, who knows?-has escaped from the cage. But victorious capitalism, since it rests on mechanical foundations, needs the support no longer. 2'

Thus, value-rational orientations continue to recede in importance until "the pursuit of wealth, stripped of its religious and ethical meaning ... become[s] associated with purely mundane passions." Habermas does not dispute Weber's observation that Western society has witnessed a progressive erosion of meaning and freedom, and he concedes that some of this is undoubtedly the result of cultural and social rationalization. Feelings of alienation and despair invariably follow demythologization, mechanization of production, and bureaucratization, regardless of the degree to which the latter accompany a rational increase in moral and cognitive learning capacity. But, for Habermas, the loss of freedom and meaning engendered by these developments is more than compensated by the enhancement of individual autonomy vis-a-vis tradition and by the emergence of new possibilities of meaning as a result of modern art and the democratic ethos of communicative humanism. 29 Moreover, insofar as this process is at all pathological, it is the result of a one-sided selective institutionalization of rationality-what Habermas calls the "colonization of the lifeworld" -that stems from the peculiar dynamics of advanced capitalism. The path to a clear understanding of social pathology is closed to Weber because of the metatheoretical and methodological narrowness of his approach. First, Habermas contends, Weber conflates rational society with capitalism. In his study of world religions, he distinguishes between the necessary and universal features intrinsic to

51

Weber's Theory of Rationalization any process of cultural rationalization and the specific, historical forms that such a logical potential has assumed in the course of social institutionalization. But this distinction becomes blurred in his later analysis of the religious and juristic roots of capitalism. Second, Habermas maintains that Weber's inability to escape the tendrils of philosophy of consciousness and its postulation of an opposition between subject and object led him to mistake purposive rationality for reason tout court. Lacking an understanding of the communicative basis of formal reciprocity or democratic procedural justice, he quite naturally concluded that value rationality and its correlative mode of political legitimation would eventually be overshadowed along with the religious ethic to which it was substantively linked. 30 Third, by prematurely rejecting sociological functionalism as a naturalistic aberration, Weber was forced to restrict his sociological explanation to the action-theoretical plane of sinnversrehen. But Habermas contends that to focus narrowly on the agent's subjective understanding of his or her action, including whatever cynicism he or she may entertain about the meaningfulness and freedom-enhancing virtues of the values that the action embodies, gives the impression that cultural rationalization itself is responsible for social pathology and altogether neglects those unintended (and uninterpretable) consequences of action resulting from the irrational functioning of economy and state. A bilevel model of society incorporating a systems-theoretical analysis of these objective constraints would properly reinstate the source of social pathology in a contradiction between the action-theoretical (communicative) infrastructure of a meaningfullifeworld and the systems-theoretical (functional) goals of a managed capitalist economy. As Habermas notes, Weber's late essays "Politics as a Vocation" and "Science as a Vocation" and the famous Zwischenbetrachtung included among the studies on sociology of religion, "Religious Rejections of the World and Their Directions," convey the impression that the loss of freedom is logically entailed by the loss of meaning. In the Zwischenbetrachtung, Weber connects each of the three cultural value spheres (cognitive, normative, and aesthetic) with corresponding interest positions, or orders of life, that regulate the possession of ideal goods (science/knowledge, religion/morality, and art/taste) and material goods (economy/wealth, politics/power, counterculture/ love). 31 The resulting conflict between the religious ethic of love of neighbor and the other orders of life is attributed not to particular, nonrational value preferences (contents), but to the logical irreducibility of universal, rationalizable value spheres (formal structures). So construed, none of the three rationality complexes is capable of exerting a structure-building influence on society as a whole; as a conse-

52

Weber's Theory of Rationalization quence, value-rational orientations are entirely uprooted from their religious base and are replaced by instrumental and hedonistic modes of conduct. The resulting loss of freedom is in part symptomatic of the disappearance of moral autonomy (in the Kantian sense), but, to complete the image of society as an iron cage, Weber must further assume that modern law can be detached from natural law, its legitimating anchor, and can be rationalized in accordance with the instrumentallogic of statutory proceduralism. What emerges is a model of selective rationalization in which society, culture, and personality are overburdened with integration problems while at the same time being threatened with absorption into the combined economic-bureaucratic apparatus. Habermas does not deny that the freedom to adopt differing attitudes toward the three domains of reality "can become a source of conflict as soon as different cultural value spheres simultaneously penetrate the same institutional domains, so that rationalization processes of different types compete with one another in the same place." He adds, however, that "cognitive-instrumental, moral-practical, and aesthetic-expressive orientations of action ought not to become so independently embodied in antagonistic orders of life that they overburden the personality system's average capacity for integration and lead to permanent conflicts between lifestyles." 32 The paradoxical conclusion that such conflicts are logically necessitated by cultural rationalization stems from confusing the particular contents of cultural traditions with those universal standards of value. This confusion is especially apparent in "Science as a Vocation," in which Weber compares "the most elementary cases of struggle that the gods of the various orders and values are engaged in" -namely, between truth, goodness, and beauty-with the problem of deciding "scientifically" the relative worth of French as opposed to German culture. Even more revealing is the passage alluded to earlier in which Weber underscores the irrationality of all vocations: Whether life is worth living and when-this question is not asked by medicine. Natural science gives us an answer to the question of what we must do if we wish to master life technically. It leaves quite aside ... whether we should and do wish to master life technically . . . . Consider a discipline such as aesthetics .... It does not raise the question whether or not the realm of art is perhaps a realm of diabolical grandeur ... in its core hostile to God and, in its innermost and aristocratic spirit, hostile to the brotherhood of man .... Consider jurisprudence. It establishes what is valid according to the rules of juristic thought, which is partly bound by logically compelling and partly by conventionally given schemata. Whether there should be law and whether we should establish just these rules-such

53

Weber's Theory of Rationalization questions jurisprudence does not answer. ... Consider the historical and cultural sciences. They teach us how to understand and interpret political, artistic, literary, and social phenomena in terms of their origins. But they give us no answer to the question, whether the existence of these cultural phenomena have been and are worthwhile. 33

Habermas's interpretation of this passage merits further scrutiny, since it provides unique insight into the problems besetting his own theory. Of all the vocations mentioned above, only medicine, Habermas submits, articulates a particular value content. Here we have a case of the value-oriented application of natural scientific knowledge, that is, of the rationalization of services in the framework of a professional practice that, as the practice of healing, is directed to a specific value content-the health of patients. Empirically, this value is almost universally accepted; nevertheless, it is a, matter of a particular pattern of values that is by no means internally connected with one of the universal validity claims. This is, of course, not true of medicine as a scientific discipline; qua research it is oriented not to particular values but to questions of truth. The situation is similar with aesthetics and jurisprudence insofar as they are considered as scientific disciplines. These disciplines can also be transposed into professional practices, for example, aesthetics into art criticism, jurisprudence into the administration of justice or legal journalism. They thereby become components of cultural systems of action: the artistic enterprise or the administration of justice. These systems, however, unlike the professional practice of medicine, are not oriented to particular values, such as "health" but to systems of knowledge that have been differentiated out under one or another of the universal validity claims."

Habermas maintains that "the unity of rationality in the multiplicity of value spheres rationalized according to inner logics is secured precisely at the formal level of the argumentative redemption of validity claims. " 35 Given his admission that "arguments play different roles with different degrees of discursive binding force" depending on whether they are cognitive, normative, aesthetic, evaluative, or therapeutic, such a claim can hardly be expected to carry much conviction. Moreover, his more recent attempts to develop a holistic model of social criticism centering on the unifying forces of aesthetic rationality are not easily reconcilable with his assertion that health is a particular value. For if health is a balanced interplay and interpenetration of vital functions, as Habermas sometimes suggests it is, then it is essentially related to that integral aesthetic harmony or rationality of everyday experience celebrated by Dewey and first-generation critical theorists-a notion whose significance is revealed only in light of Habermas' s theory of selective rationalization. 54

Weber's Theory of Rationalization HABERMAS'S THEORY OF RATIONALIZATION

The rational decentering of consciousness that allows actors to adopt different attitudes with respect to different domains of reality provides Habermas with the reference points required to construct a nonselective model of social rationalization. Such a model depicts those rationalizable action systems that must not be "subordinated to laws intrinsic to heterogeneous orders of life" if the institutionalization of the three value spheres is to proceed toward healthy equilibrium. By contrast, a selective mode of rationalization results when "(at least) one of the three constitutive components of cultural tradition is not systematically cultivated (bearbeitet) or when (at least) one cultural value sphere is insufficiently institutionalized without a structure-building effect for the whole society or when (at least) one sphere of life prevails so far that it subordinates other orders of life under its alien form of rationality." 36 Now there are six spheres of cultural life-what Habermas calls "rationalization complexes" -in which cognitive-instrumental, moral-practical, and aesthetic-expressive types of knowledge are stabilized in permanent, cumulative learning processes, and these demarcate value spheres possessing their own inner logics and capable of being organized into professional discourses. Habermas "deduces" them in the following way. Since each world may be reflexively dissociated from the attitude in which it originates and may be thematized from the perspective of any of the other attitudes (for example, we can factually report the content of prescriptive and expressive statements), the three worlds and attitudes can be cross-tabulated to yield nine possible formal pragmatic relations. 37 The three original formal pragmatic relations (shown in table 4.1) of cognition and instrumental action (1.1), social obligation (2.2), and feeling and self-expression (3.3) can be linguistically articulated in assertions, regulatives, and expressive utterances and then rationalized in the context of theoretical, practical, and aesthetic (evaluative or therapeutic) discourses. These relations and their corresponding modes of discourse can be extended to underwrite strategic action (1.2), moral self-control and autonomy (2.3), and aesthetic taste (3.1), respectively. Only cognitive-instrumental (1.1/2), moralpractical (2.2/3), and aesthetic-expressive (3.1/3) relations are singled out by Habermas as founding areas of social life susceptible to rationalization. These rationalization complexes (shown in table 4.2) roughly correspond to the three cultural value spheres of Weber. 38 Difficulties arise if one tries to conceive each of the above complexes as "cumulative," "continuous," and "institutionalizable" in ex-

55

Weber's Theory of Rationalization Table 4.1. Formal-Pragmatic Relations Basic attitudes 1. Objectivating

1. Objective Cognitiveinstrumental relation

2. Norm-conformative

3. Expressive

Moralaesthetic relation to a nonobjectivated environment

2. Social

3. Subjective

Cognitivestrategic relation

Objectivistic relation to self

Obligatory relation

Censorious relation to self

Pres entation of self

Sensualspontaneous relation to self

Adapted from Jiirgen Habermas, The ThetJry of Communicative Action, vol. 1, trans. Thomas McCarthy. Introduction and translation copyright © 1984 by Beacon Press. Reprinted by permission of Beacon Press.

actly the same sense. 39 Moreover, it is unclear why Habermas thinks that relations 1.3, 2.1, and 3.2 cannot be rationalized. His denial that anything "can be learned in an objectivating attitude about inner nature qua subjectivity" (1.3) puts empirical psychology and utilitarian ethics beyond the realm of rationalizable undertakings. The idea of a hedonistic calculus has long been held suspect by philosophers, but the success of experimental psychology and psychopharmacology can hardly be doubted. 40 Although Habermas acknowledges that "we can indeed adopt a performative attitude to external nature, enter into communicative relations with it, have aesthetic experiences and feelings analogous to morality with respect to it" (2.1), he concludes that "there is for this domain only one theoretically fruitful attitude, namely the objectivating attitude of the natural-scientific experimenting observer"-a view that has been challenged by McCarthy, Whitebook, and Ottmann, who in different ways have sought to retrieve a teleological reflection on nature. 41 The reason given by Habermas for excluding an expressive-aesthetic attitude toward the social world (3.2)-perhaps the most revealing of the three formalpragmatic relations deemed not to be rationalizable and indisputably the most significant as far as the argument of this book is concerned-is that "expressively determined forms of interaction (for example, countercultural forms of life) do not form structures that are rationalizable in and of themselves. "42 We must turn to Habermas's difficult and highly ambivalent discussion of modern art to fathom the arcane meaning of this sentence. 56

Weber's Theory of Rationalization Table 4.2. Rationalization Complexes Basic attitudes

3 Expressive 1 Objectivating

2 Normconformative

1

Objective

Objective

Art Cognitive-instrumental rationality Science Technology

X

X

I !Social I technologies I Moral-practical rationality Law

3 Expressive

3 Subjective

2 Social

X

I I I

Morality Aesthetic-practical rationality

I Eroticism :

Art

Adapted from Jiirgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1, trans. Thomas McCarthy. Introduction and translation copyright © 1984 by Beacon Press. Reprinted by permission of Beacon Press.

The cognitive-and, for Habermas, essentially critical-value of modern art is that it nourishes "a counterculture, arising from the center of bourgeois society itself and hostile to the possessiveindividualistic achievement- and advantage-oriented-life-style of the bourgeoisie." 43 This new view reflects the influence of Habermas's mentor, Adorno; however, in singling out modern art as the aesthetic medium of critical reflection par excellence, Habermas seems to be advocating a view held by Adorno's chief rival, Walter Benjamin. Modern art-exemplified, for Benjamin, in the poetry of the French symbolists and by such avant-garde movements as Dadaism, surrealism, and futurism-is art that has been stripped of the cultic, ideological illusion (aura) of beautiful repose as a result of a technical decontextualization and juxtaposition of images in photographic, lithographic, and cinematographic reproduction and montage. It is precisely through the combination of conflicting images that society is exposed as a reified, fragmented totality and that new possibilities of synthetic perception are revealed: "The purification of the aesthetic from admixtures of the cognitive, the useful, and the moral, is mirrored ... in the surrealistic celebration of illumination through shock effects with its ambivalence of attraction and repulsion, of bro-

57

Weber's Theory of Rationalization ken continuity, of the shudder of profanization, of agitated disgust: in short in the reflection on those moments in which the bewildered subject 'transgresses his boundaries' as Bataille puts it." 44 The rather cavalier manner in which Habermas tosses together modern art, with its shocking violation of convention and its uncompromising hostility toward the affirmative, harmonious illusion of the beautiful, and aesthetic claims to appropriateness and harmony, is disconcerting, to say the least. Explication of the tension involved in this juxtaposition can be found in Habermas' s criticism of surrealism, in which he claims that dispersion of the contents of desublimated meaning arising from the destruction of form is not necessarily emancipatory and, in any case, must be linked to a positive mediation of cognition, evaluation, and expression at the level of everyday communication. But if so, why does Theorie deny counterculture any stabilizing, structure-building effect on society? And why does it assert that autonomous art is rationalizable, even though it putatively "has just as little structure-forming effect on society as a whole as do the shifting, unstable countercultures that form around this system"?45 Despite these disclaimers, the idea of an aesthetic structuring of social reality is unmistakably present in Habermas' s more recent pronouncements, in a Hegelian rather than a Kantian vein, concerning the "potential for truth" of works of art. The following statement by Albrecht Wellmer is cited by Habermas in support of this contention: Neither truth nor truthfulness may be attributed unmetaphorically to works of art, if one understands "truth" and truthfulness in the sense of a pragmatically differentiated everyday concept of truth. We can explain the way in which truth and truthfulness-and even normative correctness-are metaphorically interlaced in works of art only by appealing to the fact that the work of art, as a symbolic formation with an aesthetic validity claim, is at the same time an object of the lifeworld experience, in which the three validity domains are intermeshed. 46

On this reading, art's potential for truth would denote a kind of learning process, based, if you will, on a mediating, or dereifying, reflection "in the sense of a concentrically expanding, advancing exploration of a realm of possibilities," rather than "in the sense of an accumulation of epistemic contents." In contrast to Benjamin's notion of modern art as "concentrated distraction" or social critique that "remains unassimilated in the interpretative achievements of pragmatic, epistemic, and moral mastery of the demands and challenges of everyday situations," artistic truth articulates the intention of "redeeming a promise of happiness" whose "superabundance radiates beyond art. "47 Here we find Habermas affirming the other side of Benjamin's "rescuing criticism," whose aim was to preserve the pri-

58

Weber's Theory of Rationalization mal power of nature in language, its allegorical relationship to mundane suffering and happiness (Nietzsche's eternal return of the same), and to release it from the bondage of esoteric, autonomous art. 48 As against the "false Aufhebung of art into life" effected by the precipitous "liquidation of appearance" contained in so much surrealist art, the determinate negation, or mediation, of artistic truth "reaches into our cognitive interpretations and normative expectations and transforms the totality in which these moments are related to each other. In this respect, modern art harbors a utopia that becomes a reality to the degree that the mimetic powers sublimated in the work of art find resonance in the mimetic relations of a balanced and undistorted intersubjectivity of everyday life." 49 I shall later argue that the critical task which Habermas now sets for himself can no longer be justified independently of this aesthetic sensitivity.

59

CHAPTER FIVE

From Lukdcs to Adorno: Ra tiona Iiza tion as Reification

eber was so imbued with the idealistic spirit of Southwest German neo-Kantianism that he could not have interpreted the nihilistic tendencies at work in modern capitalism as other than a logical consequence of cultural rationalization. Marx, by contrast, saw the dehumanization and fragmentation of life under capitalism as symptomatic of the reduction of labor to an exchange value. Beginning with Lukacs, later critical theorists-most notably persons affiliated with the Frankfurt School of Social Research-appropriated Marx's theory of value in order to articulate the socioeconomic implications of Weber's analysis of rationality. It is Habermas's contention that, despite their success in redefining Weber's paradox in terms of a contradiction between the economic imperatives of capitalism and the emancipatory needs of a rationalized lifeworld, they did not succeed in extricating themselves from the peculiar assumptions-rooted in the subject-object model of consciousness indigenous to German idealism-that spawned the paradox in the first place. In the following discussion we will focus on the implications of this model vis-avis critical theory-an aspect of Habermas's settling of accounts with his former teachers that is best dealt with independently of his critique of their diagnosis of advanced capitalist society, which is treated in chapter 10-and consider the extent to which the subject-object model of consciousness obstructed the justification not only of critical theory but of reason itself. 1

W

THE IMPORTANCE OF WEBER IN THE TRADITION OF WESTERN MARXISM

As far as Habermas is concerned, the reception of Weber by Western Marxism is nowhere more clearly documented than in Georg 60

From Lukacs to Adorno Lukacs's Geschichte und Klassenbewusstsein (1922). Lukacs postulates a logical connection between formal rationality, understood as a global "form of objectivity" (Gegenstiindlichkeitsform) penetrating consciousness and social reality, and the reification of human relationships -what Marx called commodity fetishism. 2 In the first volume of Das Kapital Marx wrote that "the mysteriousness of the commodity form thus consists simply in this, that it reflects to men the social character of their own work as the objectified character of the products of labor itself, as social-natural properties of things. " 3 In traditional societies, labor is coordinated by customary norms which regulate standards of production, occupational roles (usually inherited), conditions of exchange, and so on. It is closely interwoven with social identity and, in addition to procuring a livelihood, also serves communicative needs of self-expression and role reinforcement. 4 With the advent of capitalism, labor is no longer aimed solely at preserving the social and material well-being of the worker but becomes a commodity, or exchange value, that is reducible to a monetary equivalent. As such it is regulated in accordance with the impersonal, functional laws of supply and demand. The emancipation of labor from its former embeddedness in communicative action affords greater opportunities for its strategic deployment. Yet freedom to sell one's labor to the highest bidder is purchased at the price of one's individuality and humanity. Freedom gained is freedom lost, since by surrendering control over the production process, one is beholden to conditions of production that vitiate one's creativity, sociality, and rationality. Even the freedom to sell one's laboring capacity is illusory inasmuch as it is constrained by the need to survive and so depends on the employment opportunities made available by the fortuitous laws of the market. Lukacs found in Weber ready confirmation of his thesis that the commodity form had thoroughly penetrated all orders of life. After all, it was Weber who had observed that the form of organization characteristic of public administration was identical with that of the business firm. If Lukacs could be said to surpass Weber in his understanding of contemporary social pathology, it was because of his recognition that the reification associated with the commodity form stems from a deeper contradiction between the functional exigencies of a market economy and the practical needs of everyday life. His diagnosis is still wedded to a critique of scientific, or formal, rationality, however, and inasmuch as formal rationality analyzes what is originally a dynamic totality into discrete, lifeless abstractions and oppositions, it is itself symptomatic of reification. Lukacs later recanted this idealistic and somewhat romantic critique of natural science under threat of expulsion from the Hungarian Communist party. Not the least of the party's concerns was Lukacs's decision to embrace a dia61

From Lukacs to Adorno lectical conception of reason that not only claimed to penetrate the illusion of reification by restoring the subjective dimension of social reality, but also catapulted the rank and file into a privileged position that threatened the notion of an elite cadre, or vanguard leadership. Although he did not have the benefit of Marx's early writings, Lukacs was sufficiently steeped in the writings of Hegel and the later Marx to recognize the importance of labor as a process of self-transformation and raising consciousness; the location of the proletariat at the point of production ostensibly enables it to perceive the contradiction between its potential sovereignty as a spontaneous social form and its perverse actual debasement to a mere appendage of the machine-or what is the same thing-between social reality (society as a dynamic totality of meaningful interrelationships rooted in social labor) and social appearance (society as a static juxtaposition of isolated things and events governed by the external laws of the market). The underlying assumption that social theory is already anticipated in practice recalls a long-standing problem in German idealism. Lukacs noted that Hegel's attempt to resolve the theory-practice, determinism-freedom antinomy posed by Kant led him to seek a reconciliation of subject and object in a higher, speculative reasonAbsolute Spirit. Since Hegel conceived Absolute Spirit in terms of religious, artistic, and philosophical contemplation of ideas, he quite naturally interpreted history (the realm of freedom) as itself the dialectical resolution of logical contradictions between ideas (the realm of necessity). However, because of his conviction that the logical progression of ideas could be grasped only theoretically, in retrospective philosophical reflection, Hegel concluded that prospective practice aiming at historical change must remain blind to the real meaning, necessity, and consequences of its action. But Lukacs, like Marx, concluded that the antinomy of theory and practice could be resolved by locating reason on the side of practice rather than theory. 5 Lukacs's revolutionary optimism belied the rise of totalitarianism and the deterioration of the labor movement in European politics. The assumption underlying all praxis philosophy, that there exists an immediate practical unity of subject and object, action and knowledge, Habermas darkly suggests, may even have contributed to Lukacs's willingness to sacrifice the integrity of social theory to the advancement of the strategic aims of the party-an abuse particularly prevalent among intellectuals who condoned Stalinist repression in the name of historical necessity. 6 But, for Habermas, as we have already seen, theoretical knowledge (truth) cannot be regarded solely as a function of action without jeopardizing the autonomy and pure reciprocity of discourse. Later critical theorists seeking to avoid both

62

From Lukacs to Adorno the contemplative objectivism of traditional metaphysics and the pragmatic subjectivism of science and political praxis were thus faced with a dilemma. By rejecting ultimately both conceptual (objective) and practical (subjective) attempts to unify theory and practice, they put the legitimacy of their own program in doubt. Repudiation of "identity thinking" in all its manifestations reintroduced a cleavage between theory and practice that was enlarged further by a willingness to take the theory of reification to its utmost extreme. In Habermas's view this was nowhere more clearly expressed than in the later writings of Horkheimer and Adorno. Horkheimer and Adorno stand before the following problem. On the one hand, they contest Lukacs's premise that the complete rationalization of the world finds its limit in the formal character of its own rationality; they contest it empirically by pointing out the manifestations of a penetrating reification of culture and inner nature, and they contest it theoretically by demonstrating that even Hegelian-Marxist objective idealism merely continues the line of identity thinking and reproduces in itself the structure of reified consciousness. On the other hand, Horkheimer and Adorno radicalize Lukacs's critique of reification. They regard the complete rationalization of the world as not merely an "appearance" and they thence deploy a conceptual device which permits them to denounce the whole as nothing less than the false. They cannot reach this goal by way of an immanent critique of science, for the conceptual device which could fulfill their desideratum advances a claim that still remains at the level of the grand philosophical tradition. This tradition, however-and this is the Weberian thorn in the side of Critical Theory-simply cannot be renewed in its systematic claim; it has "outlived" its own claim and in any case cannot be renewed in the form of philosophy.' THE CRITIQUE OF INSTRUMENTAL REASON

Horkheimer' s critique of instrumental reason betrays a close affinity to some of the central themes raised by Weber. 8 Like Weber, Horkheimer saw the emergence of formal rationality as signaling the demise of the "objective" rationality that had informed the Thomistic world view of medieval Christianity, which united cognitive, practical, and aesthetic values under a divinely preordained, objectively preexisting summum bonum. With the sole exception of truth, the various value domains were consigned to the imprimatur of subjectivity-private conviction or faith in authority-thereby establishing a link between the irrational fanaticism of Protestant sectarianism (Glaubensfanatismus) and later historicism (Bildungstraditionalismus). The logical outcome of this de-objectification of reason, the degradation of ultimate ends and values-extending eventually to truth

63

From Lukacs to Adonzo itself-to mere means in the struggle for self-preservation, culminated in the convergence of formal, instrumental, and subjective reason.9 On the one hand, Horkheimer noticed that cultural rationalization issues in a progressive loss of meaning symptomatic of the fragmentation of society into isolated, self-interested egos lacking the moral fiber, the shared sense of value and purpose, necessary for imbuing personality and character with distinction. Thus, "the increasing formalistic universality of reason, far from signifying an increasing consciousness of universal solidarity, expresses the skeptical separation of thought from its object. ... The triumph of nominalism goes hand in hand with formalism." 10 The abstraction of the individual as an egoistic subject of universal formal rights, on the other hand, epitomizes for him the loss of freedom emanating from social rationalization-the totalitarian hegemony of technological domination over passive objects. As Marcuse, writing at the same time as Horkheimer, put it: "In this manner, the various professions and occupations, notwithstanding their convergence upon one general pattern, tend to become atomic units which require coordination and management from above. The technical democratization of functions is counteracted by their atomization, and the bureaucracy appears as the agency which guarantees their rational course and order." 11 Like most first-generation critical theorists, Horkheimer amplified Weber's thesis by means of insights drawn from Freudian psychology. The "rational" suppression of vital instincts for the sake of societal preservation is inherently dialectical. The internalization of repressive social authority in the form of an overzealous superego issues in a "revolt of nature," clinically manifested in an uncontrolled release of aggressive drives of the sort commonly associated with paranoid and manic behavior. Taking this as a model for understanding the mass psychology of fascism (the authoritarian personality), Horkheimer saw the reconciliation of seemingly antithetical tendencies -the annihilation of individual freedom in deference to the total authority of the state and the uncontrolled release of lawless behavior and violence-as "a satanic synthesis of reason and nature." Fascism appeals to precisely those classes who, perceiving themselves to be victims of modern society's legal protection of minorities, labor unions, and other formerly disenfranchised groups, seek a return to a monolithic order based on social homogeneity and unquestioned obedience to authority. 12 The theory of mass culture-the term culture industry was later introduced by Horkheimer and Adorno to emphasize that consumer preferences were manipulated by publicity managers "from above" rather than democratically integrated "from below" -also linked so64

From Lukacs to Adorno cial integration with the suppression of vital instincts. Adorno maintained that the sadomasochistic tendencies at the root of fascism are also operative in the consumption of cultural commodities. The consumption of art in capitalist society is geared toward providing release from the repressive regimen of work. The kind of pleasure afforded by the entertainment industry, however, is essentially anaesthetic-one is invited to "possess" momentarily the superficial thrills and luxuries denied one in everyday life as compensation for accepting the ascetic self-renunciation required by the discipline of production and consumption. Destruction of the formal unity of work that enables it to transcend fragmented social conditions likewise issues in a regression of aesthetic appreciation to the level of precognitive, sensual distraction. 13 In Dialectic of Enlightenment (1947), Adorno and Horkheimer advanced what is perhaps the most radical version of the reification thesis. Not content to equate formal rationalization with the rise of capitalism, they speculate that the need to forestall gratification of basic drives to secure survival requires rational objectification of and control over self and nature. The principal thesis of this remarkable tour de force is that "myth is already enlightenment and enlightenment reverts to mythology," or simply, "power and knowledge are synonymous. " 14 If myth constitutes a reaffirmation of the primal powers of collective fate, it is equally true that it enables the self to differentiate itself from, and thereby rationally control, those very same forces. 15 Enter Odysseus, the "prototype of the bourgeois individual," who practices that quaint deception of getting more out of his bargain with Polyphemus and Circe-by far the most treacherous of primal forces-than was originally stipulated. 16 But this cunning extrication from passion is purchased at the cost of incurring a new debt. Accordingly, we read that Odysseus is "delivered up to the mercy of the waves," whence he is forced to "recklessly pursue his own self-interest." 17 What Freud called the return of the repressed-the power of primal instincts to resurface in neurotic episodes-is here joined with the anarchy of production imputed to capitalism by Marx and the bureaucratic reification of political life imputed to rationalized society by Weber to produce a global dystopia in which the gods of reason devour their own children. The rational bifurcation that the autonomous self inflicts on itself in the course of individuation (self-consciousness as self-objectification) is not an isolated incident but is symptomatic of a far-reaching disenchantment that extends to nature in its entirety. It was Nietzsche, not Weber, however, to whom Adorno and Horkheimer turned in explicating the reversion to arbitrary power as the 65

From Lukacs to Adorno ultimate source of valuation-albeit, not without reservations. Nietzsche's panegyric to the agonal culture of Homeric civilization, especially its glorification of natural beauty and strength, was seen by them as a harbinger of fascism. At the same time, however, they conceded that "the realization of Nietzsche's assertions both refutes them and at the same time reveals their truth." 18 Thus, they could agree with Nietzsche that the task of enlightenment- "to make princes and statesmen unmistakably aware that everything they do is sheer falsehood" and to show how even in democracy "the reduction and malleability of men are worked for as 'Progress'" was fundamentally ambiguous. 19 As Nietzsche so eloquently put it: "What an enormous price man had to pay for reason, seriousness, and control over his emotions-those grand human prerogatives and cultural showpieces! How much blood and horror lies behind all good things!" 20 Just how much finds ample testimony in the rational "interiorization of the instincts" whereby the "soul" -what Nietzsche calls that "wild beast hurling itself against the bars of its cage"- is born. 21 The recurring motifs of Nietzsche's genealogy that resonate in Dialectic of Enlightenment-the relationship between exchange, justice as equivalence-retribution-revenge, guilt, punishment, responsibility, rational calculation, domination, and asceticism-are indeed ambivalent monuments to a protean will to power which can just as easily affirm life as deny it. Once again, the reversion to power as the ultimate source of valuation and, by implication, identity formation, reminds us that only a short distance separates the self-imposed legal domination of the categorical imperative from the explosive sexual violence of Sade's Juliette. 22 For Nietzsche, the will to power enshrined by Socratic rationalism and subsequently inscribed in modern science and Judea-Christian morality more often than not expresses resentment toward time, a craving for eternal repose in the empty oblivion of the transcendent, and inevitably issues in a devaluation of values. 23 In response to this purely negative (passive) nihilism Nietzsche proposes a positive (active) nihilism whereby the possibilities of the past are creatively recycled in a continuous transvaluation. In place of skepticism, conformism, utilitarianism, and fanaticism-all symptoms of modern subjectivism that stifle creativity and breed weakness-Nietzsche offers a life-affirmative vision of aesthetic modernity: a Dionysian self-forgetfulness wherein linear time is suppressed through the celebration of creative spontaneity. Heidegger maintained, however, that Nietzsche's will to power doctrine brought to its culmination the very tradition that it sought to overcome-the nihilistic subjectivism of Western metaphysics. 24 The

66

From Lukacs to Adorno Frankfurt school, accordingly, could not have acceded to Nietzsche's decision to enthrone the taste and dazzling power of the artist as the measure of value, nor could they have swallowed his genealogical estimate of the superior-because more creative and original-power of the older nobility as compared to the degenerative morality of the herd. Their negative assessment of his will to power doctrine did not deter them, however, from appropriating what they took to be the core of his aestheticism-a mimetic reconciliation with nature free of domination. In the aesthetics of Benjamin, Adorno, Marcuse, and Habermas, this venerable relic of German idealism is combined with that other Dionysian trait commonly associated with the countercultural aspirations of the avant-garde-the destruction of formal unity -in a synthesis that, as Jean-Fran