Critical Theory and the Critique of Political Economy: On subversion and negative reason 9781501302107, 9781441161390

Subversive thought is none other than the cunning of reason when confronted with a social reality in which the poor and

247 91 2MB

English Pages [242] Year 2014

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Recommend Papers

Critical Theory and the Critique of Political Economy: On subversion and negative reason
 9781501302107, 9781441161390

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

To my son Declan. He is simply the best.

9781441161390_FM_Final_txt_print.indd v

3/4/2014 11:46:27 AM

9781441161390_FM_Final_txt_print.indd vi

3/4/2014 11:46:27 AM

Acknowledgements I

had the good fortune to present some chapter drafts at conferences, including the May-Day conference in Ljubljana, May 2013, the International Conference on Neoliberalism, University of York, July 2013, the workshop on Critical Theory and Antisemitism, Cambridge, June 2013 and at a research workshop at the Centre of Social Movements, University of Glasgow, January 2013. I thank all participants for their insightful comments, discussions and helpful criticisms. Special thanks are due to Robert Fine, Lars Fischer, Nick Gane, Jay Geller, Vassiliki Kolocotroni, Anej Korsika, Michael Lebowitz, Brendan McGeever, David McNally, Stephen Shapiro, Hae-Young Song, Annette Spellerberg, Marcel Stoetzler, Ana Štromajer, Erik Swyngedouw, David Seymour and Claire Westall. I am most grateful to Ana Dinerstein, John Holloway, Peter Hudis, Michaela Mihai and Chris Rogers for their very helpful comments and insightful remarks on chapter drafts. I am indebted to Greig Charnock, Vasilis Grollios, Richard Gunn and Chris O’Kane, who read the whole manuscript, seeing things that I failed to see. Thank you so very much for your generosity, insights, disagreements, help and encouragements. The responsibility for this piece of work is of course entirely my own.

9781441161390_FM_Final_txt_print.indd ix

3/4/2014 11:46:27 AM

9781441161390_FM_Final_txt_print.indd x

3/4/2014 11:46:27 AM

1 Introduction: Critical theory and the critique of political economy Reason, left to work alone, creates monsters; while imagination unalloyed by the power of reason gives rise to futile ideas. ADORNO AND HORKHEIMER, DIALECTIC OF ENLIGHTENMENT

Subversion and the critique of political economy Subversive thought is none other than the cunning of reason when confronted with a social reality in which the poor and miserable are required to subsidize the financial system for the sake of sustaining the illusion of abstract wealth. Yet, this subsidy is necessary in existing society, to secure its wealth and prevent its implosion. This rational irrationality of a capitalistically organized mode of social reproduction is at the centre of the critique of political economy. It asks why human social reproduction takes this irrational form of an economic logic that asserts itself over the acting subjects as if by force of nature. The critique of political economy is intransigence towards the existent patterns of the world. It demands that all relations ‘in which man is a debased, enslaved, forsaken, despicable being have to be overthrown’.1 Debasement subsists as society unaware of itself, one in which human sensuous practice exists, say, in the form of a movement of coins that impose themselves objectively on and through the acting subjects as if the law of coins were a world apart from the social subjects who constitute the society governed by coins.

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 1

2/19/2014 3:36:27 PM

2

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

For the critique of political economy as a critical social theory, the fetishism of commodities entails the movement of some abstract economic forces that assert themselves over society on the pain of ruin. Yet, however objective in its nature, economic nature is in its entirety a socially constituted nature. The question of the social nature of the movement of coins is therefore one about the specific character of the capitalistically constituted social relations that assert themselves in the form of economic forces beyond human control. The money form disappears as a social relationship, and instead asserts an abstract economic logic, which, I argue, manifests the vanished social subject in her own social world as a personification of economic categories. The capitalist social subject is a coined subject. There is, says Adorno, a need for a ‘practice that fights barbarism’, and yet, he argues rightly, there can be no such practice.2 Barbarism cannot be fought in a direct and immediate manner – what does it really mean to struggle against money, resist the movement of coins, combat the movement of interest rates, fight price movements and resist poverty in a mode of social reproduction in which social wealth entails the dispossessed labourer in its concept? A ‘practice that fights barbarism’ is about the social preconditions that manifest themselves in the logic of reified economic forms. In terms of a critical theory of political economy, it is not the independence of economic categories of cash and coin, value and money, as forces over and above, and also in and through the social individuals, that requires explanation. Rather, what needs to be explained are the social relations of production, which manifest themselves as a relationship between reified economic things that assert themselves behind the backs of those same individuals who comprise and sustain society. That is, reification is really ‘an epiphenomenon’.3 Critically conceived, the theory of reification does not substitute the religious idea of God for the logic of secularized things. Reification is either a critical concept that asks about the social constitution of reified relations or it is not, in which case it becomes affirmative in its grasp of society. Spellbound by the plight of the dispossessed in a system of wealth founded on dependent labour relations, the ‘tireless charge of reification’ is premised on the assumption that reification essentially has to do with reified things.4 In this case, then, ‘the protest against reification becomes reified, divorced from thinking, and irrational’.5 The critique of reification asks what is reified and what therefore appears in reification. What appear in reification are the social relations of production in the form of self-moving economic things. However reified in its appearance, the economic world is and remains a world of definite social relations. The fetishism of commodities does therefore not just comprise, as Moishe Postone argues in his critical theory of social domination, an opposition

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 2

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

INTRODUCTION

3

between exchange value and use value in which non-identical things for use are treated identically as value abstractions.6 Nor does the illusion in the process of exchange lie solely in the socially valid objectivity of real economic abstractions, an objective illusion as Reichelt has argued.7 The mysterious character of an equivalent exchange of money for more money (M . . . M’; say, £100 = £120) has to do with the transformation of the commodity labour power into a surplus value producing labour activity (M . . . P . . . M’). The understanding of the mysterious character of an equivalence exchange between unequal values does therefore not lie, as Reichelt suggests, in the objective character of the equivalent exchange relations themselves. Rather, it lies ‘in the concept of surplus value’.8 Adorno thus argues that the equivalence exchange relations are founded ‘on the class relationship’ between the owners of the means of production and the seller of labour power, and this relationship vanishes in its social appearance as an exchange between one quantity of money for another.9 Adorno’s point not only focuses the critique of political economy as a critique of the capitalist form of wealth, and its production, it also renounces the established view, according to which the critique of political economy is a critique from the standpoint of labour.10 The standpoint of labour does not reveal an ontologically privileged position. Rather, the standpoint of labour is in every aspect tied to the capitalist economy of labour.11 Indeed, both the capitalist and the worker are ‘personifications of economic categories’.12 That is, ‘society stays alive, not despite its antagonism, but by means of it’.13 Against the grain of the classical Marxist tradition, I argue that the critique of political economy amounts to a critique of ontological conceptions of economic categories, including the category of labour as a trans-historically conceived activity that defines the human metabolism with nature in abstraction from society. The origin of this critique goes back to the early Frankfurt School challenge to the orthodox Marxist tradition, and it was later taken up by the so-called new reading of Marx that developed in Germany in the aftermath of the 1968 student movement.14

On the critique of political economy as a critical social theory The context of this book is the ‘new reading of Marx’, which was principally developed by Hans-Georg Backhaus, Helmut Reichelt and also Moishe Postone. Reichelt and Bachkaus in particular developed the critical theory of the early Frankfurt school, especially Adorno’s account, as an alternative

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 3

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

4

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

to the existing versions of Marxism that originated from the second and third Internationals as the theoretical expressions of social democracy and Leninism.15 It rejected Marxian economics as a radicalization of Ricardo’s political economy, which, as Marx had argued, develops the labour theory of value on the basis of some undifferentiated conception of labour that is presumed to be eternally valid as ‘a goal-directed social activity that mediates between humans and nature, creating specific products in order to satisfy determinate human needs’.16 Ricardo, says Marx, views ‘the bourgeois form of labour . . . as the eternal natural form of social labour’.17 For the ‘new reading’ this critique of classical political economy was pivotal. Instead of the classical Marxist view that purports a dialectics between the trans-historically conceived forces of production and the historically specific relations of production, it developed Marx’s work as a critique of ‘capitalism in terms of a historically specific form of social interdependence with an impersonal and seemingly objective character’.18 The ‘new reading’ thus renounced the classical argument about trans-historically valid economic laws of development and in its stead, conceptualized the economic appearance of society as the necessary manifestation of definite social relations. Its stance entailed the further rejection of the idea that economic development is an expression of the struggle for hegemonic class power. The new reading argued that capitalist economic categories belong to the society from which they spring. In a society that asserts itself behind the backs of the acting subjects, one in which the individuals are really ruled by economic abstractions, the idea that society is after all nothing more than a manifestation of the balance of class forces is purely instrumental in its view of ‘the social forces’. Adorno’s negative dialectics did not just provide the theoretical catalyst for the new reading. Rather, it provided both the incentive and the critical insight for the development of the critique of political economy as a critical social theory.19 The happenstance that Adorno, and Horkheimer and Marcuse too, did not publish a work about Marx’s critique of political economy has been taken to mean that they did not concern themselves with political economy nor with economics, be it bourgeois economics or Marxian economics. 20 There is, as Dirk Braunstein remarks drily, no economist by the name of Adorno or a political economist called Horkheimer. 21 The early Frankfurt school developed a distinctly heterodox Marxist approach to the critique of political economy. Its critical intent can be summarized with reference to the subtitle of Marx’s Capital – a critique of political economy – which as Alfred Schmidt argued succinctly, amounts to a conceptualized praxis (begriffene Praxis ) of the capitalistically constituted social relations. 22 In this context, the title of Adorno’s defining work, Negative Dialectics, is emblematic. It is neither a dialectics of structure and agency, nor a dialectics of history

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 4

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

INTRODUCTION

5

as a self-moving ontology of the being and becoming of economic matter; nor is it also a dialectics of the trans-historical forces of production that manifest themselves in the anatomy of capitalist social relations. 23 Negative dialectics is the dialectics of a social world in the form of the economic object, one that is governed by the movement of economic quantities. The economic world comprises the sensuous world of the ‘doing’ individual as a ‘charactermask’ or ‘personifi cation’ of a social totality that though created and reproduced by the acting subjects themselves, asserts itself behind their backs. 24 Critical theory conceives of society as an existing immanence that is ‘antagonistic in itself’.25 There is only one reality, and that is the reality of the existent social relations. The social individuals themselves produce their own reality, and it is their own reality that, as Horkheimer put it, ‘enslaves them’.26 The social individual is ‘governed by the products of his own hand’, and it is his own social product that acts ‘with the force of an elemental natural process’.27 What manifests itself behind the backs of the social individuals is ‘their own work’.28 Negative Dialectics is the dialectics of the manner in which definite social relations vanish in their own social world only to reappear as, say, relations of price competitiveness. On the pain of ruin, their own social world rules over and through them as if by the force of an invisible hand that takes care of ‘both the beggar and the king’.29 Conceived as critical social theory, the critique of political economy flouts tradition. It conceives of historical materialism as a critique of society understood dogmatically. It therefore rejects Engels’s idea of dialectics as a ‘science of the general laws of nature, human society and thought’.30 As a science of general laws, dialectics is the method of a bewitched world; it transforms social laws into laws of nature, and thus treats society as a manifestation of the forces of economic nature in being and becoming. Engels’s conception of a dialectics of general laws of nature lies at the foundation of what Heinrich characterizes as ‘worldview Marxism’.31 Worldview Marxism represses the notion that the existent relations of economic objectivity are socially constituted in their entirety. Instead, it views the economic structure of society as an expression of some trans-historically active forces of production that manifest themselves in the rise and fall of particular social relations of production. Critically conceived, the natural character of ‘capitalist society is both an actuality and at the same time a necessary illusion. The illusion signifies that within this society laws can only be implemented as natural processes over people’s heads, while their validity arises from the form of the relations of production within which production takes place.’32 In distinction to the classical view of a dialectics of history and nature, for the critical theory tradition dialectics is a method of presenting or

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 5

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

6

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

developing the categories of a definite and finite form of society, unfolding the social genesis of the whole system of real economic abstractions. 33 Critically conceived, Capital is therefore not an economic ‘text’.34 Economics is the formula of an inverted world.35 This stance raises the question about the meaning of critique in the critique of political economy. What is criticized? According to Marx, his critique of political economy amounts to a ‘critique of economic categories’ and he argued that the economists deal with unreflected presuppositions.36 That is, in the hands of the economists the ‘law of capitalist accumulation [is] metamorphosed . . . into a pretended law of nature’.37 The critique of political economy focuses thus on the system of economic inversion and its categories of cash, price and profit to decipher the social relations that vanish in their appearance as personifications of ‘particular class-relations and class-interests’.38 The circumstance that every individual reacts ‘under the compulsion’ of economic forces begs the question of the origin of this socio-economic nature and the manner in which it renders individuals ‘mere character masks, agents of exchange in a supposedly separate economic order’.39 The question of ‘capital’ thus becomes a question about the social relationship between persons expressed as a relationship between economic things, that is, real economic abstractions. Just as the critique of religion does not criticize God on the basis of God, the critique of political economy does not criticize real economic abstractions on the basis of real economic abstractions. Rather, the critique of religion deciphers the social relations that assume the form of God and vanish in the idea of God only to reappear as cowed believers in God, mere human derivatives of divine rule. Similarly, the critique of capital is not a critique from the standpoint of economic nature. Like the critique of religion, it too deciphers the definite social relations that manifest themselves in mysterious, seemingly extramundane economic forms and forces that prevail in and through the social individuals as personifications of economic forces.

The new reading of Marx and the critique of economic forms The ‘new reading of Marx’ developed as a sustained effort at a critical reconstruction of the critique of political economy as a critical social theory. It unfettered Marx from dogmatic certainties, opening up a number of critical perspectives, and, I argue, did not fully reveal what it had unchained. In particular it kept at arms’ length the political form of capitalist society, that is, the state, and in particular the class antagonism and the class struggle, which is

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 6

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

INTRODUCTION

7

the dynamic force of a negative world. Indeed, the ‘essence of an antagonistic society is that it is not a society with contradictions or despite contradiction, but by virtue of its contradictions’.40 The new reading developed a critical alternative to classical Marxism, including Althusserian structuralism, by turning against the traditional idea of society as an historically overdetermined structure of some general historical laws. Instead it developed the categories of political economy from within their social context. Against the traditional view, it thus conceived of the categories of political economy as the finite and transient products of the finite and transient reality of capitalist social relations as an existing totality. Nevertheless, by keeping the class antagonism at arms’ length, it treated society as a contradictory though conceptually logical system of economic inversion. As a consequence, it has also very little to say about the political form of political economy, the state. By viewing political economy as a supposedly separate economic order of ‘monstrous inversion’, its conception of capitalist society as a negative totality remains a mere postulate.41 The new reading saw that Marx’s work entailed contradictions and inconsistencies, argued that his critique of political economy was therefore not fully developed and that the ‘dialectical method’ of presenting the economic categories as ‘perverted forms’ of definite social relations had in fact been ‘hidden’ by Marx, apparently in an attempt at popularizing his work.42 In the hands of Backhaus and Reichelt, critical reconstruction entailed at first archaeological textual analyses and comparisons between the various editions and drafts of Capital, and all other works, to ascertain nuances and changes in the meaning of categories. This attempt at reconstruction assumed, wrongly as Reichelt argued later, that Marx’s work contained a hidden veracity, which can be reconstructed and put together to form a consistent and complete account of what Marx had intended.43 The attempt at establishing the veritable Marx ended up amplifying the very contradictions and inconsistencies that it had set out to overcome. The ‘new reading’ thus revealed the unfinished and ambivalent character of Marx’s work, and it moved hither and thither to establish a consistent account where none could be found, leading towards a circular argument that, say, on the one hand, rejected naturalistic explanations of abstract labour and then, on the other, posited Marx’s naturalist definition of abstract labour as evidence for the still incomplete character of critical reconstruction. Hans-Georg Backhaus developed Marx’s value form analysis as a most robust and insightful critique of economic categories.44 For him, economics is the discipline of monstrous economic forms. Economic theory manifests thus the categorical unconsciousness of economic abstraction, and he therefore defines economics as a discipline without subject matter. This then raises the

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 7

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

8

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

question about the foundation of economic forms. According to Backhaus, the critique of fetishism deciphers economic categories on a human basis. It reveals the human content of seemingly extramundane economic things.45 This argument, however suggestive in its critical intension, comes at a price. The anthropological standpoint is not the critical standpoint. ‘Man’ in general does not do anything. Does not work, does not eat, does not truck and barter and has no natural tendency, needs, consciousness, etc. Man in general does also not alienate herself in the form of value. In distinction to Backhaus, Man has needs only as concrete Man and the ‘determinate character of this social man is to be brought forward as the starting point, i.e. the determinate character of the existing community in which he lives’.46 Neither economic nature nor anthropology but the ‘definite social relations’ that manifest themselves in mysterious economy forms are ‘the point of departure’.47 That is to say, the reified world of economic necessity is innately practical – it entails the actual relations of life in their inverted economic form. Helmut Reichelt developed the critique of economics as an immanent critique of the existing social relations.48 For this critique, the dialectical method of exposition is fundamental – it unfolds the economic forms as real abstractions of social mystifications. The critique of political economy intends therefore to be more than ‘just a critique of the discipline of economics’. Fundamentally, it is ‘an exposition of the system, and through the exposition, critique of the system’.49 Although the value form expresses the abstract essence of capitalism – value vanishes in a constant movement of forms, in which economic quantities assert themselves as independent and seemingly irresistible economics forces – it is as incomprehensible as the existence of God in the religious world. Value form analysis thus amounts to an exposition of the law of value as a process of social ‘autonomization’, which economics analyses in terms of price movements, stock market developments and other such macro-economic analyses of, in themselves, incomprehensible economic quantities. The purpose of the dialectical exposition of the economic system is therefore to establish, say, the need of money to ‘lay golden eggs’ as the ‘objective necessity’ of the law of value and not as an entirely contingent chance development based on the decision and will of this or that banker. Adorno captures the ‘objective necessity’ of society well when he argues that ‘the objective rationality of society, that is exchange, detaches itself from the logic of reason. Society as an autonomised force is therefore no longer comprehensible. What alone remains comprehensible is the law of autonomisation’.50 What however is autonomized and what appears in the appearance of society as a movement of real economic abstractions, such as price and profit? The ‘new reading of Marx’ conceived of this law of autonomization as the manifestation of the law of value, and perceived

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 8

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

INTRODUCTION

9

value as the self-moving essence of capitalist wealth. In distinction to this conception of value as the essence of society, I argue that society is fundamentally Man in her social relations. What is therefore ‘autonomized’ is not some abstract essence of value as the ‘ontological foundation of the capitalist system’ that generates an ‘inverted reality’ in which commodities ‘simply instantiate their abstract essence as values’.51 Rather, it is the definite social relations of production that subsist in the form of mysterious economic things that seemingly possess the mystic character to ‘instantiate’ themselves. Theoretical mysteries find their rational explanation in the comprehension of the historically specific character of human social practice, however perverted this practice might be in the form of a relationships between economic things. That is, ‘definite social relations between men themselves assume . . . the fantastic form of a relation between things’ that assert themselves as real economic abstractions, upon which movement the life of the social individuals depends in its entirety. Yet, their genesis is founded on the ‘peculiar social character of the labour that produces them’.52 The ‘new reading’ focuses on the exchange validity of value without examining the peculiar social character of labour, leading to a conception of the value form as some abstractly valid selfmoving essence of wealth, an ‘universal in re ’ that posits its own expansion.53 However, the exposition of the capitalist categories falls short if it proceeds as a merely logical derivation of economic forms. These forms are the forms of definite social relations, which are historically branded and antagonistic from the outset. In distinction to the new reading, the social antagonism does not derive from the economic categories as the real-life expression of their contested movements. Rather, and as I set out to argue, the class antagonism is the constitutive premise of the economic categories. Moishe Postone develops the critique of political economic as a critical theory of both the form of wealth and its production. He argues that the economic system has its origin in the commodity form of labour and develops this notion into a powerful critique of classical Marxism, which views labour in trans-historical terms as the goal-orientated human effort of production. Postone’s critical theory therefore renounces the classical analyses of capitalism from the standpoint of labour, according to which capitalist economy is an irrational and exploitative system of labour that socialism will transform into a rationally planned economy for the benefit of workers.54 In distinction, Postone argues that ‘labour is the object of the critique of capitalist society’.55 Yet, his own conception of labour as a specifically capitalist form of labour remains flat: he does not tell us how this historically specific form of labour was branded and how its branding holds sway in the conceptuality of capitalist wealth, and its production. In distinction to the new reading, including Postone’s account, I argue that the

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 9

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

10

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

conditions which led to the creation of the capitalist form of labour, that is, the divorce of the mass of the population from the means of subsistence, passes over into ‘results of the presence’.56 In Postone’s account capitalist society appears as a rigidified system of commodified labour. He assigns to this labour systemic properties that establish the economy of labour as an objective framework for action that structures the social conflicts and class struggles in concrete social settings.57 His conception of ‘class’ is a traditional one – the life world of the social individuals is determined by their market situation, which expresses itself in a multiplicity of class-relevant and other forms of conflict. In distinction, I hold that class is not a revenue-based category. Rather, it is the critical category of capitalist wealth. A critical theory of class does not partake in the classification of people; it thinks in and through society to comprehend its existing untruth.

Scope and structure Helmut Reichelt is right when he argues that the time has come to reconsider the purpose of reconstruction, moving it on from an attempt at finding the veritable Marx to the development of the critical themes and insights that the new reading of Marx has established as fundamental to the critique of ‘the monstrous objective power’ of economic things.58 In distinction to the new reading, the development of the critical themes and insights rests on the acceptance that Marx’s account is fundamentally ambivalent, beyond reconstruction. This point is most strongly made by Michael Heinrich.59 He establishes that Marx’s revolutionary break with classical political economy is marked by the pains of transition, leaving a multi-layered argument that, say, in the case of the conception of abstract labour, which is the value producing labour, overlaps with naturalistic definitions that derive from the tradition of classical political economy. This book develops the critique of political economy as a critical social theory of economic objectivity, beyond critical reconstruction. At its best, the critique of political economy thinks against the spell of the dazzling economic forms. It wants to get behind the secret of our world, to demystify its fateful appearance as a force of economic nature. Critical theory does not think about (reified) things. Rather, it thinks ‘out of these things’.60 For this task, the insights of the new reading are fundamental, especially the argument that the capitalist social relations manifest themselves in the inverted form of objectively valid, seemingly natural economic abstractions. Yet, taken by itself, it does not explain the social character of economic objectivity. What is objectified? In distinction to the new reading, I argue with Adorno that the

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 10

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

INTRODUCTION

11

‘movement of society’ is ‘antagonistic from the outset’.61 Further, I argue that the critique of political economy is not just a critique of the economic form of society. It is also a critique of the political form of society, which I develop first by means of an argument about the relationship between world market and national state, and then by an account of the state as the political form of the capitalist social relations. The book is divided into four parts. The first part contains a connected argument about the character of a critique of political economy. It contains a chapter (Chapter 2) on the meaning of a critique of political economy, which I develop with the help of the new reading. The chapter explores the difficulty of determining the subject matter of economics, expounds the classical Marxist interpretation of economic laws and develops Marx’s characterization of his work as a critique of economic categories as critical theory of social constitution. Chapter 3 develops the implications of this characterization further into an argument about the capitalist forms of social practice, which I develop with the help of Adorno’s negative dialectics. The second part develops the class character of the law of value in three connected chapters. In distinction to the new reading, it argues that the social antagonism is the logical and historical premise of the law of value. Chapter 4 argues that the hidden secret of the law of value is the forceful expropriation of the labourer from the means of subsistence. In this context I argue that the attempt of the new reading to develop the economic categories by means of logical exposition banishes the class relationship from the critique of political economy. In distinction, the chapter argues that the existence of a class of labourers with no independent access to the means of subsistence is the fundamental premise of the capitalist social relations. Chapter 5 develops this argument further into a critical theory of class as the objective category of the capitalist form of wealth and thus of the entire system of social reproduction. The law of value is premised on the force of law-making violence that established a class of surplus value producers who depend for their life on the sale of their labour power. Chapter 6 extends discussion of the creation and reproduction of a class of dispossessed producers of surplus value into an argument about abstract labour as the historically specific labour of capitalist wealth, of value. It argues that the value-producing labour manifests the force of law-making violence in the form of an economic dictate of a time-made abstract. Social wealth manifests itself in exchange as the labour of ‘socially necessary abstract labour time’.62 The third part develops the critique of political economy as a critique of the form of the state. I reckon that the law of value has no independent economic reality. It does not dominate anything and anyone, nor does it instantiate itself – just like that. Value relations are relations of political economy, and

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 11

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

12

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

political economy presupposes the force of law making violence as the premise of its – civilized – appearance as an exchange relationship between the sellers and buyers of labour power as equal legal subjects, governed by the rule of law. Chapter 7 establishes the world market as the categorical imperative of the capitalist form of wealth. The world market asserts itself as a coercive force over labour in production. However, coercion is not a socio-economic category. It is a political category, which characterizes the state as the political form of bourgeois society. I argue that the world market society of capital entails the (national) state in its concept. Chapter 8 focuses on the state as the political form of bourgeois society. In distinction to traditional accounts that derive the state from the economic, I hold that the law of value is premised on depoliticized exchange relations, and I argue that the state is the concentrated force of socio-economic depoliticization. Fragments apart, Marx’s promise of a critique of the form of state did not materialize. The chapter therefore develops its account with reference to Hegel’s political philosophy and Smith’s classical political economy and its further development in neo-liberal thought, to make sense of Marx’s characterization of the state as the executive committee of the bourgeoisie. The conclusion returns to Marx to argue that the state is the political form of capitalist society. The fourth and final part assesses the anti-capitalist implications of the critique of political economy as a critical social theory. Chapter 9 presents forms of anti-capitalism that personalize the critique of capitalism as the power of money or the power of imperial force, or both. Here, the critical notion that the social individual personifies the economic categories regresses into the condemnation of hated forms of capitalism that are identified with the interest of particular persons. The personalized critique of capitalism entails the elements of antisemitism from the outset, which the chapter explores as a perverted critique of capitalism. Chapter 10 is the final chapter. It summarizes the argument by exploring Adorno’s demand for a praxis that fights barbarism. Contrary to the rumour about critical theory, its entirely negative critique of existing conditions does not entail an impoverished praxis. Rather, it entails the question of praxis – what really does it mean to say ‘no’ in a society that is governed by real economic abstractions?

Notes 1 Karl Marx, Contribution to the Critique of Hegel ’s ‘Philosophy of Right ’, Introduction, Collected Works, vol. 3 (London 1975), p. 182. Throughout this book, Man with a capital ‘M’ is used in the sense of Mensch. In the German

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 12

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

13

INTRODUCTION

language, Mensch can be masculine as in Der Mensch, feminine as in Die Menschheit and neutral as in Das Menschlein. Menschlichkeit is always feminine, as is reason, labour and revolution. 2 Theodor Adorno, Einleitung zur Musiksoziologie (Frankfurt 1962), p. 30. Translations from German texts are by the author. 3 Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London 1990), p. 190. 4 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 191. Adorno’s argument is directed against Georg Lukács’s theory of reification. See Chapter 3. 5 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 110. 6 Moishe Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory (Cambridge 1996), pp. 362–3. 7 Helmut Reichelt, ‘Social Reality as Appearance: Some Notes on Marx’s Concept of Reality’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, Human Dignity: Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism (Aldershot 2005). 8 Theodor Adorno, ‘Seminar Mitschrift of 1962’, Appendix to Hans Georg Backhaus, Dialektik der Wertform (Freiburg 1997), p. 508. 9 Adorno, ‘Seminar Mitschrift of 1962’, p. 506. 10 See, for example, Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness (London 1971) and Ernest Mandel, The Formation of the Economic Thought of Karl Marx (New York 1971). 11 Marx makes this point forcefully in his Critique of the Gotha Programme, Marx Engels Selected Works, vol. 3 (Moscow 1970). 12 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 92. 13 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 320. See also Johannes Agnoli, ‘Destruction as the Determination of the Scholar in Miserable Times’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Revolutionary Writing (New York 2003). 14 The new reading characterises the German trajectory of the more general trend in the late 1960s at breaking the stronghold of Soviet Marxism on Marxist interpretation and analysis, from Italian autonomism to the Conference of Socialist Economists in the United Kingdom, and also Althusserian Marxism in France, which amounted to a concerted effort at Westernising Soviet Marxism. On this effort, see Perry Anderson, Considerations of Western Marxism (London 1976). For contemporary accounts influenced by the German debate, see Ricardo Bellofiore and Roberto Fineschi, Re-reading Marx (London 2009), Chris Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx ’s Capital (Leiden 2004), and Michael Heinrich, An Introduction to the three Volumes of Karl Marx ’s Capital (New York 2012). 15 On this point, see Hans-Jürgen Krahl, Konstitution und Klassenkampf (Frankfurt 1971). 16 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination, pp. 4–5. Backhaus renounces the traditional Marxism as Ricardian in origin, for three reasons. It deals with an undifferentiated conception of labour, accepts that economic categories manifest a naturally derived substance and develops its account akin to the tradition of classical political economy, which conceived of history as an

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 13

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

14

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

objectively unfolding process based on the development of the division of labour. 17 Karl Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (London 1971), p. 60. 18 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination, p. 3. 19 On this, see Dirk Braunstein, Adornos Kritik der politischen Ökonomie (Bielefeld 2011). Braunstein’s book explores Adorno’s reading of Marx, arguing that there is a ‘genuinely Adornoian version of critique of political economy’ (p. 10). His account is based on unpublished seminar transcripts and posthumously published material. The book is rich in detail and documentary evidence. 20 See Jürgen Habermas, Philosophisch-politische Profile (Frankfurt 1987) and Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination, A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923–1950 (London 1973). 21 Braunstein, Adornos Kritik. 22 Alfred Schmidt, ‘Praxis’, in ed. Hans-Georg Backhaus, Gesellschaft: Beiträge zur Marxschen Theorie 2 (Frankfurt 1974). In distinction, Gillian Rose, The Melancholy Science: An Introduction to the Thought of Theodor W. Adorno (New York 1979), p. 147, conceives of praxis ‘as the power of the object’. She does not enquire into the genesis of its power. 23 Gerald Cohen, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defense (Oxford 1978) offers the most elegantly written account of history as an objectively unfolding force of human progress. The classical Marxist tradition expounds this view of history with unerring enthusiasm; see, for example, Terry Eagleton, Why Marx was Right (New Haven 2011). Eagleton though critical of Cohen’s account, remains faithful to it. He expounds history as a history of (overcoming) economic scarcity. Walter Benjamin’s ‘Theses on the Philosophy of History’, Illuminations (London 1999) offers the most robust critique. See, also, Richard Gunn, ‘Against Historical Materialism’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. II (London 1992); Alfred Schmidt, History and Structure (Cambridge, MA 1983); Maximiliano Tomba, ‘Historical Temporalities of Capital: An AntiHistoricist Perspective’, Historical Materialism, vol. 17, no. 4 (2009), and Krahl, Konstitution und Klassenkampf. 24 I use the word ‘doing’ here with critical reference to Holloway’s work. John Holloway, Change the World without Taking Power (London 2002) and Crack Capitalism (London 2010). 25 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 317. 26 Max Horkheimer, Kritische und Traditionelle Theorie (Frankfurt 1992), p. 229. 27 Marx, Capital, p. 772. Karl Marx, Capital, vol. II (London 1978), p. 185. 28 Herbert Marcuse, Negations (London 1988), p. 151. 29 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 251. 30 Friederich Engels, Anti-Dühring , MEW 20 (Berlin 1983), p. 132. Engels’s point is core to the classical Marxist tradition, see footnote 23.

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 14

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

15

INTRODUCTION

31 Heinrich, An Introduction, p. 24. 32 Theodor Adorno, Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge 2008a), p. 118. 33 Hans-Georg Backhaus, Dialektik der Wertform (Freiburg 1997), p. 440. On dialectics as a method of exposition, see Helmut Reichelt, ‘Why Did Marx Conceal His Dialectical Method?’ in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn, John Holloway and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, Emancipating Marx (London 1995) and Helmut Reichelt, Zur logischen Struktur des Kapitalbegriffs bei Marx (Freiburg 2001). 34 Frederic Jameson, Presenting Capital (London 2011) sees Capital as a purely economic text. If it were, this would be bad for Marx. 35 On this, see Theodor Adorno, ‘Soziologie und empirische Forschung’, in ed. Theodor Adorno, Hans Albert, Ralf Darendorf, Jürgen Habermas, Harald Pilot and Karl Popper, Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen Soziologie (München 1993), p. 94. 36 Karl Marx, ‘Letter to Lassalle, 22 February 1858’, in MEW 29 (Berlin 1963), p. 550. On ‘the’ economist as a thinker of unreflected presuppsotions, see Karl Marx, ‘Letter to Engels, 2 April 1958’, in MEW 29 (Berlin 1963), p. 315. 37 Adorno, History, p. 118. 38 Marx, Capital, p. 92. 39 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 311. 40 Theodor Adorno, Lectures on Negative Dialectics (Cambridge 2008b), pp. 8–9. 41 Arthur captures the chained character of the new reading well. He conceives of the new reading as a ‘systematic dialectics’, in which Man in her social relations appears as an unnecessary distraction to ‘the systematic demystification of the objective irrationality of the value form’. Arthur, The New Dialectic, p. 12. 42 See Reichelt, ‘Why Did Marx Conceal His Dialectical Method?’, I use the term ‘perverted form’ with critical intent. In the German edition of Kapital, Marx uses the phrase verrückte Form. Karl Marx, Das Kapital, MEW 23 (Berlin 1979), p. 90. In the English edition this is translated as ‘absurd form’ (p. 169). In German, ‘verrückt’ has two meanings: verrückt (mad) and verrückt (displaced). Thus, the notion of ‘perverted forms’ means that they are at one remove both mad and displaced. In other words, they are perverted forms of human social practice, in which ‘subject and object do not statically oppose each other, but rather are caught up in an ongoing process of the inversion of subjectivity into objectivity, and vice versa’. Hans-Georg Backhaus, ‘Between Philosophy and Science: Marxian Social Economy as Critical Theory’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. I (London 1992), p. 60. I translate ‘verrückte Form’ as perverted form to capture this process of maddening inversion. 43 Helmut Reichelt, Neue Marx-Lektüre. Zur Kritik sozialwisschenschaftlicher Logik (Hamburg 2008). 44 Backhaus, ‘Between Philosophy and Science‘, and Hans-Georg Backhaus, ‘Über den Doppelsinn der Begriffe “politische Ökonomie” und “Kritik” bei

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 15

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

16

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Marx und in der Frankfurter Schule’, in ed. Stefan Dornuf and Reinhard Pitsch, Wolfgang Harich zum Gedächtnis, vol. II (München 2000). 45 Hans-Georg Backhaus, ‘Some Aspects of Marx’s Concept of Critique in the Context of His Economic-Philosophical Theory’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, Human Dignity (Aldershot 2005). 46 Karl Marx ‘Randglossen zu Adolph Wagners Lehrbuch der politischen Ökonomie ’, MEW 19 (Berlin 1962), p. 362. 47 Marx, Grundrisse (London 1973), p. 832. 48 Reichelt, Neue Marx-Lektüre, and Helmut Reichelt, ‘Die Marxsche Kritik ökonomischer Kategorien. Überlegungen zum Problem der Geltung in der dialektischen Darstellungsmethode im Kapital ’, in ed. Iring Fetscher and Alfred Schmidt, Emanzipation und Versöhnung. Zu Adornos Kritik der ‘Warentausch ’-Gesellschaft und Perpektiven der Transformation (Frankfurt 2002). 49 Marx, Letter to Lasalle, 22 February 1858, in MEW 29 (Berlin 1963), p. 550. For the new reading this exposition is fundamental to the character of the critique of political economy as a critical social theory. See Reichelt, Zur logischen Struktur. See also Kosmas Psychopedis, ‘Dialectical Theory’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. I (London 1992). 50 Theodor Adorno, ‘Einleitung’, in ed. Theodor Adorno, Hans Albert, Ralf Darendorf, Jürgen Habermas, Harald Pilot and Karl Popper, Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen Soziologie (München 1993), p. 23. 51 Arthur, The New Dialectic, p. 80. 52 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 165. 53 Reichelt, ‘Die Marxsche Kritik ökonomischer Kategorien’. 54 For Alex Callinicos, ‘Is Leninism finished?’ Socialist Review (January 2013), this is the revolutionary standpoint as developed for our time by Lenin. 55 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination, p. 6. 56 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 460. For insightful accounts, see in particular Silvia Federici, Caliban and the Witch (New York 2004) and Mariarosa Dalla Costa, ‘Development and Reproduction’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Revolutionary Writing (New York 2003). 57 See Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination, p. 319. On Postone’s account see, among others, Werner Bonefeld, ‘On Postone’s Courageous but Unsuccessful Attempt to Banish to Class Antagonism from the Critique of Political Economy’; Chris Arthur, ‘Subject and Counter-Subject’; Marcel Stoetzler, ‘Postone’s Marx’, all published in Historical Materialism, vol. 12, no. 3 (2004). 58 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 832. Reichelt, Neue Marx-Lektüre. 59 Michael Heinrich, ‘Reconstruction or Deconstruction’, in ed. Riccardo Bellofiore and Roberto Fineschi, Re-reading Marx. New Perspectives after the Critical Edition (London 2009); ‘Enstehungs- und Auflösungsgeschichte

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 16

2/19/2014 3:36:28 PM

INTRODUCTION

17

des Marxschen ‘Kapital’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Michael Heinrich, Kapital & Kritik (Hamburg 2011). 60 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 33. 61 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 304. 62 Adorno, ‘Seminar Mitschrift of 1962’, p. 507.

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 17

2/19/2014 3:36:29 PM

9781441161390_Ch01_Final_txt_print.indd 18

2/19/2014 3:36:29 PM

2 Political economy and social constitution: On the meaning of critique Introduction Marx frequently refers to economic categories as ‘sensuous-supersensible things’, ‘strange things’, ‘perverted forms’, abounding in ‘metaphysical subtleties and theological niceties’, ‘mythical’ in character and so forth.1 These formulations are decisively ‘uneconomic’ and point towards the critique of political economy as a theory of the social constitution of economic categories. Traditional conceptions of political economy, from classical political economy via modern economic theory to traditional Marxist accounts, are haunted by the spectre of social constitution. A traditional conception of political economy is characterized by the dismissal of the human social reality of its subject matter as a ‘metaphysical’ distraction that gets in the way of economic analyses. What however is political economy if it is not a theory about the manner in which society organizes its reproduction? Economic theory deals with economic quantities and economic laws, speaks the language of economic categories, conceives of the economy of labour as a general economic necessity, analyses economic relations in macro-economic terms and argues that economic theory is the veritable science of some innately economic matter. Economic theory is the theory of society unaware of itself. This chapter asks about the purpose of the critique of economic objectivity. What is to be understood by economic matter and what does its critique reveal? Marx’s critique of political economy asks why human social reproduction manifests itself in the form of self-moving economic forces that assert themselves behind the backs of the acting subjects, indifferent and

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 21

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

22

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

indeed hostile to their needs. The chapter is divided into three sections and a conclusion. It starts with the difficulty of economic theory to determine its subject matter in abstraction from society. It then introduces the traditional Marxist argument, including, in particular, Althusser’s structuralist account that capitalist economic categories are historically specific manifestations of general historical laws, which establish the objective framework for the development of definite forms of social relations. I hold that the structuralist account develops the insights of classical political economy, which it presents as Marx’s critique of political economy.2 The third section introduces the critique of political economy as a critique of economic categories and argues that this critique amounts to a critical social theory. Instead of deriving capitalist economic categories from some presumed trans-historical forces of economic nature, it dissolves the economic categories on a social basis, arguing that definite forms of social relations manifest themselves in mysterious economic forms. For the critical tradition, the critique of economic categories therefore entails a theory of the social constitution of economic forms. Apart from summarizing the chapter’s argument, the conclusion sets the theme of subsequent chapters, arguing that class antagonism is the critical concept of a capitalist society.

On economic nature and economic theory At best, economic theory conceives of its categories as comprising some transcendental essence of human economic behaviour. It regards Man as economic Man and having ‘put back in Man’ the economic idea of Man, it argues at best akin to the principles of classical political economy, Adam Smith and David Ricardo in particular, that the wealth of nations is founded on the productive power of labour.3 This labour evolves throughout the ages, leading to a greater technical division of labour, which occasions the rise and fall of definite ‘modes of subsistence’, from the property relations of the hunters and fishers, with whom Smith begun, via the property relations of pasture and agriculture, to the property relations between the three constituent classes that for Smith comprise what he called ‘commercial society’ – the land owners who live by rent, the owners of stock who live by profit and the class tied to work that lives by wages. According to Adam Smith, the modes of subsistence comprise definite forms of property relations, government, social institutions and moral sentiments.4 At its best, then, economics is an argument about the manner in which the evolution of the technical division labour gives rise to definite forms of society. It conceives of labour as a purposeful and goal-oriented exchange with nature, and construes this

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 22

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

23

necessity of the human metabolism with nature as a general economic law of history, in which developments in the technical division of labour give rise to historically definite forms of property, relations of distribution, forms of government, social institutions and ideological conceptions. At worst, economics is drawn into a game of formal abstractions, in which labour as a social practice of human reproduction is replaced by mathematical equations that rationalize and calculate the movement of economic quantities. In this account, economics transformed into a complex mathematical science, which analyses the movements of cash, price and currency value, ‘without asking itself what the object of its calculating analysis might be’.5 Economics presumes its object as an existing economic quantity that can be analysed according to some agreed convention of observation, measured according to some accepted standard of quantification, rationalized by means of mathematical method and whose movements can be calculated with predictive intent by means of the laws of probability.6 This, then, is the paradox of political economy: the economists, says Marx, ‘stagger about . . . within this contradiction, completely unaware of it’.7 What they just described as a ‘thing reappears as a social relation and a moment later, having been defined as a social relation, teases them once more as a thing’.8 As a theory of economic matter, economics articulates the theological quirks of its subject matter. It presumes an economic objectivity ‘external to Man’, analyses the value preferences of economic Man and studies the market as a rational means of economic distribution and individual decisionmaking, which by means of the free price mechanism informs consumers and producers of the degree of scarcity in the whole economy, leading to the adjustment of value preferences by the economic agents.9 It thus analyses the behaviour of markets as a force that objectifies itself in the individuals, defining their expectations, structuring their activities and compelling their behaviour in market relevant terms, on the promise of great wealth and on the pain of default, bankruptcy and unemployment. The subject of economic analysis is the inverted world of ‘Monsieur le Capital and Madame la Terre’ that Marx talks about in his chapter on the Trinity Formula: a definite form of sensuous human practice asserts itself in the movement of ‘perverted’ economic forms, and this appearance is real inasmuch as the social relations of production assume the form of a relationship between things that objectivize themselves in the person.10 Economic objectivity entails the assertion of the economic laws as forces ‘external to Man’ and as forces on which as Adorno put it, ‘the life of all men hangs by . . . [to the] vanishing point in the death of all’.11 Who would deny that the economy manifests itself over the social individuals as a seemingly natural, self-positing and self-moving thing beyond human control, substituting the

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 23

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

24

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

myth of economic fate for the myth of God’s wrath. Economic laws impose themselves behind the backs of the acting subjects that sustain society, and society is governed by the movement of real economic abstractions, which akin to the mythical idea of fate impose themselves on the social individuals with devastating force, cutting them off from the means of subsistence at the blink of an eye. At issue is not the irrational rationality of economic forms. What is at issue is their social constitution: why does this content of human social reproduction take that fateful economic form? According to Max Horkheimer, economic theory developed the traditional theory of society to the point of absurdity. It identifies society in the form of ‘mathematical symbols’ that rationalize its appearance as a relationship established by quantifiable economic things.12 Society appears ‘as a thing’, and ‘the economists’ perceive of this thing as having its own innate economically determined laws of development that are valid at all times and all places, as if they really embody some trans-historically active economic nature that manifests itself in capitalism as its most developed historical form. ‘The economists’ argues Marx, naturalize the economic categories, which ‘are then quietly smuggled in as the inviolable natural laws on which society in the abstract is founded’.13 Economics is the standpoint of economic matter in abstraction from society, which appears as a field of economic application. ‘It has never once asked the question why this content has assumed that form, that is to say, why labour is expressed in value, and why the measurement of labour by its duration is expressed in the magnitude of the value of the product.’14 Instead, it conceives of the capitalist labour process as the goalorientated activity of the human metabolism with nature, represents the movement of prices with mathematical accuracy, adds up economic quantities, analyses the movement of economic things, predicts on the basis of available economic data what markets will do next, describes the manner in which the human agents adjust to market demands for the sake of achieving greater economic efficiency and effectiveness and explores the means of state as the public authority of economic regulation. It identifies economic things as both some quantifiable substance and an independent force of economic rationality, which for the sake of economic progress requires a constant effort at economic adjustment from the human agents; and yet, it cannot tell us what the economic quantities are. Economic theorists who have thought about these issues accept that it is impossible to determine the subject matter of economics with any degree of certainty. Even the fundamental categories of economic analysis are not at all clear. As Joan Robinson put it, they ‘turn out to be unseizable concepts when we really try to pin them down’ and economic theory evades the ‘problem of giving meaning to a quantity of “capital” . . . by putting it into algebra’.15

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 24

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

25

Economic theory presumes some decipherable economic rationality – yet, what really is this rationality? Is it a socially constituted rationality that though created by the social individuals enslaves them to the product of their own social world, which appears to them in the form of real economic abstractions; or is the economic rationality founded on some trans-historical economic nature that manifests itself in definite modes of subsistence? The notion that society is governed by some general economic laws is confronted by the paradox that their validity is fundamentally social. Validity is a social category. Only for society can something be valid and have validity.16 Economic laws are therefore not valid in themselves. They are ‘not eternal natural laws independent of history’.17 Rather, their validity is fundamentally social, and they are valid in and through society and society is always concrete society. That is, economic laws are valid in and through the society to which they belong. Yet, society is not the subject matter of economic theory. For economic thought the notion that economic laws are inverted forms of definite social relations is a scandal. It deprives economics of its economic subject matter. If, however, economics does not deal with social essentials, and if it has therefore to eliminate the concern with such essentials in order to establish itself as a science of abstract economic quantities, of quantities of capital, then it has to accept that its subject matter amounts to a metaphysics of economic being. Or as Joan Robinson put it in exasperation about the seeming inability of economics to establish itself as a science of economic matter: ‘K is capital, ΔK is investment. Then what is K? Why, capital of course. It must mean something, so let us get on with the analysis, and do not bother about these officious prigs who ask us to say what it means.’18 Economic science is haunted by its inability to define its subject matter. Nicholas Kaldor suggested that it is quite unable to determine its subject matter with any satisfactory degree of certainty – is it a social science, an economic science or a science of economic nature?19 Friedrich Hayek was sceptical about its ability to make refutable predictions, and according to Sam Brittan, his economics amounted ultimately to a moral philosophy.20 Daniel Bell pointed out that ‘economic theory is a convenient fiction, an “as if”, against which to measure the habitual, irrational, logical, egoistic, selfinterested, bigoted, altruistic actions of individuals, firms, or governments – but it is not a model of reality’.21 But even as a fictional ideal, it is inherently problematic. Joan Robinson offered the hopeful view that it might be feasible after all to establish economics as a science of economic matter and that this would entail the elimination of its hitherto metaphysically conceived foundational concepts, such as humanity and her needs.22 Joseph Schumpeter argued early in his career that economics as a science has to view its categories as

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 25

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

26

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

categories of natural laws (Naturgesetze ) and that it therefore has to take care never to try to justify its social presuppositions.23 Later in his life, he appeared undecided whether economics could in fact be called a science – the question was still in the balance.24 Schumpeter posited the very question that is core to Marx’s critique of political economy, and which economic theory has to answer and continuously fails to answer with any degree of certainty. Is capital, he asked, a ‘repository of value, which can be expressed by but does not consist in money, without reference to its particular commodity form or its concrete application? . . . In fact the question arises: how is it possible, that the values of any good whatsoever appear as something independent [Selbständiges ]? For the value is inseparable from the object that is valued.’25 Schumpeter was well aware that the science of economic matter depends on conceptions of society that are not only alien to economics but also defy its attempt at establishing itself as a science of economic matter.26 He therefore suggested that the attempt at banishing the metaphysical baggage of Man in her social relations from economics amounts to an impossible task. Robinson granted as much when she argues that ‘money and interest rates prove to be incomprehensible concepts, as do goods and purchasing power, when we attempt to pin them down’.27 They thereby conceded that it was impossible to establish economics as a science in its own right. Crudely put, the metaphysical baggage is the human-social content of economic categories, which economics posits but cannot accept without calling itself into question as a science of purely economic matter. Economics conceived as a discipline without human-social ‘metaphysics’ tends towards its definition as a science of economic numbers, its application as a method of analysing the relationships between economic cost and economic benefit or to an argument about economics as a science of physical quantities, which, as Kunihiro Jojima sees it, deals with ‘atoms’ and ‘molecules’.28 In either case, be it as a science of numbers or atoms, or analysis of costs and benefits, economics is accepted as some determinate ‘second nature’ that though independent from the human-social relations, structures the actions of its human agents who struggle over the spoils of a system that asserts itself over them, as if it were a nature apart. Traditionally this indeterminacy of a first nature within the determinate order of a second nature has been conceived in terms of Say’s (in)famous law of the market democracy of demand and supply. Here the social forces are seen to operate within the framework of a spontaneous order in which each social category is indeterminate in terms of its relative worth or economic position but where every single social category is obliged to all in the generality of their spontaneous interaction.29 For the science of economics, the movements of economic quantities express value preferences, which reveal a rationality

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 26

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

27

of economic action that is regulated by price movements.30 It sets out to rationalize yesterday’s movement of prices as a manifestation of a plurality of economic-value preferences and on the basis of this direct and immediate calculus, predicts tomorrow’s utility movements of economic quantities. That is, it aggregates yesterday’s economic behaviour to measure today’s deviation in order to predict tomorrow’s price movements, with winning intent. That is, it translates quantities of ‘capital’ into algebra. 31 The idea that economics is a philosophy of numbers, or a branch of physics, or a science of the supply and demand for economic quantities, defines its character as a science without a subject. Proudhon’s mockery seems as relevant now as it was then: ‘How might economics be a science? How can two economists look at each other without laughing? . . . Economics has neither a principle nor a foundation . . . it knows nothing; it explains nothing.’32 The economist, says Marx, is unable ‘to utter a sentence without contradicting himself’.33 Economics sides with the mischief of a world that ascribes subjective power to economic things and invisible principles. That is, for economic thought the essence of economics is not society. It is economic nature; yet it cannot tell us what this is. It thus seeks validation by means of philosophical justification about the character of economic Man. Whatever its calculations, in the end everything comes down to ‘the natural propensity of truck and barter’ and thus to ‘human nature’, this ‘metaphysical’ foundation of economics as a moral philosophy of natural laws. 34 For the critique of political economy, economic nature is not the essence of economics. The essence of economics is society, and society is the social individual in her social relations. The circumstance that Man in her social relations appears as a personification of economic things – a bearer of economic laws – focuses the critique of political economy as a negative theory of society. In capitalism, Marx argues, the individuals are governed by the product of their own hands and what appears thus as economic nature is in fact a socially constituted nature that belongs to definite social relations. Social reality is thus an ‘objective appearance’: the social individual vanishes in her own social world only to reappear with a price tag, by which she is governed.35 Yet this inversion of the social subject into the economic object is her own work. It does not derive from some abstract economic matter that objectifies itself in the acting subject, as if by force of nature. For the critique of political economy the critical issue is thus not the discovery of general economic laws of history. Rather, its object of critique is the existent society, in which definite social relations subsist in the form of abstract economic forces, things endowed with an invisible will that ‘asserts itself as a regulative law of nature’.36 The following section explores the structuralist Marxist tradition. I argue that its analysis of the capitalist economic forms is entirely

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 27

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

28

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

traditional in its grasp of society. It, too, rejects the idea of Man in her social relations as a metaphysical distraction to the science of economic forces.

Economic nature and capitalist anatomy Louis Althusser famously declared that Marx’s critique of political economy is a work of theoretical anti-humanism and proclaimed for a politics of practical humanism to set things right.37 In his Preface to the French edition of Capital, he made two important observations that focus his anti-humanist stance succinctly.38 First, he argued that the philosophical idea of alienation of the Marx of the Paris-Manuscripts of 1844 does not have anything to do with the ‘economic’ Marx as the founder of scientific socialism. He therefore rejected the ‘theory of reification’ as a projection of the theory of alienation of the early Marx onto the ‘analysis of commodity fetishism’ ostensibly at the expense of the scientific character of Marx’s account.39 Second, he argued that Capital develops the conceptual system of scientific Marxism, not as a critique of capitalism as an existing reality, but as a means of comprehending history in its entirety.40 According to Althusser, Marx’s study of capitalism led him to the discovery of the general economic laws of history that manifest themselves in the structure of the capitalist economic relations. Marx’s Capital is thus seen to present the general economic laws of the forces of production in their historically specific capitalist form. The structure of society is thus determined by the forces of production, which manifest themselves in historically specific social relations of production. Capitalist social relations are perceived to unfold within an objective framework of general economic laws. According to Alfred Schmidt, Althusser’s structuralist view of Marx’s critique of political economy ‘does not interpret familiar Marxist ideas in structuralist language . . . Rather he presents structuralist positions without ceremony as Marxist ones’.41 However, Althusser’s point about the 1844 Manuscripts is a valid one. Man as such does not exist and the anthropological standpoint is indeed uncritical.42 Althusser sees the late Marx as the scientific Marx, and defines science as a discourse without a subject.43 He therefore argued that one can recognize Man only on the condition that the ‘philosophical myth of Man is reduced to ashes’.44 Poulantzas reinforced this view when he conceived of scientific Marxism as a radical break from the ‘historical problematic of the subject’.45 Their argument that, for the sake of scientific understanding, the social sciences have to be a science without a subject points towards a conception of society as an historically specific structure of enduring general economic laws. Science is thus the ‘consciousness’ of the inescapable lines and tendencies of structural

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 28

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

29

necessity. It recognizes the structured existence of general economic laws in the anatomy of the capitalist mode of production without being distracted by the musing about reification or the fuzzy humanism of the ‘doing’ subject, be it in the form of the alienated subject or the anti-capitalist subject.46 Like the economists discussed earlier, for the sake of scientific insight into the capitalist anatomy of general economic laws, scientific Marxism argues that the analysis of economic matter has to proceed ‘without ulterior metaphysical thoughts’.47 For the structuralist tradition capitalist economic categories manifest general economic laws in historically overdetermined forms of society. Instead of conceptualizing the actual social relations of production, it argues that capitalist development takes place ‘within the framework of its general laws’, and it is within this framework that ‘capitalist development is determined . . . by the actions of the acting subjects and classes, the resulting concrete conditions of crisis and their political consequences’.48 Analysis of ‘really existing’ society depends thus on the development of intermediary concepts, which analyse the mediation of general economic laws in concrete settings.49 This mediation is however difficult to achieve. The ‘general laws of capitalist political economy operate as a force of nature’ leading to the breakdown of ‘the clear distinction between natural and social laws’.50 Haug’s account exemplifies the scientific method appropriate to the task of resolving this difficulty in a clear manner. As he sees it, every economic category can be traced back to some basis in nature, and the scientific method thus consists in tracing the natural basis of social phenomena.51 However, nature does not exist in the abstract. One can therefore not find in history ‘pure manifestations’ of natural necessity because it never coincides directly with its appearance in concrete societies. Thus, ‘history . . . [is] the sphere of manifold overdeterminations’.52 In this perspective, then, the critique of political economy reveals the capitalist ‘mode of functioning’ (Wirkungweise ) of the general economic laws. Methodologically, the structuralist analysis of capitalism applies a method of abstraction akin to the microscope of the biologist. By means of ‘microscopic’ analysis, abstraction is to dissect the general economic laws in the anatomy of the capitalist social relations to determine the inescapable economic laws that govern society in the last instance. For the structuralist tradition, the most fundamental economic law comprises the inescapable necessity of labour as the purposeful activity of social reproduction. Labour expresses thus a trans-historical materiality, which is defined by its metabolism with nature. Capitalism is therefore viewed as a historically specific modality of this necessity of labour. As Postone argues most succinctly, instead of a ‘critique of production’, this

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 29

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

30

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

view offers a ‘theory of production’ defined by technical relations combining factors in material production, which is about the production of use-values.53 There is, then, the enduring general law of labour as purposeful exchange with nature in the abstract, regardless of time and space, and there is the historically specific modality of this same exchange. These two forms of labour are said to form a contradictory unity between materiality and social form – which is traditionally discussed as a contradiction between the transhistorically conceived forces of production and the historically specific social relations of production – and it this relationship between the materiality of labour as a trans-historical force of production and the historically specific social relations of production that establishes the fundamental contradiction of capitalism. In this account, the capitalist modality of the trans-historical materiality of labour is one in which a class of private individuals possess a legal title to factors of production. According to Étienne Balibar, the capitalist social relations are historically overdetermined manifestations of the trans-historical forces of production, in which ‘the economic relations of production appear . . . as a relation between three functionally defined terms: owner class/ means of production/class of exploited producers’.54 That is to say, the forces of production are seen to manifest themselves in the form of historically specific social relations of distribution, which are ‘mapped on to production by the legal connection of ownership of means of production’.55 As an account of political economy, it defines the class character of society on the basis of the legal title to one of the factors of production, from which the classes derive their revenues – rent for the owners of land, profit for the owners of the means of production and wages for the owners of labour power. Capitalism is seen as a fundamentally private organization of labour based on the legal title of the owners of the means of production to the product of labour. At the same time this private character of labour organization is fundamentally social in character since everybody is in fact working for each other. The connection between the private organization of labour and its social character is established by the market, which brings the many private labours into contact with each other, establishing points of sale and purchase. The social character of private labour is governed by the law of value that in capitalism is seen to regulate the distribution of social wealth not only by means of marketbased exchange relations but also by means of class struggle – who gets what and who, say, pays the costs of austerity?56 According to Jessop the capitalist exchange relations involve thus an interaction between multiple social forces that in turn denote multicentric, multiscalar, multitemporal, multiform and multicausal processes, which are co-existing and interpenetrating in a tangled

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 30

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

31

and confused manner, and are thus anarchic, uncontrolled, unplanned and crisis-ridden.57 As Patrick Murray put it succinctly in a different context, the structuralist idea of historical materialism argues that ‘the “forces of production” are not social-form-determined but, on the contrary, are the ultimate determinant of the “relations of production”’.58 Instead of dissolving the reified appearance of things, it views this appearance as the manifestation of natural economic laws that structure the actual relations of life. Whereas social laws can be changed, the laws of nature cannot. Harvey argues thus that ‘human beings are part of nature and are not passive agents, let alone mere victims, in natural evolution’ and that they can thus change the manner in which the inescapable law of labour is made manifest in the anatomy of historically specific social relations.59 The question of socialism thus becomes a question of the rational organization of the economy of labour, from the capitalist anarchy of the ‘uncontrolled, unplanned, and crisis-ridden’ market relations to the socialist rationalization of the economy of labour by means of central planning.60 When posited as natural, the economy of labour appears as a force of nature, legitimizing existing social relations as developed nature and delineating possible futures as idealized derivatives of the existent. Both depend on the deadly notion that ‘freedom is recognition of necessity’.61 Yet, nature has nothing to do with it. The idea that society is in the last instance determined by historically active, general, economic laws is in its entirety tied to existing conditions.62 Historical materialism conceived dogmatically as a science of some general economic laws reflects existing society under the spell of identification, which includes the allegedly realistic thesis that the capitalist social relations embody the logic of an abstract market structure whose empirical reality is mediated by class struggle.63 Instead of the critical notion that ‘concepts are moments of the reality that requires their formation’, this idea holds that concepts are generally applicable scientific instruments, which are capable of dissecting and analysing every society at all times and places as an overdetermined manifestation of abstract economic laws. This view suggests a radical separation between thought and reality. Haug articulates this view most clearly when he proclaims that the mastery of Marx was ‘the discovery of thought independent from empirical conditions’.64 Alex Callinicos argues similarly. He advocates that the Marxist method of analysis amounts to a sophisticated version of the science of knowledge, which hypothesizes society as an ‘as if’ of theoretical construction.65 Theoretical knowledge appears as an hypothetical figure of speech, an ‘as if’, which is corroborated by empirical analysis that falsifies or verifies the proposed theory of society. This appearance is, however,

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 31

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

32

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

deceitful in that the real world is mirrored in its theoretical hypothesis. That is, the science of knowledge posits the scientific idea that the real world is, say, regulated by a competitive market structure and then applies this idea to capitalist markets, with conclusive effect, though questions remain as to whether the freedom of competition has in reality not trans-morphed into a freedom of monopolies. The supposition of thought as an independent instrument of knowledge releases society from critical scrutiny. Rather than asking about the social constitution of markets, it supposes the existence of general economic laws, transforming the social laws into historically overdetermined derivatives of natural laws, and then analyses the manner of their mediation in the social world of intersubjective actions, comprising class-relevant and other social interests, and finally examines what it calls the hegemonic strategies of the competing social interests to ascertain emergent political opportunity structures for the conduct of hegemonic strategies that act through the state to achieve their goals.66 The structuralist supposition of society does not comprehend society. It merely describes it abstractly as an hypothesized unit of analysis. The scientific statement that capitalism is in the last instance determined by the general economic laws of development is as hypothetical in its conception of society as the statement that the state is the decisive force of the power of the social forces that act through it. The classical demand for a unity of theory and practice has historically entailed the struggle for the state as the means of socialist transformation, replacing the legal entitlements of capital to the products of labour by means of collective organization, making the economy of labour ‘directly’ social by unfettering it from the constraints of the capitalist pursuit of profit. Reminiscent of scientific socialism’s ability to transform its theoretical hypothesis of society into catchy slogans, Haug thus states without further ado that ‘the power of money and capital retreat when the state advances’.67 Althusser’s view that Capital is not a critique of capitalism as a living process but rather a scientific study of the capitalist anatomy of general economic laws is therefore apt as a succinct characterization of the traditional view that capitalist economic forms have a basis in nature and thus express a natural propensity.68 In the history of political thought, this view derives, as Simon Clarke argued succinctly, from ‘classical political economy’.69 Indeed, the attempt to free political economy from the metaphysical baggage of human purposes is a traditional one, from classical political economy to the classical tradition of historical materialism. It allows for a science of general economic laws as natural laws (Naturgesetze ) that, like Smith’s natural propensity to truck and barter, are historically active, leading the process of evolution, which in the case of classical political economy appears linear in its developmental logic

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 32

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

33

towards commercial society, and which in the case of the classical Marxist tradition entails a more contradictory process of struggles and setbacks and yet progressively moving forward throughout the ages towards capitalism as a transition to socialism, as if history really is some automatic, theologically conceived thing that unfolds by means of its own innate force. Smith’s theory is remarkable not only for the emphasis given to economic forces that work their way through history towards ‘commercial society’, it is also remarkable for the argument that in each historical stage, the political form of society, be it conceived in terms of authority or jurisdiction, necessarily flows from the state of property. For Smith, the transition towards commercial society and its law of private property rests on the natural propensity of humans to truck and barter and is the consequence of the development in the technical division of labour. He views labour as goal-oriented in its purpose, sees the productive power of labour as the foundation of social wealth and argues that the development of this labour determines the progress of society, from this stage of production to that state of production, affecting the mode of subsistence at any given stage of development. The development towards commercial society is founded on the technical division of labour, which gives rise to the growing social differentiation of society into distinct social classes, comprising a definite social division of labour. He defines classes by their respective revenue sources – wage, rent, profit – and argues that these revenues are determined by the contribution of the classes to the labour process – labour, land, stock. The underlying process of this differentiation of society into the constituent classes that comprise commercial society is the extension of the technical division of labour, which increases the social surplus and leads to the expansion of private property, which in turn underpins the evolving social division of labour and lays the foundation for the separation of the state from society in capitalism. In sum, for Smith, the forces of production manifest a general law of historical development, which leads to the rise and fall of distinct social relations of production, culminating in the system of perfect liberty that characterizes what he calls commercial society. The innate nature of the forces of production thus entails a dynamic of historical being and becoming. In Smith’s view the system of perfect liberty is the unplanned outcome of the processes founded on the natural human propensity to truck and barter. The underlying conception of this idea of historical progress was summarized well by Adam Ferguson in 1782: ‘nations stumble upon establishments, which are indeed the result of human action, but not the execution of any human design.’70 That is, history appears as an objectively unfolding process without a subject; it is designed akin to a law of nature and results from the unintended consequences of human action.71 History thus

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 33

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

34

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

appears as an unfolding of the human propensity to truck and barter, which encourages the growing technical division of labour, which first facilitates the emergence of historically specific social relations of production that then become fetters to the further development of the forces of production, leading to a crisis of a mode of production and transition towards a new mode of production that facilitates the further development of the forces of production towards commercial society. Clarke’s argument that the Althusserian view of Marxism derives from classical political economy is thus to the point – society can only do as nature does, and what nature does for society results from the unintended consequences of human action. In distinction, the circumstance that Man lives in nature and is herself a natural being neither explains history nor capitalism, nor for that matter any other form of society.72 Alfred Schmidt’s assessment of the classical Marxist tradition is to the point: it elevates ‘into a scientific norm’ what Marx criticized in his critique of political economy, that is, like classical political economy, it views social laws as laws of economic nature.73 It represses the notion of social constitution in its entirety. Its grasp of society remains abstract and its critique of capitalism does not aim at the thing itself. Instead of deciphering the conceptuality of society that holds sway in its own context, it identifies capitalist economic categories as historically overdetermined manifestations of some transhistorical forces of production. It thus hypothesizes the capitalist social relations of production as a developed form of the general economic law of labour. It perceives of this law of labour as the law of economic necessity, and the law of necessity characterizes history as a force towards the overcoming of conditions of economic scarcity. Terry Eagleton expresses this view with disarming clarity. His account does not start with hunters and fishers, with whom Smith began. He starts with some imagined primitive communist mode of subsistence: ‘When there is little or no surplus, as in so-called primitive communism, everyone has to work, nobody can live off the toil of others, so there can be no classes. Later there is enough of a surplus to fund classes like feudal lords, who live by the labour of their underlings. Only with capitalism can enough surplus be generated for the abolition of scarcity, and thus of social classes, to become possible. But only socialism can put this into practice.’74 Eagleton’s account characterized the illusion of the first and second Internationals that perceived capitalism as a transition to socialism. As an economic statement, his view presents the categorical unconsciousness of economic theory as the revealed truth of society in the abstract. That is, he expresses the conventional view of modern economic theory, according to which economics is the study of the distribution of scarce resources among different people.75 That is to say, and as Robbins argued, economics is the

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 34

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

35

science of human action in conditions of economic scarcity, rather than one of the peculiar capitalist forms of social wealth, and the manner of its production and reproduction, which is the subject matter of Marx’s critique of political economy.76 In sum, instead of thinking out of society, worldview Marxism analyses capitalist society to discover the general economic laws and then conceives of capitalist society as a manifestation of those same general economic laws that its analysis of capitalism established. That is, it thinks about reified things with an analytical grasp that, akin to a photographic representation of reality, identifies the capitalist social relations with their appearance as forces of nature. Its grasp of society thus appears entirely realistic in that it posits society in its immediate being, which ‘is pure appearance . . . of a process running behind its back ’.77 As a science of economic processes without a subject, it dissolves Man as the subject of her own social world into the ‘substance’ of her economic inversion. ‘The illusions of such a consciousness turn into dogmatic immediacies’ about the natural character of society.78 That is, its critique of bourgeois society is entirely abstract. ‘Abstract negativity’ naturalizes capitalist society as an historically overdetermined manifestation of some trans-historical materiality of labour, implicates the capitalists for the defects of the established system of labour and proclaims to know ‘what needs to be done’ to achieve resolution.79 While Althusser’s theoretical anti-humanism leaves society untouched by thought, his practical humanism proclaims progressive ends in abstraction from society, rejecting ‘all discrimination, be it racial, political, religious’. It ‘is the rejection of all economic exploitation and political domination. It is the rejection of war.’80 The humanization of social relations is the purpose and end of the critique of political economy. However, the effort of humanizing is confronted by the paradox that it presupposes the existence of inhuman conditions. Inhuman conditions are not just an impediment to humanization but a premise of its concept. Althusser’s practical humanism therefore manifests the illusion of his science of society without a subject. It posits society as an ‘as if’ of civilized social relations, against which it measures the irrational, exploitative and discriminative relations of a bloodied world. Devoid of a conception of the actual relations of life, his practical humanism does ‘not talk about the devil’. Instead ‘it looks on the bright side’.81 The blind spot of dogmatic thought is predicated on the idea that society is a process without a subject.82 It thereby accommodates its thought to the existing ‘objective conditions’ that render the individuals mere personifications of economic categories, which its practical humanism denounces as ‘exploitative’, ‘discriminative’, ‘violent’, ‘unfair’ and ‘irrational’.

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 35

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

36

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Economic objectivity and social constitution: On the notion of critique For the critical theory tradition, Marx’s critique of political economy is ‘immanent even if in the end it negates the whole sphere it moves in’. It resists the temptation to substitute the truth content of thought for ‘its social function and its conditioning by interests’. Its historical materialism, too, is immanent in the ‘ontology of the wrong state of things’, developing the conceptuality of the capitalist relations from within. That is, critically conceived, historical materialism is ‘a dissolution of things understood as dogmatic’.83 Rather than deriving the social relations of production from some abstractly conceived trans-historically active forces of production, it asks why the social relations of production assume the form of a relationship between reified things and what appears in reification.84 At its best, Marx’s critique rejects naturalized conceptions of labour. His disdain for such conceptions was especially exacting in relation to Smith and Ricardo, and also the popular socialism of his time, from Proudhon to the German social democrats.85 In his critique of Smith and Ricardo, Marx argued that they naturalize economic categories ‘as if the [imagined] individual and isolated hunter and fisherman, with whom [they begin]’ is an actual fact, posited by nature, not arising historically in the midst of bourgeois development.86 He saw his work as a ‘critique of the entire system of economic categories’.87 In distinction to Engels’s view that historical materialism is the science of the ‘general laws of motion and development of nature, human society and thought’, he characterizes his ‘materialist method’ as a critique of existent social relations, not from the standpoint of some abstractly conceived materiality of labour, but from within their own conceptuality: It is, in reality, much easier to discover by analysis the earthly kernel of the misty creations of religions than to do the opposite, i.e., to develop from the actual, given relations of life the forms in which they have become apotheosized. The latter method is the only materialist, and therefore the only scientific one. The weakness of the abstract materialism of natural science, a materialism which excludes the historical process, are immediately evident from the abstract and ideological conceptions expressed by its spokesmen whenever they venture beyond the bounds of their own speciality.88 For the critique of political economy the transformation of ‘every product into a social hieroglyphic’ requires explanation from within the actual social

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 36

2/19/2014 3:37:08 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

37

relations. We need, says Marx, ‘to get behind the secret of [men’s] own social product: for the characteristic which objects of utility have of being values is as much men’s social product as is their language’. Thus, the fetishism of commodities ‘arises from the peculiar social character of the labour that produces them’.89 Postone picks up on this point, arguing that the traditional Marxist accounts, which argue from the standpoint of labour as the standpoint of the general historical law of the forces of production, are unable to come to terms with the critique of fetishism.90 Indeed, just as the critique of God on the basis of God leads to scholastic dispute about the precise nature of God, the critique of economic nature on the basis of economic nature leads to a spellbound scholarly dispute about the precise meaning of reified things. Just as in the critique of religion, the critique of economic nature is not a critique of the thing in-itself. It is a critique of definite social relations that express themselves in the form of a relationship between things. What therefore appears in the appearance of capitalist society as a relationship between economic things is not some general economic nature. What appear are the actual social relations in the form of objective economic forces. The ‘forces of production’ do not therefore comprise some general law of economic motion in abstraction from society. Rather, they belong to the society that contains them. As Marx put it, the forces of production and social relations of production are ‘two different sides of the development of the social individual’.91 This point is fundamental not only because it characterizes the distinction between classical political economy and Marx’s critique of political economy, it is fundamental also for the distinction between the critique of political economy as a critical social theory and the traditional Marxist accounts of political economy that ascribe a material force to history, which purports historical materialism to be a dialectics between the trans-historically conceived, or in any case naturally determined, forces of production and the historically specific social relations of production. Adorno called this traditional Marxist conception of historical materialism a ‘perverter of Marxian motives’ and criticizes it as a ‘metaphysics’.92 It denies, he says, the ‘spontaneity of the subject, a movens of the objective dialectics of the forces and relations of production’.93 The circumstance that definite social relations assume the form of a relationship between things, and thus subsist in and through a world of things, has nothing to do with the things themselves. It has to do with the peculiar character of the social relations that assume the form of things. The social constitution of the economic categories is a matter of historical formation. History does not make itself, nor does it unfold objectively. Nor is history a matter of divine intervention. Critically conceived, history is not ‘some basic ontological structure of things in being’ and becoming. 94 Benjamin calls this ‘metaphysics’ of history ‘historicity’ – a term that

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 37

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

38

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

captures the scientific conception of history as some ontologically unfolding process, from this stage of human development to that stage of human development. 95 Historicity abstracts ‘from historic experience’ and thus perceives of history in entirely unhistorical terms as the being of its own becoming.96 The theological quirks of the commodity therefore ‘mock the false consciousness in which the social relations of the exchange value is reflected to contracting parties as a quality of things-in-themselves’.97 Instead of hypothesizing economic things, the critique of political economy aims at the things themselves, dissolving their appearance as forces of nature. Demythologization is its critical intent. It thus ‘deletes the image character of consciousness’.98 The circumstance that the capitalist social relations assume the form of a relationship between things and that the acting subjects therefore experience their own social world as a world that really is governed by the movement of economic things comprises the necessary ideology of society. Critically conceived, ideology is not just a view about the world. Rather, it is the ‘socially necessary appearance’ of definite social relations in the inverted form of real economic abstractions.99 The scientific presumption of capitalist social forms as overdetermined structures of general historical laws is therefore pure ideology. It transforms the appearance of society into a scientific norm. Marx’s critique of trans-historical conceptions of economic nature recognizes value as the self-moving essence of the capitalist social relations as a solely social necessity. In capitalism the social individual is governed by the ‘products of his own hand’, and the product of labour, society in the inverted form of a real economic abstraction, ‘asserts itself as a regulative law of nature’.100 Its comprehension has to resist the temptation of deriving human social relations from the seemingly self-moving economic forces. For Adorno, such derivation manifests the ‘ideology of reification’ – under the spell of reified things, thought identifies the properties of economic categories as the revealed truth of society.101 In distinction, Marx’s critique of political economy develops, to return to the earlier quotation, the reality of capitalist society ‘from the actual relations of life’. That is, it thinks out of, and in and through, ‘the existent’ society. In order to understand things, one has to be within them. For Marx, therefore, critique has to demonstrate ‘ad hominem, and it demonstrates ad hominem as soon as it becomes radical. To be radical is to grasp the root of the matter. But for Man the root is Man himself’ and ‘Man is the highest being for Man’.102 The critique of political economy is thus subversive of the reified economic categories. Rather than identifying them on the basis of their immediate appearance, it traces them back to the actual relations of life. It thus negates the deceitful publicity of the economic categories as naturally appearing things. Their natural

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 38

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

39

appearance is a socially necessary illusion, yet it is an illusion all the same and an objective one at that. Instead of publicizing the objective illusion of society, critique is charged with dissolving their natural appearance and it does so by deciphering them as human social forms, not of Man as an ‘abstract individual’ but of Man as a member of a definite form of society. That is, ‘theoretical mysteries find their rational explanation in the comprehension of human social practice’.103 These quotations from Marx’s earlier work are at times seen to carry little weight because he is said to have matured into a scientist of economic structures as a result of his serious study of political economy. This view accepts, rightly, that Marx was a highly intelligent scholar and it is for this reason that his later work has indeed to be taken most seriously: critique, as he argues in his mature work, has to return the relations among the things themselves, the constituted forms of the economic categories, to ‘relations between men’ and the critique of the fetishism of the commodity form entails an attempt at deciphering the ‘puzzling forms’ as forms ‘assumed by social relations between man and man’.104 He thus defined his critique as a ‘critique of economic categories’ and argued that it amounts to a ‘general critique of the entire system of economic categories’.105 For the critical tradition, the ‘new reading’ in particular, Marx’s critique amounts therefore to an attempt at deciphering the entire system of economic mystification as a socially constituted real abstraction. The movement of economic abstraction is both objective, as the constituted reality of definite social relations expressed in perverted economic forms, and illusionary in its appearance as a self-moving economic force of nature.106 For Adorno, Marx’s critique engages therefore in a reducio ad hominem.107 According to Reichelt, this formulation brings the core ‘problematic’ of Marx’s critique into sharp focus: how is it possible to understand the circumstance that human social practice is constitutive at the same time as when the individuals are ruled by really existing abstractions.108 The ad hominem critique engages neither in the fuzzy humanism indicated by its dogmatic opponents nor does it conceive of economic categories on an abstractly conceived human basis. It focuses rather on the actual social relations of a definite form of society. Value is a social relationship in the form of an economic thing. ‘Value . . . is subject of a process’ that manifests a relationship between persons as a relationship between things.109 There is then only one social reality, and not two, as if the social world were split between the logic of an abstract market structure that provides the objective framework within which the empirical world of social actions unfolds in a structured manner. However much society seems divided between a system of seemingly self-moving economic quantities and the actions of the social individuals who struggle over the spoils of an

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 39

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

40

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

economic system that asserts itself independently from them, the ‘separation between the in-itself and the for-itself, of substance and subject, is abstract mysticism’.110 The circumstance, then, that the fetishism of commodities renders human social practice invisible in the form of its economic object, calls for demystification. Yet, demystification does not reveal some hidden reality of human ‘doing’. It reveals rather the constituted untruth of a world that posits itself according to some innately economic logic, which asserts itself independently from the social individuals that constitute, comprise and sustain it through their own social practice. ‘They do this without being aware of it.’111 Marx’s work focuses on forms, at first on forms of consciousness (i.e. religion and law), then later on the forms of political economy. This focus ‘on forms was identical with the critique of the inverted forms of social existence, an existence constituted by the life-practice of human beings’.112 That is, every social ‘form’, even the most simple form like, for example, the commodity, ‘is already an inversion and causes relations between people to appear as attributes of things’ or, more emphatically, each form is a ‘perverted form’, which causes the social relations to appear as a movement of coins and makes the individual appear as an adjustable derivative of the economic forces of cash, price and profit, which, as I argued at the start, the economists set out to determine without ‘metaphysical’ distractions.113 The movement of ‘coins’ expresses a definite social relationship between individuals subsisting as a relationship between things and coins, and in this relationship the actual social relations subsist but as coined factors of production. In capitalism individuals are really governed by the movement of coins – they carry their relationship with society, and therewith their access to the means of subsistence, in their pockets.114 Although they tend to inflate or become depressed, coins are not subjects. Yet, they impose themselves on, and also in and through, the person to the point of madness and disaster, from the socially necessary consciousness of cash and product, money and profit, to abject misery and bloodshed. Capitalist wealth is money as more money, and the necessity of more money objectifies itself in the persons as mere ‘agents of value’ who depend for their life on the manner in which the logic of things unfold. What a monstrosity! An economic thing, this coin, that in its nature really is nothing more than a piece of metal manifests itself as an economic quantity in fateful movement, asserting a power by which ‘the life of all men hangs by’. That is, the mythological idea of fate becomes no less mythical when it is demythologized ‘into a secular “logic of things”’ that akin to an abstract system-logic structures the economic behaviours of the actual individuals by means of competing price signals.115

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 40

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

41

Conclusion The distinction between the structuralist Marxist tradition and the critical theory reading of Marx could not be sharper.116 Here we have the ad hominem critique of capitalism, which says that the categories of capitalist political economy are the categories of definite social relations and that they are thus immanent to the actual relations of life; and there we have an argument that every social form can be traced back to some basis in nature and that the capitalist social relations manifest a historically specific anatomy of some general economic laws of history. Here we have the notion that the forces of production and the relations of production belong to the society from which they spring; there we have the idea that the forces of production comprise a trans-historical law of labour that manifests itself in the rise and fall of historically overdetermined forms of social relations. For the critical theory tradition capitalist wealth manifests a definite conceptuality of labour, and it recovered this insight against the classical tradition, which expunged it from the critique of political economy by arguing that labour is the source of all social wealth in every form of society. Like classical political economy, it thus conceives of the production of wealth as ‘productive activity of human beings in general . . . divested . . . of every social form and determinate character’.117 According to the classical tradition, then, what makes capitalism distinctive is not the peculiar character of social labour. Rather, it is the legal entitlement of the ‘owner class’ in the means of production and the products of labour that distinguish the capitalist social relations as an historically specific form of wealth appropriation and distribution. Like the classical political economy, it fails as Marx put it in his critique of Ricardo ‘to investigate . . . the specific form in which labour manifests itself as the common element of commodities;’118 and it, too, thus regards ‘the bourgeois form of labour as the eternal natural form of social labour’, defined as a productive force of social wealth abstractly conceived.119 In comparison to the orthodox tradition, Marx’s critique does not suggest the ontologization of economic laws. Rather, it suggests their critique as the purely social forms of the actual relations of life. As the theoretical programme of critique this then formulates the task of deciphering ‘the immanent soul’ and the ‘peculiar life’ of a society that is governed by the movement of economic quantities.120 The new reading of Marx introduced a Marxism stripped off dogmatic certainties and naturalistic conceptions of society. It brought to the fore a Marx who subverts the economic object as a seemingly natural thing. However, its own critical focus was blinkered. In the face of the orthodox instrumentalization of the categories of class and labour, it sought to

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 41

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

42

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

renew critical Marxist scholarship without expounding these fundamental categories. Instead it focused on the value form to establish the living reality of the capitalist exchange relations, in which the difference between two distinct commodities becomes commensurable in the form of an equivalent exchange, in which commodities express their exchange value in the form of money. In the form of money, commodities are all the same, some abstract form of value. Indeed, since production is production for exchange value, exchange value itself becomes use-value, that is, how much value can it realize in exchange and what is its rate of profit? However, there is no profit in equivalence exchange. The circumstance that the capitalist exchange relations comprise an exchange between unequal values in the form of value equivalence requires explanation. The exchange relations cannot be fully established without a critical theory of abstract labour, class and class antagonism. The attempt to do so substitutes the critique of the actual social relations for a logical development of the value form as some secularized thing that is valid in-itself, as if value posits more value just like that, without certificate of birth.121 Capitalist wealth appears as a relationship between one commodity and another; it appears thus in the form of value, which posits itself as a force of endless self-expansion. Value enters ‘into a private relation with itself. Value therefore now becomes value in process, money in process, and, as such, capital’.122 Yet, this independent process of wealth is founded on the peculiar character of capitalist labour, which is first and foremost characterized by the commodity form of labour power, which is founded on the divorce of labour from the means of subsistence. The capital relation can spring to life only on the condition that labour power exists in the form of a commodity. Marx develops the peculiar character of the commodity form of labourpower into an argument about the peculiar character of capitalist wealth, for which the distinction between concrete labour and abstract labour is as fundamental as the class relationship. As he put it in a letter to Engels, ‘[t]he best points in my book are 1. (this is fundamental to all understanding of the facts ) the double-character of labour according to whether it is expressed in use-value or exchange value, which is brought out in the First Chapter; 2. the treatment of surplus value independent of its particular forms as profit, interest, rent, etc.’123 Capitalist profit entails the class relationship between the buyer of labour power and the producer of surplus value as seller of labour power. Thus, the peculiar social form of capitalist labour is founded on the divorce of labour from its conditions and premised on the double character of labour as concrete labour and abstract labour. It produces wealth in the form of surplus value, and the value validity of her labour manifests itself in exchange by assuming the form of money. In the dazzling form of money,

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 42

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

43

value appears akin to an automatic process – ‘the original value . . . valorizes itself independently’ and money is thrown into circulation and ‘lays golden eggs’. What appears in the exchange equivalence between unequal values (M . . . M’) is money that brought ‘forth living off-springs’.124 Marx thus conceives of the unfolding of the value form as an attempt at showing ‘the origin of this money-form’,125 and argues that it is founded on the peculiar social character of the capitalist form of labour that ‘becomes productive only by producing its opposite’, that is, value, and value is money in process and as such capital.126 Neither money nor market-based exchange relations are peculiar to capitalism. Its peculiar character is founded on the existence of a particular commodity, that is, the commodity labour power. Like any other commodity it has a use-value and an exchange value, and on the assumption that it is traded on the basis of the liberal principles of equality, liberty and utility, labour power is sold and bought by means of an equivalent exchange according to its value. The peculiar character of the commodity labour power is that its consumption can create a value greater than its own. It thus has the capacity to create surplus value, which in the form of profit is realized by means of an equivalent exchange ‘between the things themselves’.127 In the equivalent exchange relations, ‘money . . . is worth more money’ and it is this manifestation of a ‘value which is greater than itself’ that is core to Marx’s conception of capital as an automatic subject that has ‘acquired the occult ability to add value to itself’. He asks where does it get this quality from, and argues that ‘money which begets money’ entails the existence of a particular commodity whose consumption creates surplus value.128 The comprehension, then, of the value form as a mysterious thing of value equivalence does not lie within itself. Rather, and as Adorno saw it, the mysterious appearance (Schein ) of value equivalence lies in surplus value.129 What appears in the equivalent exchange between two unequal values is surplus value in the form of profit. The equivalence between unequal values is thus premised on the concept of surplus value, and therewith the class relationship between the buyer of labour power and the producer of surplus value. The following chapters develop these insights. Chapter 4 argues that the conceptuality of capitalist wealth is founded on the divorce of labour from its conditions, and this divorce, which Marx calls primitive accumulation, is the constitutive premise of the capitalist class relations. Chapter 5 develops class as the critical category of the false society. Chapter 6 unfolds the double character of labour as concrete labour and abstract labour, which Marx holds to be fundamental to the understanding of the ghost-walking of Monsieur le Capital and Madame la Terre. What appears identical in the form of abstract equivalence is ‘non-identity under the aspect of identity’.130 The following chapter explores the social praxis of a ghost-walking world.

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 43

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

44

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Notes 1 These characterizations can be found at the beginning of Marx’s critique of the fetishism of commodities, Karl Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 163–4. The term ‘sensuous-supersensible thing’ cannot be found in the English edition of Capital. Marx uses the formulation sinnlich übersinnlich twice in the German edition of Kapital, vol. I (MEW 23), pp. 85, 86, and once in his Zur Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie (Berlin 1981), p. 29. The English version translates it first as ‘transcendent’ and then as ‘sensuous things, which are at the same time suprasensible or social’ (Capital, vol. I, pp. 163, 165) and the English version of the Critique translates it as ‘an abstract thing’. Karl Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (London 1971), p. 42. I translate sinnlich übersinnlich as sensuous-supersensible in accordance with the English version of Hegel’s Phenomenology, where übersinnlich is translated as supersensible. On this, see Helmut Reichelt, ‘Social Reality as Appearance: Some Notes on Marx’s Concept of Reality’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism (Aldershot 2005). 2 On this line of argument, see also Simon Clarke, ‘Althusserian Marxism’, in ed. Simon Clarke, Terry Lovell, Kevin McDonnell, Kevin Robins and Victor Seidler, One Dimensional Marxism. Althusser and the Politics of Culture (London 1980). 3 Karl Marx, ‘Comments on James Mill, Éléments d ’ économie politique ’, in Collected Works, vol. 3 (London 1975), p. 215. 4 On this, see Simon Clarke, Marx Marginalism and Modern Sociology (London 1991). I will return to Smith’s conception of history later in this chapter when discussing the structuralist Marxist tradition. 5 Backhaus, Die Dialektik der Wertform (Freiburg 1997), p. 60. 6 As Jevons put it, ‘I do not write for mathematicians, nor as a mathematician, but as an economist wishing to convince other economists that their science can only be satisfactorily treated on an explicitly mathematical basis’. William Stanley Jevons, The Theory of Political Economy (London 1888), http://www.econlib.org/library/YPDBooks/ Jevons/jvnPE.html (accessed 4 February 2013), p. 4. 7 Marx, ‘Comments on James Mill’, p. 33. 8 Marx, A Contribution, p. 35. 9 Keynesian political economy accepts the market as an institution in which economic values are in constant flow, and recognizes that the circularity of this flow, a flow of buying and selling and reconversion of earned profits into a means of investment, is not at all guaranteed. The state is thus called upon as the public authority to maintain the circular flow of economic values, preventing leakages and stoppages for the sake of economic progress. On Keynesianism, see Simon Clarke, Keynesianism, Monetarism and the Crisis of the State (Cheltenham 1988). John Holloway, ‘The Abyss Opens: The Rise and Fall of Keynesianism’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 44

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

45

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

John Holloway, Global Capital, National State and the Politics of Money (London 1995). 10 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. III (London 1966), chap. 48. On the meaning of ‘perverted’ in this context, see chapter 1, fn. 42. 11 Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London 1990), p. 320. 12 Max Horkheimer, Kritische und Traditionelle Theorie (Frankfurt 1992), p. 207. 13 Karl Marx, Grundrisse (London 1973), pp. 87, 157. 14 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 174. 15 Joan Robinson, Economic Philosophy. An Essay on the Progress of Economic Thought (New York 1962), pp. 68, 88. 16 The point about the social validity of abstract economic laws derives from Reichelt, ‘Social Reality’. 17 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 87. 18 Robinson, Economic Philosophy, p. 68. 19 Nicholas Kaldor, ‘The Relations of Economic Growth and Cyclical Fluctuations’, Economic Journal, vol. 64, no. 253 (1954), pp. 53–71. 20 Samuel Brittan, ‘Hayek, Friedrich August (1988–1992)’, Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (Oxford 2004), http://www.oxforddnb.com/ index/51/101051095/ (accessed 28 April 2013). 21 Daniel Bell, Sociological Journey: Essays 1960 –1980 (London 1980), p. 70. This part of the argument draws on Backhaus, Dialektik. 22 Robinson, Economic Philosophy. See also Reichelt, ‘Why did Marx Conceal His Dialectical Method?’ in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn, John Holloway and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism: Emancipating Marx (London 1995). 23 Joseph Schumpeter, Das Wesen und der Hauptinhalt der theoretischen Nationalökonomie (Leipzig 1908), p. 26. 24 Joseph Schumpeter, Geschichte der ökonomischen Analyse (Göttingen 1965), pp. 35, 37. 25 Joseph Schumpeter, Theorie der wirtschaftlichen Entwicklung (Berlin 1964), p. 189. 26 Schumpeter, Geschichte. 27 Robinson, Economic Philosophy, p. 88. 28 Kunihiro Jojima, Ökonomie und Physik (Berlin 1985). 29 Jean-Baptiste Say, A Treaties on Political Economy (New York 1971). 30 Jevons, The Theory of Political Economy, conceived of the relationship between economic benefit and economic cost in terms of a relationship between pleasure and pain, which crudely put involved the pain of spending money in relation to the pleasure of purchasing a commodity. He therefore defined value in subjective terms as utility: the utility of a commodity accords value to it as an expression of pleasure over pain.

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 45

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

46

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

The cost-benefit analysis is ‘the’ economic account of life in general, see Simon Bowmaker, Economics Uncut. A Complete Guide to Life, Death, and Misadventure (Aldershot 2005). 31 Before 2008, market behaviour was buoyant as the numbers of successes seemingly spoke for themselves. Lucas who won the Nobel Prize in Economics in 1995 asserted in 2003 that the ‘problem of depressionprevention has been solved, for all practical purposes, and has in fact been solved for many decades’. Robert Lucas, ‘Macroeconomic Priorities’, American Economic Review, vol. 93, no. 1 (2003), p. 1. In 2007, he was of the view that ‘if we have learned anything from the past 20 years it is that there is a lot of stability built into the real economy’. Robert Lucas, ‘Mortgages and Monetary Policy’, The Wall Street Journal Online (19 September 2007), p. 20. David Harvey, The Enigma of Capital (Oxford 2011), reports that when, in 2008, Her Majesty Queen Elizabeth II asked her assembled economists at the London School of Economics why they had not foreseen the economic crisis, no ready response was forthcoming – the numbers had changed overnight, from boom to bust. 32 Pierre Joseph Proudhon, What is Property? An Inquiry into the Principle of Right and of Government (Teddington 2008), pp. 105–6. 33 Karl Marx, Theories of Surplus Value, vol. 3 (London 1972), p. 316. 34 Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Indianapolis 1981), p. 25. See also Israel Kirzner, ‘Human Nature and the Character of Economic Science’, Harvard Review of Philosophy, vol. VIII (2000), pp. 14–23. Samuel Brittan, Essays, Moral, Political and Economic (Edinburgh 1998). 35 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 176. The German original says ‘gegenständlicher Schein’. Marx, Das Kapital (Berlin 1979), p. 97. 36 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 168. 37 Louis Althusser, For Marx (London 1996), chap. 7. 38 Louis Althusser, ‘Preface to Capital Volume One’, in Lenin and Philosophy (New York 1971). 39 Althusser, For Marx, p. 230. 40 See Althusser, ‘Preface’, pp. 71–2. 41 Alfred Schmidt, History and Structure (Cambridge, MA 1983), p. 83. 42 On this, see Alfred Schmidt, ‘Der strukturalistische Angriff auf die Geschichte’, in ed. Alfred Schmidt, Beiträge zur marxistischen Erkenntnistheorie (Frankfurt 1969). Adorno, too, rejects the anthropological view of history and economy and its spongy rhetoric of an abstractly conceived humanism. See Dirk Braunstein, Adornos Kritik der politischen Ökonomie (Bielefeld 2011), p. 29. For Schmidt the Marx of 1844 does not illuminate the Marx of Capital. However, the Marx of Capital illuminates the Marx of 1844. Althusser’s valid critique of the ‘abstract humanism’ of the early Marx does not imply that the Marx of the critique of political economy is anti-humanistic. Rather, the ‘economic’ Marx is the humanist Marx because his critique of capitalist society seeks to decipher the actual

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 46

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

47

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

relations of life in their inverted form of economic things. The critique of political economy does not reveal trans-historical economic laws of nature nor does it argue on the basis of some abstract human essence that in capitalism exists in alienated form. The humanism of the late Marx lies in the conception of capitalism as comprising a definite form of social relations. On the idea that Man alienates herself in economic forms, see Bertell Ollman’s book Alienation (Cambridge 1977). 43 Louis Althusser, Lenin and Philosophy (New York 1971), p. 160. 44 Louis Althusser, For Marx (London 1996), p. 229. 45 Nicos Poulantzas, ‘Theorie und Geschichte: Kurze Bemerkung über den Gegenstand des “Kapitals”’, in ed. Walter Euchner and Alfred Schmdit, Kritik der politischen Ökonomie, 100 Jahre Kapital (Frankfurt 1969), p. 65. 46 On the alienated subject, see Hans- Georg Backhaus, ‘Between Philosophy and Science: Marxian Social Economy as Critical Theory’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. I, pp. 93–132 (London 1992), p. 81; On the ‘doing subject’, see John Holloway, Crack Capitalism (London 2010). 47 Wolfgang Fritz Haug, Vorlesungen zur Einführung ins ‘Kapital ’ (Hamburg 2005), p. 11. I discuss Haug’s contribution in ‘Naturalisation versus Critique of Economic Categories’, Critique. Journal of Socialist Theory, vol. 37, no. 2 (2009), pp. 279–92. 48 Joachim Hirsch, ‘The State Apparatus and Social Reproduction: Elements of a Theory of the Bourgeois State’, in ed. John Holloway and Sol Picciotto, State and Capital (London 1978), pp. 74–5, emphasis added. 49 See, for example, Bob Jessop, ‘Polar Bears and Class Struggle’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and John Holloway, Post-Fordism and Social Form (London 1991). 50 According to Harvey, ‘we can only do as nature does’. David Harvey, ‘History versus Theory: A Commentary of Marx’s Method in Capital ’, Historical Materialism, vol. 20, no. 2 (2012), p. 13. 51 Wolfgang Fritz Haug, Vorlesungen zur Einführung ins ‘Kapital’ (Hamburg 2005), p. 108. 52 Haug, Vorlesungen zur Einführung , p. 96. 53 Postone, Time, Labour and Social Domination (Cambridge 1996), p. 9. See also Simon Clarke, ‘Althusserian Marxism’, in ed. Simon Clarke, Terry Lovell, Kevin McDonnell, Kevin Robins and Victor Seidler, One Dimensional Marxism. Althusser and the Politics of Culture (London 1980). 54 Étienne Balibar, ‘The Basic Concepts of Historical Materialism’, in Louis Althusser and Étienne Balibar, Reading Capital (London 1970), p. 233. 55 Clarke, ‘Althusserian Marxism’, p. 60. 56 In this account the law of value exists twice, once as a ‘value meta-form’ that is trans-historical in its nature and which entails value as the enduring mechanism of wealth attribution and distribution in the abstract, and then there is its capitalist form as a historically specific modality of wealth

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 47

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

48

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

distribution in class-relevant terms. See Jessop, ‘Polar Bears’; Haug, Vorlesungen zur Einführung. 57 Bob Jessop, State Power: A Strategic-Relational Approach (Cambridge 2008), p. 178. 58 Patrick Murray, ‘Marx’s “Truly Social” Labour Theory of Value’, Historical Materialism, vol. 6 (Summer 2000), p. 64, fn. 21. 59 Harvey, ‘History versus Theory: A Commentary of Marx’s Method in Capital ’, p. 13. 60 Postone, Time, Labour and Social Domination, develops this point most forcefully in his critique of Marxian economics. 61 Friederich Engels, Anti-Dühring , MEW 20 (Berlin 1983), p. 106. 62 This point is most storngly made by Horkheimer, Kritische und Traditionelle Theorie, p. 246. 63 As argued most forcefully by Jacques Bidet, Exploring Marx ’s Capital: Philosophical, Economic and Political Dimensions (Chicago 2009). 64 Haug, Vorlesungen zur Einführung , p. 150. 65 Alex Callinicos, ‘Against the New Dialectic’, Historical Materialism, vol. 13, no. 2 (2005), pp. 41–59. See Vasilis Grollios, ‘Alex Callinicos’s Marxism’, Critique, vol. 41, no. 1 (2013), pp. 55–79 for a similar critique to mine. 66 This further development of the structuralist account belongs to Bob Jessop, Nicos Poulantzas: Marxist Theory and Political Strategy (London 1985). 67 Haug, Vorlesungen zur Einführung , p. 102. The force of this view remains undiminished. See, for example, Costas Lapavistas, Crisis in the Eurozone (London 2012). Alfredo Saad-Fhilo, ‘Crisis in neoliberalism or crisis of neoliberalism?’ in ed. Leo Panitch, Gregory Albo and Vivek Chibber, Socialist Register 2011 (London 2010). 68 See Althusser, ‘Preface’, pp. 71–2. 69 Clarke, ‘Althusserian Marxism’, p. 47. 70 Adam Ferguson, Essays on the History of Civil Society (Edinburgh 1966), p. 122. 71 In his critique of traditional historical materialist ideas about history as a force of its own becoming, Adorno dryly remarks that ‘historic determination is known as a metaphysical accident’. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 323. In Jessop’s terminology, society is a Fundsache – a chance discovery. See Jessop, ‘Polar Bears’, see also Bob Jessop and Ngai-Ling Sum, Beyond the Regulation Approach (Aldershot 2006) and Alain Lipietz, ‘Vom Althusserianismus zur “Theorie der Regulation”’, in ed. Alex Demirovic´, Hans-Peter Krebs and Thomas Sablowski, Hegemonie und Staat (Münster 1992). 72 On this, see Alfred Schmidt, The Concept of Nature in Marx (London 1971). 73 Schmidt, History and Structure, p. 81. 74 Terry Eagleton, Why Marx was Right (New Haven 2011), pp. 43–4.

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 48

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

49

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

75 On this definition see, Paul Samuelson, Economics: An Introductory Analysis (London 1947). 76 Lionel Robbins, An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science (London 1932). 77 Karl Marx, Zur Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie. Urtext, MEGA II.2 (Oldenbourg 1991), p. 64. 78 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 205. 79 Adorno, Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge 2008a), p. 25. 80 Althusser, For Marx, p. 237. 81 Theodor Adorno, Minima Moralia (London 1974), p. 114. 82 See Max Horkheimer, Zur Kritik der instrumentellen Vernunft (Frankfurt 1985), p. 84. 83 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 197, 11, 196. 84 Adorno’s and Horkheimer’s Dialectic of Enlightenment (London 1979), does not argue trans-historically. It analyses the historical foundation of the present. On this, see chapter IV, fn. 22. 85 Karl Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy, in Collected Works vol. 6 (London 1976). Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 248–9. Karl Marx, Critique of the Gotha Programme. 86 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 83. 87 Marx, Theories, p. 254, emphasis added, and translation altered, based on the German original. 88 Engels, Anti-Dühring , p. 132. Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 494, fn. 4. 89 Marx, Theories, pp. 165, 167. 90 Althusser’s recommendation to skip this section of Capital recognizes its challenge to the structuralist account. 91 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 706. 92 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 355, 358–60. 93 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 205. The quotation is adapted from the German original of Negative Dialektik (Frankfurt 1973), p. 205. The English version translates ‘relations of production’ as ‘conditions’, which confuses the very point that Adorno is trying to make. 94 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 358. 95 Walter Benjamin, ‘Thesis on the Philosophy of History’, in Illuminations (London 1999). 96 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 398–9. 97 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 456. 98 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 205. 99 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 188. Translation amended from the German original in Adorno, Negative Dialektik, p. 190.

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 49

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

50

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

100 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 168, 772. See also Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 355. 101 Theodor Adorno, Gesellschaftstheorie und Kulturkritik (Frankfurt 1975), p. 60. 102 Karl Marx, Contribution to the Critique of Hegel ’s ‘Philosophy of Right ’, in Collected Works, vol. 1 (London 1975), p. 182. 103 Karl Marx, ‘Theses on Feuerbach’, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London 1975). 104 Marx, Theories, p. 147. 105 Marx, A Contribution, p. 22. Marx, Theories, p. 254. 106 This point is made most forcefully by Reichelt, Zur logischen Struktur. 107 Adorno, ‘Zur Logik der Sozialwissenschaften’, in Theodor Adorno, Hans Albert, Ralf Darendorf, Jürgen Habermas, Harald Pilot and Karl Popper, Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen Soziologie (Munich 1993), p. 143. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 186, 387. 108 See, Helmut Reichelt, ‘Jürgen Habermas’ Reconstruction of Historical Materialism’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, The Politics of Change (London 2000). 109 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 255. 110 Marx, ‘Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Law’, p. 62. 111 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 166–7. 112 Reichelt, ‘Jürgen Habermas’ Reconstruction’, p. 105. 113 Marx, Theories, p. 508. Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 169. On the meaning of perversion, see chapter I, fn. 42. See also Backhaus, Dialektik der Wertform, for a critique of economic theory as a metaphysics. 114 On this, see Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 156–7. 115 Adorno, ‘Zur Logik der Sozialwissenschaften’, pp. 311, 319–20. 116 Perry Anderson, Considerations of Western Marxism (London 1976), pp. 72–3, does not agree. He notes that there is a remarkable similarity between Althusser’s structuralist account and Adorno’s Negative Dialectics. 117 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 815; translation amended. 118 Marx, Theories, p. 138. 119 Marx, A Contribution, p. 60. 120 Karl Marx, Ökonomische Manuskripte 1857/58 , MEGA II.1.1 (Berlin 1976), p. 10. 121 Chris Arthur’s, The New Dialectic and Marx ’s Capital (Leiden 2004), critical theory argues that value is ‘self-positing’. 122 Marx, Ökonomische Manuskripte, p. 256. 123 Karl Marx, ‘Letter to Engels, 24.8.1867’, Collected Works, vol. 42 (London 1987), p. 407. 124 Marx, Capital, p. 255.

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 50

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

51

POLITICAL ECONOMY AND SOCIAL CONSTITUTION

125 Marx, Capital, p. 139. See also Helmut Reichelt, ‘Zur Konstitution ökonomischer Gesellschaftlichkeit’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Michael Heinrich, Kapital & Kritik (Hamburg 2011). 126 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 305. 127 Marx, Theories, p. 127. 128 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 255–7. 129 See Adorno, ‘Mitschrift’, pp. 507–8. 130 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 5.

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 51

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

9781441161390_Ch02_Final_txt_print.indd 52

2/19/2014 3:37:09 PM

3 Society as subject and society as object: On social praxis Preamble They [the adherents of dialectical materialism] did not challenge the ideas of humanity, liberty justice as such, but merely denied the claim of our society to represent the realization of these ideas. Though they treated the ideologies as illusions, they still found them illusions of truth itself. This lent a conciliatory splendour, if not to the existent at least to its ‘objective tendencies’ . . . Ideologies were unmasked as apologetic concealments . . . [and] were rarely conceived as powerful instruments functioning in order to change liberal competitive society into a system of immediate oppression . . . Above all the leftist critics failed to notice that the ‘ideas’ themselves in their abstract form are not merely images of the truth that will later materialize but that they are ailing themselves, afflicted with the same injustice under which they are conceived and bound up with the world against which they are set.1 What divides these gentlemen from the bourgeois apologist is, on the one side, their sensitivity to the contradictions included in the system on the other, the utopian inability to grasp the necessary difference between the real and the ideal form of bourgeois society, which is the cause of their desire to undertake the superfluous business of realizing the ideal expression again, which is in fact only the inverted projection [Lichtbild] of this reality.2

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 53

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

54

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Introduction Marx’s argument that ‘the monstrous objective power which social labour itself created opposite itself as one of its moments’ is key to the critique of political economy as a critical social theory.3 Not only does he argue that the monstrous economic power is a product of social labour but also that it is beyond the control of the social individuals. He thus characterizes the commodity as a ‘sensuous supersensible thing’.4 The fetishism of commodities does not disguise the ‘real’ social relations of capitalism. Rather, the fetishism of commodities expresses the ‘real’ social relations in the form of capital as the automatic subject of bourgeois society. For the ad hominem critique of economic categories, the essence of the inverted world of economic things cannot be ‘conceived independently from its form of appearance’.5 As the previous chapter argued, the ad hominem critique is charged with cracking the relations of economic objectivity as the ‘apotheosized’ forms of the ‘actual, given relations of life’.6 It decodes economic nature on a social basis, and thus comprehends, at least, that is, its critical intension, the necessary disappearance of society in its economic appearance. It thus amounts to an attempt at deciphering the ‘immanent soul’ of the seemingly natural economic forces in order to comprehend the ‘peculiar life’7 of the ‘strange things’ that abound with ‘theological niceties’.8 The insight that ‘capital is not a thing’ but a social relationship between persons expressed as a thing entails the critique of political economy as a critical social theory.9 This chapter develops this critique in four sections. The next section follows on from the previous chapter. It argues that concepts, rather than being scientific instruments that can be applied to reality, seemingly from the outside, belong in fact to the same reality that they analyse. In this context, it assesses Lukács’s theory of reification as an entirely traditional account of the economic laws from the standpoint of labour. The following section develops this theme further by exploring Marx’s thesis that all social life is essentially practical, however perverted in the form of the economic object. Section three develops dialectics as an immanent critique of the false society. The final section argues that historical materialism is at its best a critique of things understood dogmatically. It amounts, as Sohn Rethel put it succinctly, to an anamnesis of the social origin, or genesis, of real abstractions.10

On the concept of society For a critical theory of society, the social relations of production are not historically overdetermined manifestations of general economic laws. Critical

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 54

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

55

theory argues that economic laws are purely social forms that appear as laws of economic nature. Their nature is a social nature and the genesis of the ‘monstrous objective power’ of economic laws is an entirely socially constituted monstrosity. There is thus no theoretical vantage point from which to analyse society as an object of microscopic scientific study. Social theory is immanent to its own context. Rather than analysing the actual social relations as historically specific manifestations of some general economic laws of development, it thinks out of society, and thus out of its own context, to establish the conceptuality of the existent social relations. The conceptualization of the economic categories as purely social forms entails the critique of political economy as a critique of ideology. Critically conceived, ideology is not a worldview that attributes meanings to social things from this or that moral or political standpoint. Rather, ideology is an objective term that focuses the socially necessary appearance of society, one in which human social reproduction appears in the form of a movement of incomprehensible economic quantities. The critique of political economy does not therefore reveal some ‘ontological priority of the economy’, as Lukács asserts. In Lukács account, the economy manifests ‘a second nature’,11 and nature, he says, ‘runs its course . . . according to its own dialectic, independent of the teleological projects of men’.12 The presumption of some ‘natural laws’ that govern the economic process entails the derivation of the actual relations from ‘the self-development of the economy’.13 Lukács’s account ‘remains dogmatic’.14 It identifies society as an ‘as if’ of developed economic nature. Instead of deciphering the appearance of economic nature on a social basis, his ‘tireless charge of reification’ posits this socially constituted economic nature as the ontological premise of society.15 He thus naturalizes the economic forms and condemns their capitalist mode of functioning (Wirkungsweise ) from the standpoint of labour, as the ‘as if’ of socialist rationalization. For a critical theory of political economy the perception of capitalist economic laws as historically overdetermined laws of economic nature expresses the fetishism of commodities in ideological form – it posits society unaware of itself as the premise of its theoretical dogma to lead ‘the struggling masses, to show them the way’ towards the socialist manifestation of economic necessity, conceived abstractly as a necessity of nature.16 In contrast to Lukács’s theory of reification, Adorno’s critical theory refuses ‘to lend itself to sanctioning things as they are’. Intended as a theory without ‘affirmative traits’, it purports to demystify rigidified, thing-like, congealed relationships, rendering their immediacy transparent – as socially constituted things.17 For example, Marx writes that in the money fetish, ‘a social relation, a definite relation between individuals . . . appears as a metal, a stone, as a purely physical external thing which can be found, as such, in nature, and

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 55

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

56

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

which is indistinguishable in form from its natural existence’.18 There is only one world, and that is the world of appearance. However, what is appearance an appearance of, and what appears in appearance? Social objectivity ‘does not lead a life of its own’.19 The relationship between coins is a socially constituted relationship of economic objectivity – the social relations vanish in their economic appearance as a relationship between coined metals, and this appearance is real – it imposes itself over the social individuals because it prevails in and through them. What appears in the appearance of society as a ‘stone’, or a ‘coin’, is thus a definite social relationship between individuals subsisting as a relationship between ‘coins’. Adorno therefore argues that ‘all concepts, even the philosophical ones, refer to non-conceptualities’.20 Say, the economic concept of profit entails what it is not; that is, it entails the definite social relations between individuals as the vanished premise of its economic force. What has vanished cannot be conceptualized. Man is not visible in the movement of economic quantities, and appears as a metaphysical distraction to the economic analysis of all things economic. This distraction is all-important. Capital is not ‘a very mystic being’ of nature. It is ‘a very mystic being’ of a definite form of social relations.21 Critically conceived, historical materialism opens ‘up the non-conceptual with the aid of the concept, without reducing it to the concept’.22 It thus explores the economic concept from within, and as such ‘extinguishes the autarky of the concept, strips the blindfold from our eyes. That the concept is a concept even when dealing with things in being does not change the fact that on its part it is entwined with a non-conceptual whole’, that is, Man in her actual relations of life as a personification of her own reified world.23 Adorno’s insight is fundamental to the understanding of Marx’s critique of political economy as a critical social theory. In the face of mythical economic properties, it rejects the ‘scientific doctrine of invariants’ and instead ‘aims at the thing itself’ from within its ‘own context’ in order to grasp its social nature.24 Chris Arthur rightly commends Adorno for having understood that capitalism has a specific conceptuality, and that therefore conceptuality ‘holds sway in reality (Sache ) itself.’25 In the critical tradition, conceptualization therefore does not mean the expounding of meta-theories, which, by means of infinite regress, finishes up akin to the doctrine of the Invisible Hand with deist conceptions of social existence, whether in their religious form of the power of the Almighty or their secularized forms of the so-called logic of ‘selfdeveloping’ economic things. Instead, it grounds the existence of invisible principles in definite social relations, argues that it is these that produce their own enslavement to the invisible, whether in its religious form of God or secularized form of price movements. Furthermore, conceptuality does not also entail the explanation of one thing by reference to another. Such thought

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 56

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

57

moves from one thing to another in an attempt to render its terms coherent by means of external reference. The state is explained by reference to the economic, and the economic by reference to the state. Similarly, demand is explained by supply and supply by demand. By means of vicious circularity, then, explanation becomes tautological. Further, conceptuality does not mean the discovery of natural laws, like, for example, the natural tendency of Man to barter, as Adam Smith alleged. That Man has to eat says nothing about her mode of subsistence and the social necessities that a mode of subsistence entails – so-called social laws. Society, not nature, is the point of critical departure. Conceptualization means to bring the thing to its concept [die Sache auf den Begriff bringen, der Begriff der Sache]. It has to do with the recognition of reality – not with the analysis of given socio-economic data. Conceptualization goes beyond the perception of reality in its immediate appearance as one governed by the movement of coins. For a critical theory of society, concepts ‘are moments of a reality that requires their formation’.26 They do not mirror society. They explore society from within, expounding its coined reality. The comprehension of things is therefore not the same as their identification qua definition, or indeed ‘registration in a system governed by, for example, ideal-types’. To comprehend things means to recognize their existence in connection not with other things but in and through them.27 Thinking by means of definition or identification is quite able to say what something comes under, what it illustrates, exemplifies or represents. It does not, however, say what the thing is. Thinking, as Adorno saw it, is essentially the negation of things in their dazzling appearance.28 Conceptualization thus means to subvert the immediate appearance of things in order to recognize them in their now pregnant immediacy – a mediated immediacy [vermittelte Unmittelbarkeit ]. As a critical social theory, the critique of political economy does not bow to economic things. It wants to know what they are, and what they are is within them. It does not pretend that the immediate appearance of things is unreal; nor does it simply negate the world of appearances as if it were no more than a veil that hides the real human being in her social relations. Rather it recognizes society for what it is: ‘the human being itself in its social relations’, however perverted these relations appear in their inverted form of a movement of coined economic forces.29 As a social product, the reified world is a human world. As such, it manifests the ‘objective necessity’ of the existing relations of social reproduction, ‘to which we owe everything and that yet [threaten] to bury us all’.30 Thus, conceptualization does not mean ‘thinking’ about things. Rather, it means thinking out of things.31 If it were really about things, then conceptualization would be external to its subject matter. Thought that does

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 57

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

58

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

not go into its object does not recognize its object. Instead, it hypostatizes the social object as a natural thing, and by doing so, analyses it as an ‘as if’ of theoretical construction. By hypothesizing the objective world it hypothesizes itself as the scientific consciousness of some general economic laws in being and becoming.32 Such thought is able to name and order things but cannot tell us what they are. On the one hand, its critique of reality is a moral one, proclaiming for the ideas of ‘humanity, liberty, and justice’ in abstraction from society.33 In its vulgar version, on the other hand, it operates akin to a cash register – eager to calculate and predict the movement of economic quantities with winning intent, without asking itself, and indeed rejecting the question itself as an unscientific metaphysical diversion, what these quantities might be. For instance does ‘price of labour amount to a yellow logarithm’ or is, say, £10 an hour just and fair?34 Whatever its fairness or unfairness, analytical thinking does not bring the wage relation to its concept. Instead it offers a view about the manner in which social wealth is distributed, without scrutinizing the conceptuality of the capitalist form of wealth that rests on an equivalent exchange between the buyers of labour power and the producers of surplus value. Why has human labour power acquired the form of a commodity? What laws of necessity exist in a society in which a whole class of individuals is compelled to sell their labour power in order to gain access to the means of subsistence? What does it mean to say that maintaining this access depends on the progressive accumulation of the surplus value that the buyer of labour power extracted from the labourer during the working day? That is, reification really is an epiphenomenon. What is reified and what therefore appears in reification? The social relations assert themselves in the reified form of coins that move in fateful ways, determining the access to the means of subsistence for the class tight to work, and the rate of return on somebody else’s labour for the buyers of labour power. To be a productive labourer, says Marx, ‘is not a piece of luck but a misfortune’, and it this misfortune that asserts itself in the inverted form of a coined freedom, in which the progressive accumulation of extracted surplus value is the condition of achieving a labour contract that provides access to subsistence.35 In order to understand things, one has to be within them. The work of the concept [die Arbeit des Begriffs ] is immanent to its own social context. The concept, of course, does not work. We do. The work of the concept thus means to be led by thought without fear of where that might take us. Fundamentally, its purpose is a subversive one. 36 It turns the relations of economic objectivity upside down to find their rational explanation in the comprehension of human practice. What belongs to the constituted conceptuality of, say, the form of money? Is it a cunningly conceived technical instrument of economic calculation and medium of exchange that

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 58

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

59

emerges from the pursuit of individual self-interest and comes to express the collective wisdom of society, as Menger argues?37 Or is it the dazzling form of capitalist wealth? What lies within its dazzling concept? Revealing the constituted conceptuality of things entails discovery of their ‘immanent soul’ and ‘peculiar life’; it entails understanding their mode of motion [Bewegungsweise ], their capacity and power [Macht ], their constituted force and social necessity. Conceptualization thus means articulating what is active in things and comprehending the violence that is hidden within their civilized appearance as an exchange between property owners who in spite of their manifest inequality in the ownership of the means of subsistence are ‘equal in the eyes of the law’ and who thus contract with each other by their own free will, each pursuing their own interest in this ‘Eden of the innate rights of Man’ that substitutes direct, personal coercion with forms of abstract dependency, with economic compulsion. 38 The individuals are governed by abstractions, and their life-circumstances really are dependent on the movement of economic quantities. Economic compulsion is a force of great misery that appears in the form of contractual freedom, according to which nobody is obliged to anybody in particular and therefore everybody is responsible for themselves. The freedom of contract thus entails the force of ‘silent economic compulsion’ that brings under its sway a whole class of individuals who possess no other property than their labour power and who must therefore by necessity become the selfresponsible ‘slave of other individuals who have made themselves the owners of the means of human existence’.39 That is to say, ‘the class relationship makes up the objective motor of the production process’, and it is the profitable extraction of surplus value from living labour upon which the social reproduction of a whole class of dependent sellers of labour power depends in its entirety.40 The higher the rate of return on exploited labour, the greater the prospects for the labourer to achieve a contract of future employment. The world of economic rationality is a perverted world. The critical effort at deciphering the conceptuality of objective economic forms works against its own tendency. Its critical intent is to demystify the fetish; however, to conceptualize means to identify. Identification does not crush the fetish; it affirms it. Conceptualization is thus itself contradictory – it has to think against itself in order to reveal things. In short, the conceptualization of economic things as the objectified (vergegenständlichte ) forces of the actual relations of life entails more than just their identification as ‘perverted’ social forces. Fundamentally, it entails the recognition of the sheer unrest of life as the non-conceptual premise of the constituted economic forms.41 That is, the conceptualization of economic things entails not only the recognition of their contradictory, fractured, fragmented and indeed antagonistic character,

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 59

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

60

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

it also entails the understanding that capitalist society does not reproduce itself despite the social antagonism. Rather, it ‘maintains itself only through antagonism’.42 The antagonistic character of bourgeois society is immanent to its concept. Society is the appearance of disunity in the unity of its concept. The social antagonism asserts itself not only over the social individuals, it asserts itself also in and through the social individuals who for the sake of their life ‘react under the compulsion’ of the movement of economic quantities, sustaining themselves as ‘personifications of economic categories’.43

On social praxis ‘All social life is essentially practical.’ This, from Marx’s 8th Feuerbach thesis, includes thinking. Thinking is part of social life and all social life is essentially practical. The thesis continues: ‘All mysteries which lead theory to mysticism find their rational explanation in human practice and in the comprehension of this practice.’ The thesis is clear and at the same time most difficult. Thought is to reveal reality by demystifying it, and demystification is a matter of comprehending the human practice that is not immediately visible in the mysterious social forms. Human practice is deemed essential as the foundation of the social mysteries, and thought’s purpose is a subversive one: it is to reveal the hidden social essence of mysterious things.44 For thought to be thought it needs to comprehend human practice, or as Marx put it in Capital, ‘develop from the actual, given relations of life the form in which these have been apotheosized’.45 The comprehension of human practice demystifies the world of economic things. And here the difficulties start. What human practice has Marx in mind and where might it be found? The appearance of human practice in the world as we know it does not show the human practice whose comprehension alone is said to explain it. Marx’s thesis suggests that human practice needs to be discovered by thought in order to comprehend the mysticism of its own appearance in the form of an economic object that possesses the obscure quality of positing unequal values as equal in equivalence exchange (M . . . M’). In the form of an economic relationship between price and product, human practice is the practice of coined economic agents, who sustain ‘the unconscious society’ by their own rational action.46 What appears in appearance is the enchanted world of capitalist wealth that in the form of value asserts itself as if it were a force of nature. What sort of human practice do we have to comprehend for the sake of demystification and which practice is the valid one? And this in a society where the living have been replaced by the dead that is, by the actions of economic things.47

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 60

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

61

The problem analysed here is well focused by Helmut Reichelt. Expounding on Marx’s critique of fetishism – human social relations appear as relations between things and this appearance is real – he argues that capitalist exchange relations suggest that rationally acting subjects meet freely in the marketplace to realize their rational interests, whereas in fact they act as executives of abstract social laws which they themselves have generated historically and reproduce through their rational behaviour, and over which they have no control. The perception of society thus ensues from within the subjects who . . . make contracts in the sphere of circulation, where they deal in mysterious economic forms with so-called ‘goods’, and who have always already perceived of each other as equal and free subjects of law, and who, prior to this thinly veiled perception of themselves as independent subjects, experience class society as one of inequality, exploitation and rule by an autonomised system.48 Society is thus experienced not only as a class society based on inequality, exploitation and domination, it is also experienced as a ‘real abstraction’, that is, it entails both chance and necessity, which are experienced as ‘fate’. The supersensible world of real abstractions subsists thus ‘not merely over people’s heads, but through them’. That is, it ‘prevails over mankind as something that prevails in them’.49 Sensuous practice is contained within the enchanted world of real abstractions as ‘that which has not been included’ in its concept.50 The world of economic forces expresses sensuous human practice in the form of a ‘social hieroglyphic’.51 Value, thus, asserts itself as the autonomic subject of more value, instantiating, as Arthur sees it, its own self-valorization.52 However, the power of value to instantiate its own expansion, ‘passes not merely over people’s heads, but through them’.53 That is to say, the supersensible world contains the social individual within itself as the sensuous personification of her own reified social world. The circumstance that subjective rational behaviour subsists through a context of objective irrationality, that is, beyond human control, makes society appear as an objectively unfolding force. Traditionally this unfolding is analysed as a relationship between the forces of production and the social relations of production that comprise the actions of the social classes and other social groups within an overdetermined structured framework of economic laws. Human action unfolds within an objective framework. This view is widely shared, from Hayek’s praise of the logic of the market as the best possible framework for the pursuit of individual autonomy, to Althusser’s theory of capitalism as an historically overdetermined structure of the general economic laws, and Habermas’s dualist differentiation of reality

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 61

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

62

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

into life-world and system-world.54 If, as Marx claims, the comprehension of human practice really is key to the comprehension of the enchanted world of economic objects, can this same human practice be derived from those same things whose comprehension is said to depend on the understanding of human practice? Instead of being demystified, the world of things would be affirmed in every conceivable way. The idea that ‘society is subject to natural laws is ideology if it is hypostasized as immutably given by nature’.55 The fetishism of commodities expresses the social nature of the inverted [verkehrte ] and perverted [verrückte] world of definite social relations that vanish in the ‘theological niceties’ of ‘strange things’ only to reappear as the living character masks of economic categories. Social reproduction is governed by the movement of coins that structure the social relations – and yet, the systemic property of the economic laws is entirely social: ‘their own movement within society has for them the form of a movement made by things, and these things, far from being under their control, in fact control them.’56 Marx’s thesis that the understanding of the world of things has to comprehend human practice implies that this practice is constitutive. However, this formulation is full of dangers, too. It invites, argues Adorno, the ‘liquidation of everything thinglike regressed to the subjectivism of the pure act’ of human doing.57 Does human doing remain external to its own perverted social product? Negri says that capital is a ‘bewitching force’ whose power is such that the doing, or the constitutive subject is, as it were, sucked into capital.58 The real power, it seems, is not the constitutive but the constituted subject. There is, however, only one reality, the recognition of which is fundamental to the ad hominem critique of political economy.59 It does not disregard its object of critique by elevating human subjective ‘doing’ into a natural social essence.60 The essence of capitalist society is capital itself, and capital is fundamentally just a name of a definite form of social relations. Nor does it mock the human subject by declaring it redundant.61 The meaning of objectivity excludes the possibility that it can also be a subject. However, there can be no subject without objectification. Detached from objectivity, subjectivity amounts to a pure being of nothingness, without time and place, that, always ready to denounce and condemn, asserts its existence for this or that cause of action because of itself, indifferent to social contents.62 As a subject of action for its own sake, it proclaims mastery over a world that has completely devoured it. The critical intension of what Adorno called the ad hominem critique of political economy is the demystification of value as a supersensible economic force. It argues that value is in fact a sensuous, supersensible thing. Within itself, it contains the sensuous practice of the actual relations of life as its

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 62

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

63

constitutive premise. Sensuous practice exists in and through those same supersensible things that govern the social individuals as personifications of their own social world. Adorno captures this idea of a socially constituted world of inverted supersensible things well: ‘The supersensible world, which is the inverted world, has thus transcended the other world [the sensuous world – WB] and contains it within itself; for itself as inverted world, that is, inverted in and of itself, it is itself and its opposite in their unity.’63 Rather than replacing the object by the subject, be it the subject of history as an objectively unfolding force or Man herself as being in alienation, or indeed, economic being as an ontological force that, in the last instance, colonizes the life-world of social action, the critique of political economy sets out to comprehend the social subject in the form of the object, which is the mode of existence of the subject. Just as objectivity without the subject is nonsense, subjectivity detached from its object is fictitious. Man is a social being qua objectification [Vergegenständlichung ]. Man is always objectified Man. Subjectivity means objectification. To be an object is part of the meaning of subjectivity. The issue that the critique of fetishism brings to the fore is not the subject’s objectification but its reified mode. Appearance [Schein] ‘is the enchantment of the subject in its own world’.64 The circumstance that objectification exists in the form of an independent movement of ‘value in process, money in process, and, as such, capital’ does not imply that there is an as yet undiscovered, and indeed undiscoverable, ontologically conceived economic logic that lies solely within the thing itself.65 Only as a socially determinate object can the object be an object.66 Value is a relation between persons expressed as a relation between things and this relationship between things governs over and prevails in the social individuals. They are the living premise of real economic abstractions and subsist in their own social world as the human resource of ‘capital in process’. The social world is the objective world of real economic abstractions, and the economic world is therefore an objective illusion. As Debord puts it: ‘in a world which really is topsy-turvy, the true is a moment of the false.’ Truth exists as an existing untruth. Yet, it is true all the same.67

On the appearance of essence ‘All science would be superfluous if the outward appearance of things and the essence of things directly coincided.’68 Nor do essence and appearance coincide directly, or belong to distinct realities. Essence must appear. If it does not, then it is not essence; conversely, appearance must be the appearance

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 63

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

64

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

of essence or it is nothing. There is only one reality – a reality of disunion, contradiction, fissures and antagonism; and thus a reality where subject and object are inverted in a topsy-turvy way.69 The distinction between essence and appearance exists within the things by means of an irreconcilable, antagonistic, restless unity. Disunity subsists against itself in the form of unity. Disunity in the form of unity entails coercion as the condition of unity. It is within the concept of society, in its internality and immanence that the non-coincidence of essence and appearance exists in the form of a coerced and coercive unity. Disunity in the form of unity entails a social reality that is antagonistic from the outset.70 The social antagonism holds sway in the concept of capitalist society. Society is torn by contradictions and in antagonistic battle and reproduces itself by virtue of its contradictions and antagonism. Antagonism is not only a relationship of battle; it is also a relationship of mutual dependency of a disunited social unity. The class relationship between capital and labour is the relationship of social reproduction, and for the sellers of labour power access to the means of subsistence depends on the progressive accumulation of their living labour on the pyramids of abstract wealth that feeds onto itself in a crisis-ridden effort of avoiding ruin. Thus, the concept of reality is divided within itself: mutual dependency exists qua antagonism, and unity exists qua disunity. Its reality contains within itself what it denies. It manifests movements of economic quantities that deny the social antagonism that threatens to force its reality apart, beyond itself. And yet the concept of economy is not one of antagonism but of unity established by the circular flow of economic quantities. The living-fate of the individuals depends on the movement of these quantities. Fate is a category of a ghostlike society; the ‘mystic being of capital’ prevails in the social individuals as ‘bearers of particular class-relations and interests’.71 Hegel’s notion that essence has to appear does not mean that the human subject makes an appearance by asserting itself against the world of things – say, in terms of a conception of class struggle as a force that, from the outside, breaks into the capital relation during periods of crisis.72 Hegel’s notion that essence has to appear means that essence cannot choose not to appear. It is forced to appear – it is as if essence is coerced to appear in its own inhospitable world, that what makes essence essential subsists in appearance. Its appearance is thus at the same time its disappearance. The necessity of its appearance entails that it vanishes in its appearance. The law of essence is its disappearance qua appearance. That is, in the ‘enchanted and perverted’ world of capital,73 essence appears in the form of value and as such it appears as a force of constant valorization that manifests itself in the form of profit.74 Value becomes visible in the money form. Money is thrown into circulation to make more money. The essence of society appears thus as an automatic process of

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 64

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

65

‘money which is worth more money, value which is greater than itself’.75 In this peculiar form of wealth, material wealth in the form of use values, things for use, becomes the form of manifesting its opposite, that is, value, which is wealth in ‘abstraction from their use-values’.76 Money does not express use values. It expresses exchange value and exchange value entails the conceptuality of money as capital that, in its restless pursuit of social wealth, is nothing unless it begets more money. The circumstance that the essence of society disappears in its appearance as an automatic force of abstract wealth is as real as the fact that, on the other hand, there would be ‘nothing without individuals and their spontaneities’.77 Sohn Rethel’s conception of historical materialism as the anamnesis of the genesis of mysterious economic forms is thus to the point. It focuses ‘the monstrous objective power’ of capital as a real abstraction that originates ‘in the peculiar social character of the labour that produces them’.78 The actual relations of life disappear in the form of a movement of abstract economic quantities, and yet what disappears in its appearance is the constitutive premise of the entire system of economic things. The forces of production belong to the inverted reality of the actual relations of life, in which Man is ‘governed by the products of his own hand’.79 Here he appears as a mere ‘human’ embodiment of the abstract economic forces, on the movement of which her life hangs by. In the world of economic objectivity, the person appears as an investor in her own labour power, and thus as an entrepreneur of labour power, seeking to maintain access to the means of subsistence by maintaining her employability as an effective producer of surplus value. The positivity of facts is deceitful. It hides what they are; yet when confronted with what they are, the spell of positivity looses its magic, revealing the violence and coercion that created and sustains the law of value. The law of value obtains through what it denies, that is, the force of value, which compels a whole class of dispossessed individuals to produce surplus value as sellers of labour power, for the sake of making a living. The traditional attempt at seeking empirical validation for theoretical pronouncements about the probability of the economic lines of development upholds an identity between thought and thing that is ‘inextricably entwined with the structure of reality itself’.80 Reality is identified on the basis of its immediate and direct appearance – as if the fact of a given economic quantity really speaks for itself. The mistake, says Adorno, ‘in traditional thinking is that identity is taken for the goal’.81 The circumstance that the ‘appearance of things hides their genesis’82 in human social relations entails a programme of critique that deciphers ‘the hieroglyphic’.83 The economic law of factor competitiveness is the appearance of living labour as productive power. Critique’s enlightening intent is to make visible what is hidden in things. It comprehends essence in its appearance, that is, as a disappeared essence. Adorno captures this

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 65

2/19/2014 3:37:42 PM

66

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

appearance qua disappearance when he argues that essence [Wesen] is first of all the fatal mischief [Unwesen] of a world that degrades men to means of real abstractions that rule over and prevail in them.84 Essence exists in the mode of economic things – as mischief. That is to say, sensuous human practice subsists against itself in the form of, say, freedom as wage slavery. The ‘perverted [verrückte] form’85 of value manifests thus the mode of existence of human purposeful activity in the form of ‘quasi objective, impersonal social forms expressed by categories such as the commodity and value’. These categories ‘do not simply disguise the “real” social relations of capitalism (that is, class relations); rather, the abstract social structures expressed by those categories are those “real” social relations.’86 As a movement of value, capital is therefore neither an assortment of economic quantities that can be moved from here to there, applied in this trade or that industry. Fundamentally, capital is ‘only a name’,87 and every individual capital is at the same time the capital.88 Fundamentally, it is the name of a peculiar form of social reproduction. Capital therefore really is the ‘autonomic subject’ of bourgeois society: not as a personal subject but, rather, as an impersonal subject that asserts itself as if by force of nature. It posits wealth as ever-expanding wealth, restless in its pursuit of more wealth for its own sake. In this dynamic, money is the constantly vanishing appearance of wealth. It ‘appears only fleetingly, or its substance consists only in this constant appearance as disappearance’.89 In the form of money, the law of wealth as more wealth (M . . . M’) asserts itself as capitalist wealth ‘par excellence’, and, that is, it asserts itself as the ‘consummate automatic fetish, the self-expanding value, the money making money, and in this form it no longer bears any trace of its origin’.90 This then is, the ‘“most unintelligible form” of wealth that posits “pure madness” (reine Verrücktheit )’.91 Yet, money in the form of capital (M . . . M’) posits itself as more money only on the condition that it maintains its relationship to labour as the productive power of surplus value. ‘Money is labour time in the form of the general object.’92 It assumes the form of an ‘automatic fetish’ in which it ‘antecedes its own process of reproduction’.93 In this appearance, money begets more money seemingly by investing into itself. The disappearance of its origin in the labour of surplus value production appears in the form of financial crisis. The necessity of its affirmation qua destruction – discussed by Marx as the socially constituted dialectic between the forces and the relations of production – manifests the premise of labour within the concept of capital. Labour has to produce surplus value for money to maintain value validity. Destruction is the constituted nightmare of the capitalist mode of social reproduction: Society suddenly finds itself put back into a state of momentary barbarism; it appears as if famine, a universal war of devastation had cut off the

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 66

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

67

supply of every means of subsistence; industry and commerce seem to be destroyed; and why? Because there is too much civilisation, too much means of subsistence; too much industry, too much commerce. The productive forces at the disposal of society no longer tend to further the development of the conditions of bourgeois property; on the contrary, they have become too powerful for these conditions, by which they are fettered, and so soon as they overcome these fetters, they bring disorder into the whole of bourgeois society, endanger the existence of bourgeois property. The conditions of bourgeois society are too narrow to comprise the wealth created by them. And how does bourgeois society get over these crises? On the one hand by enforced destruction of a mass of productive forces; on the other, by the conquest of new markets, and by the more thorough exploitation of the old ones.94 This commentary by the 29-year-old Marx is not a brilliant anticipation of globalization and its crisis, which given the horrors of the last century, would anyway have turned out to be far too optimistic. Rather, it conceptualizes the critical subject and, in doing so, shows what lies within it. What lies within it is its social nature. Creation qua destruction is a valid necessity of capitalist social relations – it belongs to its conceptuality [Begrifflichkeit ], that is, the critique of political economy discloses the conceptualized praxis (begriffene Praxis ) of the capitalist social relations.95 ‘Conceptuality expresses the fact that, no matter how much blame may attach to the subject’s contribution, the conceived world is not its own but a world hostile to the subject.’96 Man vanishes in her economic appearance and her own sensuous practice manifests itself as the practice of supersensible things that make the world go round. Value is not a self-standing concept. It does nothing and has no ontological force. It depends on what its appearance denies, the non-conceptual renders its concept ‘objectively valid’.97 In a world governed by real abstractions, ‘society as subject and society as object are the same and yet not the same’.98 Reason exists in irrational form. It exists in the form of real abstractions – of price and profit, unit labour costs and human factors of production.

Expounding irrational social forms: On dialectics Dialectics is not a formal procedure or method applied to reality to determine the enduring structures of economic necessity in the anatomy of bourgeois social relations. The much-praised dialectics between structure and agency

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 67

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

68

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

is not helpful. It moves in vicious circles as it hops from structure to agency, and back again, from agency to structure; and instead of comprehending what they are, each is presupposed in a tautological movement of thought; neither is explained. The dialectical method is also not to be confused with the so-called dialectics of history that presumes the existence of transhistorical forces of production, which progress through history effecting the rise and fall of definite social forms of production. Socialism, says Lukács, is the ‘necessary product of the internal dialectic of social being, of the selfdevelopment of the economy [ . . . ] as well as of the class struggle’.99 This view of history as the becoming of socialism is absurd. Dialectics is not a theology of history. Neither is dialectics some magic wand. The circumstance that, in capitalism, human beings enter into relationships with one another as character masks of value says that the individuals vanish in their economic appearance. Thus, the demand that thought is adequate to its subject matter entails more than it bargains for. Its adequacy cannot be established by means of falsification or verification. There is no verifiable ‘it is’. To say that something ‘is’ already casts doubt on the proclaimed identification of the ‘it’. To bring things to their concept requires that concepts are open to the living experience of the thing. The freedom of the wage contract challenges the concept of freedom in its experience. Dialectics opens concepts. It focuses on social contents and does so by moving within their social forms. It is tasked with subverting the economic categories by revealing their social basis; and rather than translating our consciousness of them into the ‘doctrinaire language’ of natural economic necessity,100 it dissolves their dogmatic posture by negating ‘the whole sphere it moves in’.101 It affirms nothing – it really is a ‘critique of the entire system of economic categories’.102 That is, it demystifies the monstrous economic forms as a socially constituted reality that asserts itself behind the backs of those same social individuals who comprise and sustain it. Dialectics says ‘no more, to begin with, than that objects do not go into their concepts without leaving a remainder’. There is no concept of, say, value without the experience of value. Value does not experience itself. Experience is a sensuous category of lived objectification (Vergegenständlichung ). By means of this ‘cogitative confrontation of concept and thing’,103 dialectics articulates the real life-activity of the capitalist social forms as the definite social practice of ‘active humanity’, however perverted its activity might be in the form of capital as an automatic subject that prevails over, in and through society.104 The dialectical method amounts thus to a generic exposition of the categories of political economy. Its purpose is to grasp the ‘relations between humans’ in their perverted form of economic objectification.105 The content of economic categories contradicts their economic form of appearance. However much

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 68

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

69

value appears as an independent force of its own self-expansion, valorizing value for the sake of valorization, it is a social form of human reproduction. The circumstance that the capitalist form of social wealth is ‘hostile’ (Adorno) to the human subject highlights the perverted character of this definite form of ‘social relations between men themselves’.106 As an ad hominem critique, the critique of political economy confronts the constituted reality of the economic forces, and by means of generic exposition, comprehends them as the automatic forms of definite social relations. Concepts do not refer to God or Nature, or to themselves. ‘All concepts refer to non-conceptualities’,107 and as I discussed at the start of this chapter, the non-conceptual comprises the actual relations of life in their existent ‘forms of appearance’ – of mischievous economic things. That is, Man in her social relations exists in the ‘mode of being denied’.108 In the critical theory tradition of the critique of political economy, dialectics is not a form of thought that pacifies the contradiction, nor does it reconcile the antagonism by means of formalistic indifference to social contents. Dialectics is rather a method of presenting the economic categories on a social basis, bringing to the fore the social origin of a topsy-turvy world. Adorno thus conceived of dialectics as ‘the consistent sense of non-identity’. Non-identity is immanent to the movement of reified economic forces. The supersensible world is neither natural nor divine. It is a world of the actual relations of life, and the circumstance that these relations manifest themselves in the form of the economic object defines its negative character. Dialectics thinks against the dazzling spell of the world of value. That is, it thinks against the flow of the world, ‘in contradictions, for the sake of the contradiction once experienced in the thing, and against that contradiction’. It is thus ‘suspicious of all identity’.109 Reification is real, but its concept contains more than it cares to reveal. Reality is divided within itself. The resolution to the dialectical context of immanence is that context itself.

Conclusion No theory ‘escapes the market place’, including that theory which flouts tradition.110 A critical theory flouts tradition only for as long as it retains consciousness of its own entanglement with the ‘false’ world of economic inversion.111 It maintains this consciousness by thinking in and through society developing the conceptuality of capital as a social relationship expressed as a relationship between things that prevails not only over the individuals but also in and through them. Capitalist society reproduces itself not despite the class

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 69

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

70

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

antagonism. It reproduces itself by virtue of the class antagonism. The class antagonism is immanent to its concept. The chapter has argued that ‘human sensuous practice subsists through its supersensible existence in the autonomisation of society as both the object and subject of its perverted social practice’.112 The critique of reification is thus not about reified things as such. Rather, the reified world of economic quantities finds its rational explanation in the comprehension of the actual social relations that constitute and sustain it, and disappear in their economic appearance as a dependent factor of production. In distinction to traditional conceptions of historical materialism, which assign a material force to history with the result that history becomes a ‘basic ontological structure of things in being’,113 at its best historical materialism amounts to a critique of economic nature, one that deciphers the movement of real economic abstractions as the necessary manifestation of actual social relations. It therefore does not mock the human subject as a metaphysical nuisance. As a critical social theory, historical materialism goes to the root of the matter, and the root of the matter is immanent to its own social context. It thus dissolves the dogmatic posture of the relations of economic objectivity by revealing their social genesis, grounding the economic forces in the social relations of production. The following chapter explores the social foundation of the capitalist social relations. It argues that the primitive accumulation of capital is the constitutive premise of capitalist society.

Notes 1 Adorno, ‘Spengler Today’, Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung , no. 9 (1941), p. 318. 2 Marx, Grundrisse (London 1973), pp. 248–9. 3 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 832. 4 On this characterization of society, see Chapter 2, fn. 1. 5 Helmut Reichelt, ‘Social Reality as Appearance: Some Notes on Marx’s Concept of Reality’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism (Aldershot 2005), p. 36. 6 Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 494, fn. 4. On the meaning of ‘cracking’, see Holloway, Crack Capitalism (London 2010). 7 Karl Marx, Ökonomische Manuskripte 1857/58 , MEGA II.1.1 (Berlin 1976), p. 10. 8 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 163.

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 70

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

71

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

9 Marx, Capital, vol. III (London 1966), p. 814. 10 Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Warenform und Denkform (Frankfurt 1978), p. 139. The German original says: ‘Historischer Materialismus ist Anamnesis der Genese.’ Sohn Rethel also coined the phrase ‘real abstraction’ to capture the independent movement of economic things that move seemingly by their own volition. Yet, they do not. Their movement expresses the ‘automaticity’ of an inverted society, which, in the form of the economic object, is unaware of itself. In Marx’s words: the individuals ‘do this without being aware of it’. Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 166–7. Still, awareness does not stop the movement of society as an economic abstraction either. For this to happen, the social relations of production need to be changed. 11 Georg Lukács, Marx ’s Basic Ontological Principles (London 1978), pp. 10, 160. 12 Georg Lukács, Conversations with Lukács, ed. Theodor Pinkus (Cambridge, MA 1975), p. 74. For an argument about the origins of this stance in classical political economy, see Chapter 2, section II. 13 Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness (London 1971), p. 306. Lukács, Marx ’s Basic, p. 159. 14 Theodor Adorno, ‘Reconciliation under Duress’, in Ernst Bloch, Georg Lukács, Bertold Brecht, Walter Benjamin and Theodor Adorno, Aesthetics and Politics (London 1980), p. 154. See also Simon Clarke, Marx, Marginalism and Modern Sociology (London 1991), pp. 315–17. 15 Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London 1990), p. 191. 16 Georg Lukács, Lenin: A Study in the Unity of his Thought (London 1997), p. 35. For a rigorous examination of Lukács along the lines suggested here, see Vasilis Grollios, ‘Dialectics and Democracy in Georg Lukács’s Marxism’, Capital & Class (forthcoming) and Joe Fracchia, ‘The Philosophical Lenin and Eastern “Western Marxism” of Georg Lukács’, Historial Materialism, vol. 21, no. 1 (2013), pp. 68–93. 17 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 159. 18 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 239. 19 Adorno, ‘Zur Logik der Sozialwissenschaften’, Theodor Adorno, Hans Albert, Ralf Darendorf, Jürgen Habermas, Harald Pilot and Karl Popper, Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen Soziologie (Munich 1993), p. 127. 20 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 11. 21 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 827. 22 Adorno, Lectures on Negative Dialectics (Cambridge 2008b), p. 65. 23 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 12. 24 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 355, 205, 197. 25 Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx ’s Capital (Leiden 2004), p. 243. See also Helmut Reichelt, ‘Die Marxsche Kritik ökonomischer Kategorien. Ueberlegungen zum Problem der Geltung in der dialektischen Darstellungsmethode im Kapital ’, in ed. Iring Fetscher and Alfred Schmidt,

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 71

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

72

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Emanzipation und Versöhnung. Zu Adornos Kritik der ‘Warentausch’Gesellschaft und Perpektiven der Transformation (Frankfurt 2002). 26 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 11. 27 See Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 25, 149. 28 Theodor Adorno, Drei Studien zu Hegel, in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 5 (Frankfurt 1971), p. 204. 29 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 712. 30 Adorno, Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge: 2008a), p. 55. 31 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 33. 32 See Lukács, Lenin: A Study in the Unity of his Thought, p. 41. 33 Adorno, ‘Spengler’, p. 318. 34 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 818. 35 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 644. For the development of this point, see Chapters 4 and 5. 36 Johannes Agnoli, Subversive Theorie – Die Sache selbst und ihre Geschichte (Freiburg 1996). 37 Carl Menger, Problems of Economics and Sociology (Urbana, IL 1963). 38 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 271, 280. 39 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 899. Marx, ‘Critique of the Gotha Programme’, in Marx Engels Selected Works, vol. 3 (Moscow 1970), p. 13, translation amended. 40 Adorno, ‘Spengler’, p. 320. 41 The notion ‘sheer unrest of life’ is Hegel’s. Georg W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit (Oxford 1977), p. 27. 42 Adorno, ‘Spengler’, p. 311. 43 Adorno, ‘Spengler’, p. 311. Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 21. 44 Adorno, ‘Spengler’, p. 33, sees the implication of this clearly: ‘What differs from the existent will strike the existent as witchcraft’. The priceless character of negative thought invites mockery as an academic judgement and death (by burning), if and when required. 45 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 494, fn. 4. 46 Adorno, ‘Spengler’, p. 356. 47 See Adorno, Minima Moralia (London 1974), p. 229. 48 Reichelt, ‘Social Reality’, p. 65. 49 Adorno, History, p. 26. 50 Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Towards a New Manifesto (London 2011), p. 27. 51 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 167. 52 Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx ’s Capital, p. 80. 53 Adorno, History, p. 25.

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 72

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

73

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

54 On Habermas’s traditional conception of society as system and action, see Helmut Reichelt, ‘Jürgen Habermas’ Reconstruction of Historical Materialism’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, The Politics of Change (London 2000). 55 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 355. 56 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 167, 167–8. 57 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 374. 58 Antonio Negri, ‘Interpretation of the Class Situation Today: Methodological Aspects’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. II (London 1992), p. 89. 59 I use the term recognition here in distinction to Axel Honneth, who employs the term to tease out the ‘promise of freedom’ that he considers bourgeois society to contain. I use the term recognition to mean the recognition of reality, not its hypothesis as an ‘as if’ of a surplus of freedom. Axel Honneth, The Pathologies of Individual Freedom (Cambridge, MA 2010), p. 10. 60 Existentialism conceives of Man in abstraction from society, and perceives society as the alienated existence of Man. The standpoint of human nature is the standpoint of nature. It replaces the conceptuality of society by its hypothesis. On this, see the debate between Herbert Marcuse and Alfred Schmidt in their book Existenzialistische Marx-Interpretationen (Frankfurt 1973). Traditional social theory is both existentialist and structuralist – it differentiates between economic system and economic action, between structure and struggle, system-logic and life-world, objective framework and inter-subjective relations, etc. Werner Bonefeld, ‘Between Structure and Autonomy’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Revolutionary Writing (New York 2003). 61 See Poulantzas, ‘Theorie und Geschichte: Kurze Bemerkung über den Gegenstand des “Kapitals”’, in ed. Walter Euchner and Alfred Schmidt, Kritik der politischen Ökonomie, 100 Jahre Kapital (Frankfurt 1969). 62 I return to this point in Chapter 9 in the context of a critique of forms of anti-capitalism that leaves capitalism entirely untouched. 63 Adorno, Drei Studien, p. 131. In his Negative Dialectics he discusses this unity as one of social identity, and conceives of this identity as an identity between identity and non-identity. See also Reichelt, ‘Social Reality as Appearance’ for an insightful interpretation of this point. 64 Theodor Adorno, Stichworte, Kritische Modelle 2 (Frankfurt 1969), p. 159. 65 The quotation is from Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 153. The idea of economy as an ontological force derives from Lukács, Marx ’s Basic Ontological Principles. 66 See Adorno, Stichworte, p. 157. 67 Guy Debort, Society of the Spectacle (New York 1994), para. 9. 68 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 817.

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 73

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

74

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

69 On this, see Backhaus, ‘Some Aspects of Marx’s Concept of Critique in the Context of His Economic-Philosophical Theory’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism (Aldershot 2005). 70 See Adorno, ‘Society’, in ed. Stephen Eric Bronner and Douglas Mackay Kellner, Critical Theory and Society (London 1989), p. 272. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 304. 71 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 827. Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 92. 72 On this, see Werner Bonefeld, ‘Capital as Subject and the Existence of Labour’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn, John Holloway and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. 3 (London 1995). 73 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 830. 74 Or as Marx put it in Capital, vol. I, pp. 677–8: The categories of political economy express ‘the forms of appearance of essential relations’. Political economy ‘borrowed’ these categories ‘from everyday life without further criticism’ – it compares this portion of profit with another, transforming the concept of value into an ‘imaginary’ expression. 75 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 257. 76 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 127. 77 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 304. 78 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 165. 79 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 772. 80 Adorno, Lectures, p. 20. 81 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 149. 82 Adorno, Einleitung zur Musiksoziologie (Frankfurt 1962), p. 25. 83 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 167. 84 See Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 167. 85 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 169, uses the phrase ‘absurd form’. On this see chapter I, fn. 42. 86 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory (Cambridge 1996), p. 62. Postone does not expound this insightful point. 87 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 262. 88 Reichelt, ‘Social Reality as Appearance’. Simon Clarke, ‘Capital, Fractions of Capital and the State’, Capital & Class, vol. 2, no. 2 (1978), pp. 32–77. 89 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 209. 90 Marx, Theories, p. 455. 91 Hans- Georg Backhaus, ‘Between Philosophy and Science: Marxian Social Economy as Critical Theory’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. I (London 1992), p. 62. Backhaus is citing from the German edition of Marx’s Grundrisse (Berlin 1974), p. 928.

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 74

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

SOCIETY AS SUBJECT AND SOCIETY AS OBJECT

75

92 Marx, Grundrisse (English edition), p. 168. 93 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 392. 94 Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto (London 1997), pp. 18–19. 95 On these points, see Alfred Schmidt, ‘Praxis’, in ed. Hans-Georg Backhaus, Gesellschaft: Beiträge zur Marxschen Theorie 2 (Frankfurt 1974), and Horkheimer, Kritische und Traditionelle Theorie (Frankfurt 1992). 96 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 167. 97 This is Reichelt’s point in ‘Social Reality’. 98 Adorno, Einleitung , p. 44. 99 Lukács, Marx ’s Basic Ontological Principles, p. 159. 100 Max, Theories, p. 535. 101 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 197. 102 Marx, Theories, p. 254. 103 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 5, 144. 104 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 489. 105 Marx, Theories, p. 147. 106 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 167; Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 165. 107 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 12, 11. 108 This articulation of the ‘non-conceptual’ belongs to Gunn, ‘Against Historical Materialism’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. II (London 1992). 109 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 5, 145, 12. See also Johannes Agnoli, Politik und Geschichte (Freiburg 2001), pp. 164–8. 110 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 4. 111 See Adorno, Minima Moralia, p. 50. 112 Reichelt, ‘Social Reality’, p. 65. 113 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 358.

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 75

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

9781441161390_Ch03_Final_txt_print.indd 76

2/19/2014 3:37:43 PM

4 Capital and labour: Primitive accumulation and the force of value Introduction Conventionally, primitive accumulation is seen as a period of transition towards capitalist society, which once established, brought primitive accumulation as a distinctive period of transition from pre-capitalist societies to capitalism to a close.1 In distinction, I argue that primitive accumulation did not contain capitalist accumulation within itself as an already written future. The past does not contain the future as its unfolding destiny. Rather, the present contains the past, and it is the present that reveals the significance of the past as the historical foundation of the existing social relations. This understanding of primitive accumulation as the historical foundation of capitalist society has important consequences for the critique of political economy. In my view, the value form becomes clear only when primitive accumulation is considered. In distinction to the new reading of Marx, which developed the value form as a conceptually closed system and located the class relations within the framework of this system, I hold that class is the historical and logical premise of the value form. It entails the force of law-making violence within its concept.2 This force of law-making violence is the divorce of labour from the means of subsistence, which appears in the law of value in the form of economic compulsion. Many commentators have analysed capitalist development to include elements of ‘primitive’ accumulation.3 David Harvey’s book The New Imperialism brought this stance to wider attention and debate. He argues that primitive accumulation is the basis of all further capitalist accumulation and that, in order for capitalism to maintain the wheels of accumulation, it

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 79

2/19/2014 3:38:16 PM

80

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

has eventually to be repeated. He calls this primitive accumulation within capitalism accumulation by dispossession, and contends that in contemporary capitalism, accumulation by dispossession represents not only a specific attempt to overcome the capitalist crisis of over-accumulation but that it has in fact become the dominant form of accumulation.4 Accumulation by dispossession appears not only at capitalism’s periphery as a means of developing the capitalist social relations but also at its centre. In his view, accumulation by dispossession ranges from those processes of expropriation that Marx identified as the violent separation of the producers from their means of production and subsistence to, for example, the privatization of nationalized industries.5 The meaning of the term connotes proletarianization qua commodification. Massimo de Angelis makes this case most strongly in his analysis of contemporary capitalism, in which he argues that capital employs ‘primitive accumulation’ as a means of decomposing what he sees as society’s natural desire to protect itself from the enforcement of the rule of the market.6 In contemporary analysis, primitive accumulation appears as an ‘imperialist’ effect of capitalist accumulation, both internationally and domestically. This understanding of primitive accumulation goes back to Rosa Luxemburg.7 She maintained that capitalism must always have something outside of itself in order to stabilize, and that crises of capitalist accumulation find a temporary resolution in the imposition of conditions of primitive accumulation upon new populations, creating new markets, discovering new raw materials and recruiting new and cheaper proletarians.8 Writing in the 1970s, Samir Amin reasserted this view. The mechanisms of primitive accumulation, he argued, ‘do not belong only to the prehistory of capitalism; they are contemporary as well. It is these forms of primitive accumulation, modified but persistent, to the advantage of the centre, that form the domain of the theory of accumulation on a world scale’.9 Harvey’s analysis follows on from Luxemburg and Amin, emphasizing the processes of primitive accumulation that the expansion of capitalism into the periphery has brought about under so-called neoliberalism, and like de Angelis he expands on this analysis by arguing that it is also a contemporary force at capitalism’s centre, maintaining dispossessed labour in conditions of economic compulsion. In these analyses primitive accumulation is a permanent feature of capitalist accumulation. However, this dialectical movement, that is one in which the historical presupposition of capitalism becomes a result of its reproduction, suggests that the relationship between accumulation by means of dispossession and accumulation by means of surplus value extraction is more intricate than Luxemburg-inspired conceptions of the permanence of primitive accumulation allow. The transformation of the historical

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 80

2/19/2014 3:38:16 PM

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

81

‘presupposition’ of capitalism into the result of its reproduction suggests that the originality of primitive accumulation has to do with its social contents, that is, the capitalistically organized social relations of production. This chapter argues that the contemporary elements of primitive accumulation are not ‘side-effects’ or the result of some uneven and combined logic of development; nor are they ‘employed by capital’ to contain labour.10 Rather, primitive accumulation belongs to the conceptuality of capital. It ‘forms (bildet ) the concept (Begriff ) of capital’.11 It is both ‘the foundation of [capitalist] production . . . [and] given in capitalist production’.12 The conceptual foundation of this argument is as follows: ‘In themselves money and commodities are not more capital than are the means of production and the means of subsistence.’13 Indeed, trade, exchange and ‘money’ pre-date capitalism, and like the means of production or the means of subsistence, neither are intrinsically capitalist in character. For them to be ‘transformed into capital, the prerequisites for capitalist production must exist’.14 This transformation ‘can only take place’ on the condition that ‘two different kinds of commodity possessors . . . come . . . into contact’, that is, on the one side, the owner of money, means of production and means of subsistence, and on the other, the owner of labour power. The occult quality of money to lay golden eggs requires that ‘the owner of the means of production and subsistence meet in the market with the free labourer selling his labour power’. This is the ‘one historical condition’ for the transformation of the products of labour into commodities and of money into capital. Capital ‘dripping from head to foot, from every pore, with blood and dirt’, is founded on the ‘complete separation of the labourers from all property in the means by which they can realise their labour’.15 In short, it is thus essential that the labourer is unable to subsist other than by selling her labour power in exchange for a wage. ‘Commodity and money are transformed into capital because the worker . . . is compelled to sell his labour itself (to sell directly his labour power) as a commodity to the owner of the conditions of labour.’ This historical condition is not only the ‘prerequisite for the transformation of money (or of the commodity by which it is represented) into capital’,16 it is also the ‘historical basis’ from which ‘all methods for raising the social productive of labour . . . grow up’.17 Capitalist society contains its historical foundation in the premise of its concept; its werewolf hunger for surplus labour subsists through it, and its law of accumulation reproduces its premise in dispossessed labour ‘on a continuously expanding scale’.18 That is, the ‘conditions of its becoming’ pass thus over into the ‘results of its presence’.19 Once established ‘capitalist production therefore reproduces in the course of its own process the separation between labour-power and the conditions of labour’ as the premise and innate necessity of its concept.20

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 81

2/19/2014 3:38:16 PM

82

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

The circumstance that its constitutive premise in the expropriation of the labourer vanishes in the law of value says no more than, to begin with, that the violence of its historical foundation hides in its appearance as an economic force of nature, which not only possesses the magical ability to instantiate its own expansion – value posits more value and appears thus as a force of self-valorization – it also entails the compulsion to sell labour power as the condition of making a living. That is to say, the conceptuality of the law of value is antagonistic from the outset. The chapter is divided into two sections. It first expounds the transformation of primitive accumulation as a precondition of capitalism into its constitutive premise. It then shows how the concept of primitive accumulation fits into Capital. In distinction to the new reading, which holds that Marx’s critique entails a purely logical exposition of the categories of political economy, these categories express historically stamped relations. The law of value contains the force of law-making violence within its concept – in its civilized form, it appears as the freedom of economic compulsion.

The secret of primitive accumulation In the German original of Capital, Marx does not speak about ‘primitive’ accumulation. This term is offered in the English translation and, I suppose, it is as close to the German original as is possible. Yet, it is inaccurate. The German text says ursprünglich. This term can also be translated as ‘original’, ‘initial’, ‘unspoiled’, as well as ‘beginning’, ‘first manifestation’ and ‘springing to life’. The term does not connote ‘causality’, where, say, an historical event ‘causes’ the formation of a distinct mode of social relations. Instead the term asks about the genesis of the existent, its foundation. The significance of primitive accumulation is capitalist accumulation. In other words, and with reference to Marx, the anatomy of Man can explain the anatomy of the ape, but not conversely, the anatomy of the ape does not explain the anatomy of Man.21 If the anatomy of the ape could really explain the anatomy of Man then the ape would already possess Man as the innate necessity of its evolution – a natural teleology or an already-written future. Capitalist accumulation was not already written into primitive accumulation as its necessary future. Rather capitalist accumulation reveals the necessity of primitive accumulation in its own concept.22 That is to say, and contrary to Jim Glassman’s view, primitive accumulation is not a progressive historical force of human development that paves the way of transition from pre-capitalism via capitalism to socialism. He sees primitive accumulation as a ‘necessary step in the direction of fuller

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 82

2/19/2014 3:38:16 PM

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

83

human development’. Glassman’s point is either banal – the present is the result of historical development – or teleological in its conception of history as a force that unfolds for the benefit of human satisfaction. According to Glassman Marx’s discussion of primitive accumulation focuses ‘largely on proletarianisation, since he is pre-eminently concerned with the formation of what he takes to be the most revolutionary subjects and the central issues over which they struggle’.23 He seems to suggest that Marx was not concerned with conceptualizing the social foundation of capitalism in free wage labour, but rather in developing the revolutionary subject. The separation of ‘genesis’ from ‘existence’ constitutes the blind spot of teleological or, in any case, dogmatic thought, in which social practice is conceived of as a functional agent in a structure of being and becoming. Primitive accumulation is primitive only from the standpoint of capitalist accumulation. Conceived as an ursprüngliche accumulation it is not primitive at all – its terror has been ‘written into the annals of mankind in letters of blood and fire’.24 It led to the complete separation of labour from its means of existence, and this separation ‘forms the concept of capital’.25 The capitalist form of labour is thus founded on ‘object-less, free workers ’.26 The divorce of labour from the means of production and subsistence turns them ‘into proletarians’ and ‘their means of labour into capital’.27 Labour divorced from its means of existence is thus the ‘foundation of capitalist production’.28 The conditions of work thus confront labour ‘as alien capital’ because they ‘are lost to [the labourer] and have assumed the shape of alien property’.29 Primitive accumulation is the centrifugal point around which revolves the specific capitalist form of social labour. In capitalism the terror of separation appears in the civilized form of free and equal exchange relations. Here Man is free because she needs to obey no person but solely the laws of contract and is self-responsible for adjusting the pursuit of her interests to changing market conditions. Force appears in the civilized form of freedom as economic compulsion, which is the freedom of ‘economic bondage’. That is to say, the freedom of the wage labourer amounts, on the one hand, to the same ‘old age activity of the conqueror, who buys commodities from the conquered with the money he has stolen from them’.30 On the other, it amounts to the freedom of contract between equal legal subjects of law in trading labour power, the one for the sake of consuming it for the purpose of greater wealth in the form of profit, the other to dodge the ‘freedom to starve’.31 ‘The Roman slave’, argues Marx, ‘was held by chains; the wage-labourer is bound to his owner by invisible threads’ inasmuch as her access to the means of subsistence is governed by the rate of accumulation that determines the rate of unemployment and therewith the conditions of the buying and selling of labour power.32 Thus, the free

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 83

2/19/2014 3:38:16 PM

84

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

labourer vanishes in the economic categories, such as rate of investment and economic growth, labour productivity and profitability, competitive labour unit costs and world market conditions, etc., that govern her access to the means of subsistence. The wage-labourer subsists in her own social world as a mere agent of those same economic categories that have their historical basis in the class struggle over the original expropriation of the mass of the population from the means of subsistence. Capital is not only ‘the form assumed by the conditions of labour’,33 it also appears as the independent force of wealth in that the commodity seems to be ‘a product of capital’.34 What appears in this appearance ‘rests on the foundation of the workers’ propertylessness’ – a propertylessness in the means of life that asserts itself in the form of capital as an independent power of economic compulsion over the class-divided social individuals.35 Instead of relations of personal dependency, capitalist social relations are governed by abstract forms of dependency. Economic compulsion appears to issue from the things themselves, as if by the force of nature. It seems as if the social world existed twice, once as an innately economic thing that imposes itself objectively on the acting subjects, and then as a human personification of that thing, mere agents of production who, as personifications of capital and wage-labour, embody the definite social characteristics stamped upon them by the process of social production. 36 Society makes itself manifest behind the backs of the class-divided social individual who is ‘chained to the rock of his past’. 37 As a movement of economic quantities, society is no longer comprehensible – here it appears as ‘encased in eternal natural laws independent of history’38 – from ‘time immemorial’. 39 The understanding of primitive accumulation as the constitutive premise of the existent economic forces destroys their deceptive appearance as forces of nature. It also renounces the idea that the perverted economic forms have a basis in some abstractly conceived ‘human basis’.40 In the world of economic abstractions ‘what alone remains comprehensible is the law of autonomisation’. 41 This law of autonomization is however a double-edged sword in that it carries its historical foundation in the separation of the labourer from her means of existence within the law of its movement. The propertylessness in the means of life entails the struggle for the means of life. Capitalist society cannot divorce itself from its historical basis. In essence, capital is the existence of social labour – the combination of labour as subject as well as object – but this existence as itself existing independently opposite its real moments – hence itself a particular existence apart from them. For its part, capital therefore appears as the predominant subject

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 84

2/19/2014 3:38:16 PM

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

85

and owner of alienated labour, and its relation is itself as complete a contradiction as is that of wage labour.42 What, then, needs to be explained is not the relation between capital and wage labour in its direct and immediate sense – say, of capital as an economic quantity of this or that amount of money, or of the worker as an investor in human capital of this or that amount of employable skills – but rather the social constitution upon which the capital relation is founded and through which it subsists. The capitalistically organized form of social labour presupposes the expropriation of the direct producer, and it is thus the definite social form of that expropriation. It ‘originally appeared as conditions of its becoming – and hence could not spring from its action as capital – now appears as results of its own realization, reality, as posited by it – not as conditions of its arising, but as results of its presence.’43 Capitalist accumulation reproduces its constitutive presupposition in dispossession as the result of its own, innate social laws of reproduction. The labourer constantly produces material, objective wealth, but in the form of capital, of an alien power that dominates and exploits [the labourer]: and the capitalist as constantly produces labour-power, but in the form of a subjective source of wealth, separated from the objects in and by which it can alone be realised; in short he produces the labourer, but as a wage-labourer. This incessant reproduction, this perpetuation of the labourer, is the absolute necessary condition for capitalist production.44 As a result of its own realization, primitive accumulation is a permanent accumulation. What is to be understood by ‘permanent’ in this context? In Latin, ‘per’ means through, way; and ‘manere’ means to remain, to be continuous; permanent then connotes a lasting character, something maintained through and also in time. Regarding primitive accumulation, permanence means that the divorce of labour from the means of production constitutes the fundamental social practice of the capitalist social relations in the form of independent economic forces that manifest themselves behind the back of the individuals, as if the economic world were regulated by an invisible hand. Indeed, the economic world asserts itself as an independent force not only over and above the social individuals. It also prevails in and through them. The logic of separation that gives economic things independent force, appears in the form of an irresistible system dynamic, in which nothing remains in the way it was and in which, and at the same time, the essential character of the social relations remains unchanged: capital as the form assumed by

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 85

2/19/2014 3:38:16 PM

86

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

the conditions of labour on the one hand, and the doubly free labourer, on the other. Adorno’s concept of ‘dynamic within stasis’ focuses this well:45 capitalism is a dynamic, ever developing and changing configuration of definite social relations, where everything that is solid melts, at the same time as which the ‘law’ of development remains unchanged: expansive reproduction of the object-less, free workers as the social foundation of the capitalist form of wealth that dazzles to deceive. Wealth seems to posit itself as more money and therefore always also as too little money; its demand for expansion is tireless. The law of capital can thus be summarized as follows: the law is what remains in disappearance. Whatever the specific and changing historical forms of capitalism, it develops on the basis and by force of ‘the logic of separation’. This logic is the constitutive premise of capital as the ‘automatic subject’ of a relentless process of accumulating abstract wealth for its own sake.46 I have argued that primitive accumulation is the historical presupposition and basis of capital and that its systematic content is the constitutive premise of the capitalist social relations. Its content is suspended in capitalist economic forms. The critical issue here is the precise meaning of ‘suspended’ (aufgehoben ). ‘Suspended’ is usually used as the English translation of the German term ‘aufgehoben ’ or Aufhebung. Aufhebung is a term that is most difficult to translate into English, and ‘suspended’ does not carry the full meaning of this typically many-sided German term. The notion that primitive accumulation is ‘suspended’ in capitalist accumulation does not collapse two distinct concepts, as if there were no difference between accumulation by expropriation (dispossession) and accumulation by means of exploiting the ‘free’ labourer. This difference is important, but so, too, is the connection between them. In Hegelian language, Aufhebung connotes a dialectical process of determinate negation. That is, the determination of a term negates it at the same time as which the so negated term transforms into a new term. In this process, the negated term loses its independent existence and it does so at the same time as which its essential character is retained in the new term – the new term is informed by the negated term. The circumstance that the essence of the negated term is maintained in the new term means that the essence of the old term is also the essence of the new term. Aufhebung has more than just different meanings; they are also contradictory. The concept entails all these different and contradictory meanings. Aufheben has three main meanings: ‘to lift up’ or ‘to raise’; ‘to make invalid’ or ‘to cancel/ eliminate’; and ‘to keep’ or ‘to maintain’. In our context, Aufhebung means that the historic form of primitive accumulation is raised to a new level where its original form and independent existence is eliminated (or cancelled) at

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 86

2/19/2014 3:38:16 PM

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

87

the same time as its substance or essence (Wesenshaftigkeit ) is maintained in the new form. In other words, the notion that the essence of primitive accumulation is aufgehoben in accumulation proper means that the essential character of primitive accumulation, this divorce of the direct producers from the means of subsistence, is raised to a new level, eliminating the history of primitive accumulation as a specific epoch. At the same time its essential character is maintained in the new form, that is, the historical presupposition of capitalism becomes the premise of its existence: labour divorced from its means becomes the result of a process of accumulation that is based on the appropriation of the surplus labour that capital is able to extract, and seeks to validate in exchange in the form of value, from the free labourer in the hidden abode of production. Paraphrasing Marx’s treatment of the commodity, the process of the disappearance of primitive accumulation in accumulation proper ‘must, therefore, appear at the same time as a process of the disappearance of its disappearance, i.e. as a reproduction process’.47 As such a process of reproduction, ‘the real foundation’ of the capital relation becomes the ‘characteristic result of capitalist production’, perpetuating and renewing the divorce ‘between the objective conditions and the subjective labour-power’.48 The productive labourer does not represent an eternal condition of labour. Rather, the productive labourer is historically specific. She carries the violence of primitive accumulation within her branded existence as the dispossessed producer of surplus value.

Value form and free labour I have argued that it is not the anatomy of primitive accumulation that explains the anatomy of capitalist accumulation but that it is instead the anatomy of capitalist accumulation that explains the anatomy of the primitive accumulation. This contention rejects both teleological explanations, such as Adam Smith’s stages theory of history, and natural law explanations of history, such as, again, Adam Smith’s natural propensity of Man to truck and barter, upon which rests the traditional Marxist view of the trans-historical forces of production and the social relations of production. The circumstance that Marx discusses primitive accumulation in at the end of volume I of Capital might therefore not be an afterthought, as Glassman believes it to be the case. In his view: Marx came to the issue of primitive accumulation late in the day . . . [A]fter having spent hundreds of pages analysing the labour process

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 87

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

88

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

through which commodities and surplus value are produced in capitalist society, the process of ‘expanded reproduction’, he backtracks to consider the origins of the surplus that made the first process of accumulation possible – the ‘so-called primitive accumulation’.49 In distinction to Glassman, dispossession does not create a surplus in wealth, it is mere robbery of the many by the few. It changes the distribution of the means of existence and in this process creates the social foundation of private property, that is, the doubly free labourer. Marx’s presentation of the historical presupposition of the commodity form at the conclusion of volume I of Capital is thus in part explained by the insight that the significance of primitive accumulation does not lie, as Glassman argues, in primitive accumulation as the first capitalist surplus, but, rather, in the establishment of the capitalist social relations. That is to say, capitalist accumulation ‘illuminates’ the historical significance of primitive accumulation, and not the other way round.50 According to Marx, Capital was to ‘track down [the] inner connection’ between the economic categories, developing the ‘actual movement’ of the capitalist society, which is founded on the commodity as the ‘elementary form’ of capitalist wealth.51 The exposition of the economic categories does therefore not present an historical process. Rather, it develops them from within their own context, establishing their innate conceptuality from within their own social relations of production. Therefore ‘presentation must differ from inquiry’. For the ‘new reading’ of Marx, this distinction between historical analysis and logical exposition was fundamental for its reconstruction of Marx’s critique. It entailed a dialectical exposition of the entire system of economic categories, unfolding the economic forms as forms of ‘real inversion’.52 The ‘new reading’ followed Marx’s methodological observation to the point where it would be ‘unfeasible and wrong to let the economic categories follow one another in the same sequence as that in which they were historically decisive. Their sequence is determined, rather, by their relation to one another in modern bourgeois society.’53 Nevertheless, although the value form of the commodity is the established principle of the capitalist social relations, it represents the appearance of the separation of labour from the means of production, and is founded on the peculiar character of capitalist labour. The dialectical presentation of the system of economic inversion is therefore limited, and by following Marx’s observation to the letter, the ‘new reading’ limited its own critical potential. Chris Arthur’s ‘systematic dialectics’ is a case in point. He argues that the dialectical method deals with ‘a given whole and demonstrates how it reproduces itself: thus the ordering of the categories is in no way determined by the recapitulation of a historical chain of causality; it is articulated on the basis of purely systematic considerations’.

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 88

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

89

He righty argues that the dialectical method deals with ‘a given whole’, and he wrongly treats this whole as a closed logical system. In his view, ‘capital may be seen as the avatar of Hegel’s absolute concept’ and he wonders why Marx introduces labour as a concept when introducing the general form of value in the first chapter of Capital. His systematic dialectics thus tends to substitute an argument about the homology between Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s Science of Logic for the recognition of the capitalist social relations. Whatever homology there might be, the idea of a logical beginning is absurd. The peculiar character of capitalist social relations cannot be found in some logic of immanent abstractness, as Arthur argues.54 Similarly Backhaus believes that the exploration of the capitalist social relations has to have ‘a logical beginning’, which, he says, forms the basis of Marx’s ‘theoretical system’.55 He subscribes to the absurd idea that the category wage labour can be derived from the peculiar character of abstract social labour. Yet, he does not tell us how.56 His insistence that exposition of the economic categories is a matter of a priori construction sits ill with the notion that the dialectical method entails their generic development as forms of definite social relations. Backhaus resolves this difficulty by falling back onto an argument about species being. ‘Critique’, he says, has to reveal the genesis of a perverted world that Man as a ‘species being has posited outside of itself’, be it in the religious form of ‘God, the form of the political state, or indeed the form of money’.57 In distinction, Marx’s point about the distinction between presentation and inquiry does not say that inquiry should be dropped for the sake of systematic presentation – and really what would be the subject matter of presentation if it would not be a presentation of the capitalist social relations. Presentation presupposes inquiry, and the logical presentation of the capitalist economic categories does not proceed independently from the social relations whose peculiar character it seeks to decipher in its entirety and from within its own context. The capitalist social relations are based on one ‘essential condition’: that is, capital can spring to life ‘only when the owner of the means of production and subsistence finds the free worker available, on the market, as the seller of his own labour-power’.58 The purpose of Arthur’s systematic dialectics and Backhaus’s search for an ‘objective beginning’ is to reveal the peculiar conceptuality of the capitalist social relations. However, this conceptuality is a historically branded conceptuality. For the sake of logical coherence, they thus exclude from their development of the ‘celestial forms’ of capital the peculiar character of the social relations that manifest themselves in the form of economic monstrosities.59 According to Helmut Reichelt, Man ‘becomes a free labourer when his labour power is objectified and becomes exchangeable as a commodity’.60 What however does this mean? Reichelt conceives of society as a social

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 89

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

90

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

system that is governed by the law of value, without the force of value. He develops the value form as an objectively valid real economic abstraction, a universal in re of capitalist wealth.61 However, the labourer did not become free when her labour power was objectified in the commodity. The labourer became free when she was forced off the land, when her means of existence were expropriated by force and when her labouring existence was disciplined with fire and blood. The genesis of economic categories cannot be found in the idea of a free labourer who objectifies herself in capitalist social forms. The law of value presupposes the force of value in the premise of its concept. This premise is the labourer who is free of the means of production, free to sell her labour power, and a labourer upon whom labour discipline has been instilled, more often than not by means of terror and, always, abject poverty.62 Similarly, Moishe Postone recognizes that the understanding of commodified labour is fundamental to the comprehension of the value form. However, he too develops commodified labour in abstraction from its historical branding arguing that the peculiar character of commodity-producing labour does not mean that the processes of primitive accumulation remains central to the conception of alienated labour and commodity fetishism.63 Postone makes commodity-determined labour the starting point of his critical theory, and having cut it off from its historical constitution, argues akin to Giddens’s theory of structuration when he develops the critique of political economy as ‘a complex analysis of the reciprocal constitution of system and action in capitalist society’.64 By severing the genesis of the social forms from the existing social relations, his account splits society into two interconnected realities of system and action, or structure and agency, which, as I argued in Chapter 3, rather than offering a critique of the fetishism of commodities, articulates the fetish in theoretical form. The capitalist economic categories do not have a logical beginning, nor do they have an anthropological foundation in Man as a ‘species being’. Rather, ‘economic categories . . . bear an historical imprint’, and their logical presentation amounts thus to a presentation of categories that bear the stamp of history.65 That is, Marx’s caution about the merits of dialectical exposition merits attention: ‘It is made quite definite at this point that the dialectical presentation is right only when it knows its own limits.’66 With this in mind, the distinction between inquiry (Forschung ) and presentation (Darstellung ) is fundamental. Indeed, the understanding of Capital ‘stands and falls with the concept of presentation’.67 The chapter sequence of Capital volume I does indeed not follow historical events and the ‘mode of presentation’ does not parallel any actual course of events. The chapter sequence unfolds the fundamental categories of capitalistically constituted

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 90

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

91

social relations – commodity, exchange value, abstract labour, money, etc. He discusses their historical constitution at the end of the volume. Marx’s argument is in reverse order to the actual, historical sequence in which the social relations underlying these categories developed. That is, the method of presentation must differ in form from that of inquiry. The latter has to appropriate the material in detail, to analyse its different forms of development, to track down their inner connections. Only after this work is done, can the actual movement be appropriately presented. If this is done successfully, if the life of the subject-matter is now reflected back on the ideas, then it may appear as if we had before us an a priori construction. The logical development of the decisive economic forms takes ‘a course directly opposite to their real development’. That is to say, the reflection begins post festum, with therefore the result of the process of development ready in hand. The forms which stamp products as commodities and which are therefore the preliminary requirements for the circulation of commodities, already possess the fixed quality of natural forms of social life before man seeks to give an account, not of their historical character . . . but of their content and meaning.68 The categories of abstract labour, value, exchange value, money, capital, surplus value, capital accumulation, etc., presuppose the systematic content of primitive accumulation in their conceptuality – a conceptuality of separation qua social unity. Unity appears in the form of a movement of real economic abstractions that, endowed with an invisible force, govern over and prevail through the social individuals. Like the religious form of God, the autonomized force of economic abstractions cannot be understood. What can be comprehended is the law of autonomization, that is, the disappearance of the actual social relations in their own apotheosized economic forms. This disappearance is therefore also an appearance of the social individuals as personifications of economic categories, bearers of particular class interests.69 The fetishism of commodities makes it seem as if the social individual is separated from her own social world, which appears to them in the form of an unfolding system logic that threatens the further colonization of the life world. The comprehension of the movement of economic forces is, however, not advanced by the invocation of some mysterious life-world that is deemed to be at risk of colonization by the economic forces. Rather, and as argued in Chapter 3, all social life is essentially practical, and the explanation of the

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 91

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

92

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

system logic is thus a matter of comprehending this practice from within its own perverted context. Marx’s critique of political economy argues that separation of labour from the means of production ‘is given in capitalist production’70 and that ‘capitalist production therefore reproduces in the course of its own process the separation between labour-power and the conditions of labour’.71 It does so by perpetuating the conditions under which the worker is exploited. It incessantly forces him to sell his labour-power in order to live, and enables the capitalist to purchase labour power in order that he may enrich himself . . . It is the alternating rhythm of the process itself which throws the worker back onto the market again and again as a seller of his labour-power and continually transforms his own product into a means by which another man can purchase him. The logic of separation determines the class antagonism as a disunited relationship of social unity – no capital without dispossessed labour and no surplus value without the imposition of necessary labour on ‘formally free labour’. That is, capital presupposes wage-labour, and wage-labour presupposes capital. They reciprocally condition each other’s existence; they reciprocally bring forth each other. Does a worker in a cotton-factory produce nothing but cotton goods? No, he produces capital. He produces values that serve afresh to command his labour and by means of it to create new values.72 Commodities must be realized as values. The fact that value – whether it exists as money or as commodities – and in the further development the conditions of labour confront the worker as the property of other people, as independent properties, means simply that they confront him as the property of the non-worker or, at any rate, that, as a capitalist, he confronts them [the conditions of labour] not as a worker but as the owner of value, etc., as the subject in which these things possess their own will, belong to themselves and are personified as independent forces.73 Capital appears here as an intangible, abstract force – a transcendental subject that is neither this nor that, and yet both at the same time, governing the social individuals as if by ‘fate’, and that is akin to the idea of the invisible hand as the regulative mechanism of reified economic things. Marx’s critique

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 92

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

93

of commodity fetishism does not reject the reality of the invisible hand that, with unyielding steadiness, regulates the relations of abstract wealth by reproducing the inequality in property between capital and labour on an expanding scale. Indeed, fetishism is real. It is founded on the doubly free labourer – this indispensible prerequisite of the commodity form. Having developed the categories of value, value form, use-value and exchange value, abstract labour and concrete labour, Marx develops his argument from the transformation of money as money into money as capital, to the analysis of the buying and selling of labour power. Then it follows the free labourer into the factory, analysing the relationship between necessary labour and surplus labour, the constituent parts of the working day. Here capital sets the free labourer to work attempting to appropriate as much surplus labour time as possible – in effect an attempt at expropriating the life-time of the labourer, seeking to reduce it to labour-time in its entirety. ‘But all methods for raising the social productivity of labour that grow up on this basis [the basis of primitive accumulation – WB], are at the same time methods for the increased production of surplus value’. From the production of surplus value we arrive at the reconversion of surplus value into capital. This conversion ‘reveals’ the law of equal exchange as fiction: the ‘separation of property from labour thus becomes the necessary consequence of a law that apparently originated in their identity’. On the other hand, the individual capitalist has constantly to expand ‘his capital, so as to preserve it, and he can only extend it by means of progressive accumulation’. The risk is bankruptcy. Thus, mediated through competition, personified capital is spurred into action. He is ‘fanatically intent on the valorization of value; consequently he ruthlessly forces the human race to produce for production’s sake’, leading to the ‘extension of the area of exploited human material and, at the same time, the extension of the direct and indirect sway of the capitalist’.74 In sum, the law of private property entails that ‘labour capacity has appropriated for itself only the subjective conditions of necessary labour – the means of subsistence for actively producing labour capacity, i.e. for its reproduction as mere labour capacity separated from the conditions of its realization – and it has posited these conditions themselves as things, values, which confront it in an alien, commanding personification.’75 Capitalist reproduction thus reproduces the class antagonism on an expanding scale by positing the capitalist as the owner of the means of existence on the one hand, and the doubly free labourer on the other. It posits its own presupposition – a presupposition that transformed from historical presupposition into the constitutive premise of the capitalistically organized mode of social reproduction. Turning finally to capitalist accumulation, Marx argues that it ‘merely presents as a continuous process what, in primitive accumulation, appears

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 93

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

94

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

as a distinct historical process, as the process of the emergence of capital’.76 Capital accumulation continues the process of expropriation in its own terms, as capital centralization. ‘One capitalist strikes down many others.’77 At the same time, ‘the capitalist reproduces himself as capital as well as the living labour capacity confronting him . . . Each reproduces itself, by reproducing the other, its negation. The capitalist produces labour as alien; labour produces the product as alien.’78 Leaving aside his desperately triumphal remarks when analysing the historical tendency of capitalist accumulation – the ‘centralisation of the means of production and the socialisation of labour reach a point at which they become incompatible with their capitalist integument. This integument is burst asunder. The knell of capitalist private property sounds. The expropriators are expropriated’79 – his critique unfolds the logic of separation upon which the entire system of economic categories rests, to the point of destruction. The force of value vanishes in the law of value that, once the ‘capitalist process of production . . . is fully organised . . . breaks down all resistance’ by means of the ‘silent compulsion of economic relations’ that not only ‘compel workers to sell themselves voluntarily’, but that also constantly generates ‘a relative surplus population’ that maintains competitive labour markets. The law of value now appears as a natural economic law of the ‘supply and demand of labour’. Nevertheless, the direct employment of the forces of law-making violence, the force of state, ‘is still of course used, but only in exceptional circumstances’, at times of great uncertainty.80 In sum, the logic of separation ‘begins with primitive accumulation, appears as a permanent process in the accumulation and concentration of capital, and expresses itself finally as centralisation of existing capitals in a few hands and a deprivation of many of their capital (to which expropriation is now changed).’81 In the course of capitalist accumulation, labour power is hired with the money that in the form of profit appeared only yesterday as the coined expression of the surplus value that was pumped out of social labour. The exchange between equivalents manifests itself as the ‘age-old activity of the conqueror, who buys commodities form the conquered with the money he has stolen from them’.82 It is now also in the process of transforming the individual owner of redundant or, in any case, superfluous labour-power into a bodily thing that can be dissected into saleable parts.83 Marx’s notion of the doubly free wage labourer appears to have been transformed. The doubly free wage labourer has indeed become, at least for a growing part of humanity, more than just a labouring commodity. It has also become a carrier of bodily substances that, like any other commodity, can be sold on the market at prevailing market prices. The historical foundation of its existence transforms into the fundamental dynamic of its own presence, in

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 94

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

95

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

which ‘accumulation of wealth at one pole is, therefore, at the same time accumulation of misery . . . and moral degradation at the opposite pole, i.e. on the side of the class that produces its own product as capital.’84 In the equivalent exchange between the buyer of labour power and the producer of surplus value, living labour vanishes in its mediated existence as more money, and ‘value . . . now becomes value in process, money in process, and, as such, capital’.85

Conclusion By treating capitalism as a conceptually logical system, the new reading remains spellbound to the logic of things. I have argued that the ‘logic of separation’ is the ‘real generation process of capital’.86 It is the historical foundation and premise of capitalist social relations. It holds sway in the conceptuality of capital as a definite social relationship. At its best, the dialectical method of presentation unfolds the system of economic categories as the necessary form of this – historically branded – conceptuality. The violence of capital’s original beginning is the formative content of the ‘civilized’ forms of the commodity exchange relations, which are governed by the ideals of an equivalent exchange between equal legal subjects who contract in freedom from coercion, each seeking to advance their own personal interests. The law of value presupposes the force of value within its concept of freedom. Violence hides in the civilized form of the equivalence exchange relations as economic compulsion. Chapter 5 develops this topic further in relationship to class.

Notes 1 See, for example, Paul Zarembka, ‘Primitive Accumulation in Marxism’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Subverting the Present. Imagining the Future (New York 2008). See also Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory (Cambridge 1996), p. 349. 2 For an argument about the centrality of primitive accumulation for capitalist development, see Silvia Federici, Caliban and the Witch (New York 2004), and Dalla Costa, ‘Development and Reproduction’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Revolutionary Writing (New York 2003). John Holloway, Crack Capitalism (London 2010), pp. 166–70. The notion of an innate connection between the force of law-making violence and its civilized appearance in the form of the rule of law derives from Walter Benjamin, ‘Critique of Violence’, Reflections (New York 2007).

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 95

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

96

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

3 See, for example, Jesse Goldstein, ‘Terra Economica, Waste and the Production of Enclosed Nature’, Antipode, vol. 45, no. 2 (2013), pp. 357–75. Derek Hall, ‘Rethinking Primitive Accumulation’, Antipode, vol. 44, no. 4 (2012), pp. 1188–208; Stuart Hodkinson, ‘The New Urban Enclosures’, City, vol. 16, no. 5 (2012), pp. 500–18. Mark Neocleous, ‘War on Waste: Law, Original Accumulation and the Violence of Capital’, Science and Society, vol. 75, no. 4 (2011), pp. 506–28, Wilhelm Peekhaus, ‘Primitive Accumulation and Enclosures of the Commons’, Science and Society, vol. 75, no. 4 (2011), pp. 529–54. The origins of this chapter go back to Werner Bonefeld, ‘Class Struggle and the Permanence of Primitive Accumulation’, Common Sense, no. 6 (1988), pp. 54–65 and builds on Werner Bonefeld, ‘Primitive Accumulation and Capitalist Accumulation: Notes on Social Constitution and Expropriation’, Science and Society, vol. 75, no. 3 (2010), pp. 379–99. 4 David Harvey, The New Imperialism (London 2003), pp. 140–2, 149–50, 153, 158, 172. 5 Harvey, The New Imperialism, p. 146. 6 Massimo de Angelis, ‘Marx and Primitive Accumulation’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Subverting the Present. Imagining the Future (New York 2008). 7 Rosa Luxemburg, The Accumulation of Capital (London 1963). 8 See Karl Marx, Capital, vol. III (London 1966), chap. 14, where he discusses means of crisis resolution. 9 Samir Amin, Accumulation on a World Scale. A Critique of the Theory of Underdevelopment (New York 1974), p. 3. 10 As argued by de Angelis, ‘Marx and Primitive Accumulation’; Jim Glassman, ‘Primitive Accumulation, Accumulation by Dispossession, Accumulation by “Extra-economic” Means’, Progress in Human Geography, vol. 30, no. 5 (2006), pp. 608–25. 11 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 246. 12 Marx, Theories of Surplus Value, vol. 3 (London 1972), p. 272. 13 Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 874. 14 Marx, Theories, p. 272. 15 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 874, 255, 926, 874. 16 Marx, Theories, p. 89. 17 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 775. 18 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 874. 19 Max, Grundrisse, p. 460. 20 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 723. 21 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 105. 22 For Adorno, too, history can be comprehended from the standpoint of the present alone. See Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment (London 1979 ). See also Dirk Braunstein, Adornos Kritik

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 96

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

97

der politischen Ökonomie (Bielefeld 2011), p. 177. Adorno’s argument that history has been a history of invention from the sling-shot to the atom bomb, or a process of the forward march of instrumental reason, does not say that the sling-shot contained the atom bomb as its necessary further development. The atom bomb is not the innate necessity of the sling-shot. Rather, it says that the atom bomb reveals the sling-shot, and as such, it reveals a history made universal as one of violence and destruction. Similarly, Marx’s notion that history is a history of class struggle does not entail history as an ontological force of universal class oppression that somehow develops by means of its own logic towards capitalist society and, some hope, beyond capitalism towards socialism. Rather, it grasps the existent social relations. In Adorno’s view, Marx’s critique of political economy amounts to a critique of history because his critique of capitalism reveals the whole of history in the present conditions of domination, exploitation and misery. See Adorno, Gesellschaftstheorie und Kulturkritik (Frankfurt 1975), p. 7 and Stichworte. Kritische Modelle 2 (Frankfurt 1969), pp. 29–50. See also Benjamin’s critique of the philosophy of progress in his ‘Theses on the Philosophy of History’, in Illuminations (London 1999 ). For the sake of history, one needs to read history against its grain, and, that is, one needs to think out of history, out of the battles, out of the struggles, to comprehend what has not been. On this, see Chapter 10. 23 Glassman, ‘Primitive Accumulation’, p. 611. 24 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 875. 25 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 246. 26 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 507. 27 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 928. 28 Marx, Theories, p. 272. 29 Marx, Theories, p. 422. 30 Marx, Capital, vol. I, 728. 31 Adorno, Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge 2008a), p. 201. 32 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 719. Adam Smith argues this point succinctly. He says, the freeman is responsible for his own subsistence, whereas the slave is in the keep of his masters. The slave is thus of ‘more expense than the worker’ and the ‘work of a freeman comes cheaper then that performed by a slave’. Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Indianapolis 1981), p. 87. On the rate of accumulation as the regulative force of labour market conditions, see Marx, Capital, vol. I, chap. 25. 33 Marx, Theories, p. 492. 34 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 880. 35 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 515. 36 See Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 716. 37 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 51.

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 97

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

98

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

38 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 87. 39 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 825. 40 See Backhaus, ‘Some Aspects of Marx’s Concept of Critique in the Context of His Economic-Philosophical Theory’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Komsas Psychopedis, Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism (Aldershot 2005). 41 Theodor Adorno, ‘Einleitung’, in Theodor Adorno, Hans Albert, Ralf Darendorf, Jürgen Habermas, Harald Pilot and Karl Popper, Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen Soziologie (Munich 1993), p. 23. 42 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 471. 43 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 460. 44 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 716. 45 Adorno, Gesellschaftstheorie, pp. 26–45. 46 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 255, translation altered. 47 Marx, From the Preparatory Materials, in Marx Engels Collected Works, vol. 29 (London 1987), p. 498. 48 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 716. See also p. 724. 49 Glassman, ‘Primitive Accumulation’, p. 610. 50 In Hegelian language, capitalist accumulation ‘posits its presupposition’. On this, in the context of Marx’s dialectical development of the economic categories, see Roberto Fineschi, ‘Dialectic of the Commodity and its Exposition’, in ed. Riccardo Bellofiore and Roberto Fineschi, Re-reading. New Perspectives after the Critical Edition (London 2009). Kosmas Psychopedis, ‘Dialectical Theory’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. I (London 1992). 51 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 102, 125. 52 Marx, Theories, p. 453, and Capital, vol. I, p. 167. 53 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 107. 54 Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx ’s Capital (Leiden 2004), pp. 64, 141. Arthur’s notion of history as a ‘chain of causality’ is most traditional in its view of the present. 55 Backhaus, Die Dialektik der Wertform (Freiburg 1997), p. 442. 56 Backhaus, ‘Über den Doppelsinn der Begriffe “politische Ökonomie” und “Kritik” bei Marx und in der Frankfurter Schule’, in ed. Stefan Dornuf and Reinhard Pitsch, Wolfgang Harich zum Gedächtnis, vol. II (München 2000), p. 178. Nor does he determine the meaning of abstract labour, except to say that it can be understood as general social labour, which for him contradicts the capitalist form of labour as private in character. Since abstract labour is social in character, he sees it as an inverted form of communism (p. 174), at the same as which he maintains against the Ricardian tradition that it is a peculiar capitalist form of labour.

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 98

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

99

CAPITAL AND LABOUR

57 Backhaus, ‘Über den Doppelsinn’, p. 127. Also Backhaus, ‘Between Philosophy and Science’, p. 81. 58 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 274. 59 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 494, fn. 4. Translation altered. 60 Helmut Reichelt, Zur logischen Struktur des Kapitalbegriffs bei Marx (Freiburg 2001), p. 270. 61 See Helmut Reichelt, ‘Die Marxsche Kritik ökonomischer Kategorien. Ueberlegungen zum Problem der Geltung in der dialektischen Darstellungsmethode im Kapital ’, in ed. Iring Fetscher and Alfred Schmidt, Emanzipation und Versöhnung. Zu Adornos Kritik der ‘Warentausch’Gesellschaft und Perpektiven der Transformation (Frankfurt 2002). 62 As documented and developed by, for example, Edward Palmer Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class (London 1968). Peter Linebaugh The London Hanged (London 2003). Christopher Hill, The World Turned Upside Down (London 1972), and Federici, Caliban and the Witch. 63 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination, p. 349. 64 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination, p. 158. Anthony Giddens, The Consequences of Modernity (Cambridge 1990). 65 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 273. 66 Karl Marx, From the Preparatory Materials, p. 505. 67 Alfred Schmidt, ‘Zum Erkenntnisbegriff der Kritik der politischen Ökonomie’, in ed. Walter Euchner and Alfred Schmidt, Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie heute. 100 Jahre ‘Kapital’ (Frankfurt 1968), pp. 35–6. 68 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 102, 168. 69 Louis Althusser, Essays in Self-Criticism (London 1976), pp. 129, 202–3, identifies the social individuals by their function and fits them into the economic structure as ‘bearers’ of structural properties. 70 Marx, Theories, p. 272. 71 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 723. 72 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 723, 928, 724, fn. 21. 73 Marx, Theories, pp. 475–76. 74 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 775, 730, 739, 739–40. 75 Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 452–3. 76 Marx, Theories, p. 272. 77 Marx, Theories, p. 929. 78 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 458. 79 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 929. 80 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 899. See Chapter 8 for an exposition of the force of exception in neoliberal thought. 81 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 246.

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 99

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

100

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

82 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 728. 83 See Mariarosa Dalla Costa, ‘Capitalism and Reproduction’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn, John Holloway and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. III (London 1995), p. 12. 84 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 799. 85 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 256. 86 Marx, Theories, p. 422.

9781441161390_Ch04_Final_txt_print.indd 100

2/19/2014 3:38:17 PM

5 Class and struggle: On the false society Introduction According to Adorno, Marx found economics ‘disgusting’, but he dealt with it, and this constituted part of his ‘genius’.1 Marx did not complete his critique of political economy and, as Adorno puts is, he ‘died over his exposition of the theory of class’ in the final chapter of Capital volume III.2 Adorno’s point is both right and wrong. At its best, Marx’s critique of political economy does not amount to a social theory of class. It amounts, rather, to a critique of ‘capital’ as a ‘social relationship between persons which is mediated through things’. 3 He is right in that Marx was seemingly unable to complete his chapter on class, which does not go much further than asking ‘what constitutes a class?’4 The use of the verb ‘constitutes’ contrasts sharply with the conventional Marxist attempt at developing an authoritative definition of class.5 How might it be possible to define ‘class’ within a critical project that emphasizes that theoretical mysteries find their rational explanation in the comprehension of the actual relations of life? The ‘definition’ of the working class would require at least one additional definition, namely that of the capitalist representing the other side of the class divide. Marx’s critique of political economy argued that the capitalist ‘is capital personified and endowed . . . with consciousness and a will’. The characterization of the capitalist and worker as ‘personifications of economic categories’, ‘bearers of particular class interests’, suggests that class is not a subjective category that derives from class consciousness.6 Rather, it suggests that class is an objective category of the false society. The labour market is a mysterious institution: the class tied to work is compelled to sell its labour power voluntarily to the owner of the means of subsistence. Both parties appear as equal legal subjects who are governed

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 101

2/19/2014 3:39:04 PM

102

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

by the law of contract according to which equivalent is exchanged for equivalent. Marx’s argument assumes that the commodity labour power is traded according to its value, like any other commodity. The labourer does not sell herself. She sells her labour power. However, the seller of labour power cannot be distinguished from the commodity that the capitalist has acquired and, as is his right, puts to use with the express aim that his investment yields a profit. For the seller of labour power, the purpose of the sale is to make a living mediated by wage income. For the buyer of labour power, it is the production of surplus value. Class thus characterizes a relationship between the ‘owners of the means of production and the producers of surplus value’.7 I hold that class is the critical category of the entire system of capitalist wealth, which appears in the form of an equivalent exchange between money and more money. This appearance is real. What appears in the appearance of the value form as an equivalence exchange relationship between unequal values (M . . . M’) is the surplus value that has been ‘pumped out of the workers’.8 Or as Adorno put it, the mysterious character of the value form lies ‘in the concept of surplus value’.9 The chapter argues that the understanding of ‘class’ can go forward only in and through the critique of ‘capital’ as ‘the form assumed by the conditions of labour’.10 In distinction to Postone, who argues that the capitalist ‘social forms cannot be fully grasped in terms of class categories’ and that any such attempt entails a ‘serious sociological reduction of Marx’s critique’, I argue that class is an objective category of a perverted system of wealth, and its production.11 It is the ‘logical and historical presupposition for the existence of individual capitalists and workers, and the basis on which the labour of one section of society is appropriated without equivalent by another’.12 It therefore denotes a social relationship that is independent from individuals while prevailing only in and through them. It is the foundation of the whole system of mysterious economic forces that manifest themselves behind the backs of the social individuals, on the pain of being cut off from the means of subsistence. That is to say, to be a productive labourer is not an ontologically privileged position, according to which the working class is the driving force of historical progress.13 Rather, ‘it is a great misfortune’.14 The critique of class society finds its positive resolution only in the classless society, not in a ‘fairer’ class society.

On class and classification In his short chapter on class, Marx answers his question ‘What constitutes a class?’ by saying ‘and the reply to this follows naturally from the reply to

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 102

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

103

another question, namely: What makes wage-labourers, capitalists and landlords constitute the three great social classes?’15 He then shows the difficulty in arriving at any sensible answer: each individual occupation will constitute its own class-group, a group that needs to be divided again and again to grasp the specificity of each category’s functional characteristic and socio-economic role.16 ‘Classification’ contradicts its very purpose: clarification is sought by classifying the social relations into distinctive segments with the result that social categories proliferate to such an extent that the classificatory project finishes up with an unmanageable number of definitions. Instead of clarity, definitions encourage, in the name of accuracy (!), an infinite number of categories. This in turn leads to the creation of more general classifications,17 such as the level or basis of income, to provide clarity where ‘accuracy’ failed. The notion of, for example, ‘income’ as a ‘tool’ to indicate ‘class characteristics’ was of course very much criticized by Marx in his chapter ‘The Trinity Formula’, which precedes his short chapter on ‘class’. Indeed, if class is understood as a social relationship, the definition of the social individuals according to economic positions, levels and sources of income, social status and labour market situation, eliminates ‘the critical function of concepts by claiming that their negative aspect simply does not exist’ as everybody is positively identified and classified.18 The revenue of the working class is the wage and the revenue source ‘wage’ defines the working class. This circularity of thought proliferates into many other circularities: capital’s revenue is profit, and landowners’ revenue is rent; and the psychoanalyst who is paid by the state from the taxes collected – merely, an unproductive service provider just as the social worker?19 All these groups stand not so much in relation with each other but, rather, in relation to each other. They relate externally to each other. The concept of social groups does not inform, and is not informed by, the concept of social relations: it reports, instead, on externally related things that are seen either to be colliding with one another20 or capable of interpolation.21 Is it really possible to view a group as a social relation? The theory of social stratification ‘classifies’ the social individuals as members of this or that social group according to some analytical criteria such as level of income, educational achievement, living standard, etc. In this manner it seeks to render intelligible the observable ‘facts’ of life without conceptualizing them as forms of definite social relations. Instead, it generalizes the ‘raw sense data’ of the ‘sign’ worker into a classificatory category and then applies the classification to the working class to signify it. In other words, first of all a norm is abstracted from empirically observable ‘signs’, and then it is in the light of this norm that the significance of these same signs is assessed. The empirically observable fact that a great number

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 103

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

104

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

of people are tied to work and make a living by means of wage income leads to the classification ‘working class’ as the ideal-type of the class that works, and then the classification working class is validated by the same reality from which the classification derived in the first place. This clearly tautological approach finds its raison d’être as a mathematical number game: the traditional working-class, however this suspect category might itself be defined, might or might not have declined. Were this research to find that there are no more workers but only ‘employees’, and that employment has been replaced by employability,22 would this mean that the class antagonism between capital and labour, that is, between the buyers of labour power and the producers of surplus value, has been transformed into a different set of social relations and form of social wealth?23 Within the classical Marxist tradition, ‘class’ is defined by its economic position. There is thus an argument about the ‘location’ of the working class in the production process, the ‘position’ of the working class in relation to capital on the labour market, the ‘differentiation’ between productive and unproductive labour in relation to the production of surplus value, the distinction between mental and manual labour, and the novelty of immaterial labour succeeding, it is said, its former materiality, etc.24 For this approach, the great embarrassment is the circumstance that there are social groups that do not fit into either of the two main classes, the working class and the capitalist class. Still, the embarrassment is only one of degree. All that is required is to introduce a new classificatory category into which those that stand in the middle between the two opposing classes can be assigned: the middle class. Again, this class is internally stratified based on income and status differentiations, ideological projections, closeness to working-class interests, backwardness in terms of ideological projection and social position, etc. In this context, the class struggle is conceived as a question of the leadership of the working class vis-à-vis other ‘class strata’ to ascertain the construction of likely class alliances. It is the position of the working class in the production process that privileges it as the revolutionary class in-itself. In order to become a class ‘for-itself’ it has to acquire the requisite revolutionary class-consciousness, which provision is a matter of revolutionary leadership.25 While favouring a vocabulary with a progressive ring, such as class position, class alliance, etc., the classical Marxist conception of class is entirely affirmative of the working class as the producer of social wealth, and perceives its position in production as an ontological privilege. In his Trinity Formula, Marx develops a robust critique of the theory of class proposed by classical political economy, and shared by modern sociology, including the classical Marxist tradition, according to which the component classes of society are determined according to the source of their revenue,

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 104

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

105

wages, rent and profit, which Weberian sociology perceives of in terms of market situation. Moishe Postone develops this sociology ostensibly as an alternative to the orthodox Marxist tradition. He argues that the Marxian theory does ‘of course include an analysis of class exploitation and domination’. But, he says, the critique of political economy ‘goes beyond investigating the unequal distribution of wealth and power within capitalism to grasp the very nature of its social fabric, its peculiar form of wealth’. It thus analyses, he argues, a definite ‘system’ of labour that is ‘structured by . . . the social forms of commodity and capital’ and argues that this system is differentiated from the life-world of class-relevant struggles over the (un)equal distribution of wealth.26 Terry Eagleton’s conception of class struggle brings this classical view into sharp focus. For Eagleton class is a category of ‘struggle over the surplus’ and he argues that the class struggle ‘is likely to continue as long as there is not sufficiency for all’.27 The class character of society has thus to do with the class-specific distribution of the ‘scarce’ economic resources that the structured system of labour produces. Eagleton’s views on the class struggle over scarce resources and the progress of wealth beyond scarcity falls into the tradition of political economy that Marx denounced as a ‘learned dispute . . . as to how the booty pumped out of the workers may be most advantageously divided for the purposes of accumulation’.28 In this tradition, the critical notion that the class relationship is constitutive of the capitalist form of wealth, which entails an equivalent exchange between the owner of the means of subsistence and the propertyless producer of surplus value, disappears from view. In its stead, it views the economic structure of capitalism as some objectively given framework of social development, and it is within this framework that the class struggle unfolds as a struggle over the spoils of the system of wealth – how much for wages, how much for profits? Conventionally, this idea of class as structurally embedded social force is expressed by the term ‘class in-itself’. The notion of a class ‘in-itself’ refers to capitalist social relations as objectified relations of economic nature. Class ‘in-itself’ is not a category that thinks out of society. Rather, it is a category of social observation, which articulates what is immediately apparent, that is, there is a class that is tied to work, it lives by wages and is the living factor of production. It thus defines this class by its labour market situation, contribution to the production process and wage-based access to the means of subsistence.29 That is, class ‘in-itself’ is not a critical category. Its employment leaves the so-called objective conditions entirely untouched by thought.30 Following Horkheimer’s account, the acceptance of society as an objectively structured thing constitutes the blind spot of dogmatic thought, which is predicated on the separation of the social existence from its genesis.31 Class relations cannot be derived from

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 105

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

106

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

the hypothesized ‘anatomy’ of bourgeois society and its – equally hypothesized – economic laws. Such a derivation transforms dialectical concepts of social practice into classificatory categories that describe reality abstractly without telling us what it is.32

Equivalence and surplus value: On class and competition There are of course such things as the market situation of the middle class and associated moralities and interests; and the location and position of working class in the social organization of capitalist wealth; and there is the capitalist spurred ‘into action’ by the forces of world-market competition to increase the productivity of labour as a means of avoiding bankruptcy – and there are also the categories of population and nation, national interest and transnational class, and hegemonic project. In order to comprehend the conceptuality of these terms, one has to find out about the relations of subsistence to decipher the movement of this divided, contradictory, fractured, disjointed, unsocial, antagonistic and thus coercive sociability of abstract wealth, in which equivalent is exchanged for equivalent on the expectation of a profitable return, whatever the product. The circumstance that buyer and seller of labour power meet on the labour market as equal legal subjects masks their fundamental inequality. Each individual carries the bond with society in her pocket. The buyer of labour power is the owner of the means of subsistence. The seller of labour power is free of them and at liberty to satisfy her needs by trading her capacity to work for a wage. Economic compulsion is a form of freedom that is experienced in and through a constant struggle to secure her living existence. A theory of society is critical on the condition that it conceives of society from within its mode of subsistence: what constitutes social wealth, why does the metabolism with nature take the form of money as more money, how is this wealth produced and by whom, what is the social necessity of this wealth, what lies within its concept and what does it have in store for the producers of wealth? There is no profit in equivalence exchange. Profit expresses a surplus in value that was pumped out of the labourer during the production process, here the labourer is a mere economic resource – ‘human material’ for the production of surplus value.33 This ‘valorization of value’ manifests its sociability in the civilized forms of equivalence exchange relations between the sellers and buyers of commodities; here the labourer trades her labour power for a wage to the owner of the means of production who views

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 106

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

107

her as a means for profit. Pace the idea of an analytically precise definition of the working class or any other social class or sociologically defined group, the notion of the working class is contradictory. Richard Gunn makes this point succinctly: the feet of the wage labourer ‘remain mired in exploitation even while [their heads breathe] in bourgeois ideological clouds’.34 These are the clouds of what Marx refers to as the ‘very Eden of the innate rights of man’ – this ‘exclusive realm of Freedom, Equality, Property, Bentham’, in which the economic compulsion appears in the form of a non-coerced equivalent exchange between equal legal subjects, each responding to price signals to advance their interests.35 The labour contract is the expression par excellence of capitalist freedom: it combines the freedom of trade in labour power with exploitation. Class is a living contradiction: Contradictions cannot be classified. Any such attempt would merely identify the individual as a bearer of this or that ascribed class characteristic. Class denotes a social relationship that though independent from the individuals, prevails in and through them as the dispossessed producers of surplus value whose access to subsistence depends on the successful sale of their labour power, and the conditions of trade are regulated by the rate of accumulation, and thus the profitable employment of their labour power in competition with all other workers. The category class has thus a double meaning: it entails the notion of class unity as the manifestation of the class antagonism between the classes, and it entails class disunity as a competitive relationship between the sellers of labour power. Unity qua disunity entails coercion as the condition of social reproduction. In Capital, Marx develops the capitalist class relations from the sale of the commodity labour power. In truth, however, ‘the sale of labour power presupposes coercion as the foundation of its sale’.36 For the seller of labour power, the original violence of dispossession appears in the civilized form of labour-market competition between this seller of labour power against that seller of labour power. Economic compulsion manifests itself as both a daily struggle for securing the means of subsistence by means of wage income and as competition among the sellers of labour power to achieve and maintain that income. For the seller of labour power, competition is not some abstract economic law. Rather, it is experienced in the form of precarious labour markets and pressure to secure the profitability of her employer as the basis of sustained employment. The class relation does not just amount to the wage relation; rather, it subsists through the wage relation. That is, the line of class antagonism falls not merely between but also, and importantly, through the social individuals. For the sellers of labour power, the freedom of contract entails the common class experience of labour-market competition. Competition is not a category of social unity. It is a category of

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 107

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

108

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

disunity. Class society exists in the form of individualized commodity owners, each seeking to maintain themselves in competitive, gendered and racialized, and also nationalized labour markets where the term cutthroat competition is experienced in various forms, from arson attack to class solidarity, and from destitution to collective bargaining, from gangland thuggery to communal forms of organizing subsistence-support, from strike-breaking to collective action. The critique of political economy does not conceive of the economic categories as personalized forms of class power. Rather, it conceptualizes capital as social relationship that manifests itself in the form of seemingly independent economic forces. Thus, as Marx put it in his short chapter on class, ‘we have already seen that the continual tendency and law of development of the capitalist mode of production is more and more to divorce the means of production from labour, and more and more to concentrate the scattered means of production into large groups, thereby transforming labour into wage-labour and the means of production into capital’.37 In Marx’s critique, there is hardly any reference to ‘class consciousness’, if any. His notion of the working class, as that of the capitalist, was ‘objective’ insofar as both wage labourer and capitalist are personifications of a social world that subsists, contradictorily, as a relationship between things. The law of class society is what ‘remains in disappearance’.38 Capitalist social relations are founded on dispossessed labour and in its appearance, dispossession disappears in the form of the free labourer who as an equal legal subject is governed by the rule of law, as a private citizen who is responsible for herself. Personal coercion and dependency disappears in the appearance of economic compulsion, which binds the ‘wage labourer . . . to his owner by invisible threads’.39 What remains in disappearance, too, is the law of accumulation, which entails the expanded reproduction of social wealth in the form of capital, perpetuating its constitutive presupposition in dispossessed labour on an expanding scale; in its own time, says the Communist Manifesto, it penetrates ‘Chinese walls’. What also remains in disappearance is the capitalist form of social labour, which entails the free labourer as the productive factor of surplus value that appears in the world-market form of factor competitiveness, measured by the rate of profit. Capitalist accumulation in ‘no way alters[s] the fundamental character of capitalist production’. It continuously reproduces ‘the capital relation . . . on an expanded scale’.40 Capital is not a ‘thing’ and the standpoint of capital and labour is the same and not the same.41 Both, the labourer and the capitalist are personifications of the perverted reality of value. The one owns the means of subsistence and buys the labour power of another Man, transforming it into labour activity so that his investment may lay golden eggs, which it has to on

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 108

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

109

the pain of ruin; the other sells her labour power to the owner of the means of subsistence to secure access to the means of human subsistence by wage income, that is, by the continuous sale of her labour power. The one struggles with great courage and determination to achieve higher wages and lessen the burden of work. The other tries to pay as little as possible and demands greater productive effort to make a profit. Class struggle is incessant. It belongs to the concept of bourgeois society. It characterizes its disunity as the condition of its perverted unity. For the sake of subsistence the labourer cannot live without selling her labour power, and thus depends for her life on the progressive accumulation of capital by which the owner of the means of production converts the extracted surplus value back into economic activity, employing the labourer by yesterday’s yield of surplus value. Her continuous access to subsistence rests on the profitability of her labour, that is, on the effective exploitation of her labouring existence by the buyer of labour power. Relating to each other as antagonistic members of opposing classes, each presupposes the other, and each produces the other, not by their own personal will but by means of an objective social process that prevails not only over them but also in and through them. Thus, the capitalist and wagelabourer ‘are as such merely embodiments, personifications of capital and wage-labour; definite social characteristics stamped upon individuals by the process of social production’.42 That is, sensuous activity not only vanishes in the supersensible world of economic things, it also appears in it – with a price tag; and what appears with a price tag is the dispossessed producer of surplus value, who makes a living by trading her labour power for a wage. Society reproduces itself by virtue of struggle, this manifestation of the ‘sheer unrest of life’ for access to the means of subsistence and also for life-time over labour-time. The class struggle is the objective necessity of the false society. It belongs to its concept.43

Labour and surplus value The ghost walking of Monsieur le Capital and Madame la Terre that Marx talks about in his critique of the classical conception of class, is founded on the incessant consumption of living labour during the working day.44 For the sake of bringing the production of surplus value into sharp focus, Marx assumed that the seller of labour power receives a wage that expresses the value of her labour power. He developed the concept of surplus value, and with it the law of value as the law of valorization, on the basis of an equivalent exchange between two property owners. The value of labour power is determined like

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 109

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

110

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

the value of any other commodity. It is the socially necessary labour time required for the production and thus reproduction of this specific commodity, with the one exception of a moral and historical element, which accrues to it as a consequence of the class struggle in the form of, for example, favourable wage conditions and systems of welfare support, etc.45 The circumstance that the labourer depends for her subsistence on the successful sale of her labour power does not violate the law of equivalent exchange. It merely focuses the ‘sheer unrest of life’ in the constituted form of freedom. Once the labour contract has been signed, the capitalist has acquired the right to consume the commodity that he has acquired for the duration of the contract, and the labourer has relinquished her rights to her property. There is however a distinction between the commodity labour power and the other commodities. The buying, say, of an apple entails its consumption. The buying of labour power also entails its consumption. However, the commodity labour power is inseparable from its seller. The consumption of labour power is therefore consumption of the labourer. Yet, according to the contract, the seller of labour power was not bought, only her labour power. According to the liberal rule of rule of law, subjects of law exchange commodities by their own free will, and slavery is not permitted. The seller of labour power does thus not sell herself as a person to the highest bidder. The free labourer is not obliged to any person in particular. Instead, she is subjected to the freedom of the labour market. Nevertheless, the working class ‘is just as much an appendage of capital as the lifeless instruments of labour are . . . The appearance of independence is maintained by means of a constant change in the person of the individual employers, and by the legal fiction of contract.’46 As an independent subject of exchange the labourer is entirely responsible for herself, which includes her right to restrict the expenditure of her labour power during the working day in order to maintain herself as a person. The right of the capitalist to consume the acquired commodity labour power is pitted against the right of the worker to resist the consumption of her labour power in order to maintain her health, integrity and, indeed, secure her survival. Since the labourer did not sell herself but only her labour power, and since the consumption of her labour power entails nevertheless the consumption of the labourer, class struggle is incessant. Between two equal rights, Marx writes, force decides, ranging from the force of starvation that Adam Smith talks about when highlighting the futility of strikes, to the force of the state that Marx talks about in his analyses of the struggle over the limits of the working day.47 The class character of the capitalist form of wealth entails distinct conceptions of social time. On the one hand, there is the socially necessary labour time, which determines the value of the commodity labour power.

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 110

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

111

On the other, there is the time of the labour process as a production process of capitalist wealth. Here labour power is transformed into actual labour activity for the duration of the length of the working day. These two notions of time are distinct. Adorno’s point that the trading of labour power amounts fundamentally to a social relationship between the buyers of labour power and the producers of surplus value says that the working day is divided into two distinct temporalities.48 During a part of the working day, the doubly free labourer ‘produces himself as labour capacity, as well as the capital confronting him’ and during another part, her labour expands the existing social wealth in the form of capital, that is, in the form of surplus value.49 The working day is thus divided into two parts, one in which labour reproduces the value of her labour power and the other in which she adds to the existing wealth, essentially working for free. The first part represents the labour time necessary for reproducing the existing social wealth, the other the surplus labour time for the creation of surplus value, that is, the labour time of profit. In order to generate surplus value, the necessary labour time needs to be a fraction of the total of the working day, positing the surplus labour time of profit. The time of production is the time of a struggle over the appropriation of surplus labour time.50 Surplus labour time is the foundation of capitalist wealth. ‘All surplus value . . . is in substance the materialisation of unpaid labour.’51 In order for the worker to be a producer of surplus value, the necessary labour time of the worker appears as a limit to the production of capitalist wealth. Time, then, really is not only money. It is also more money. The workers’ surplus labour time is the foundation of profit, and profits need to be made to avoid bankruptcy. Labouring for the sake of a surplus in value is innate to the concept of the worker, who by selling her labour power sold herself as a living means of greater wealth. From within the concept of capitalist wealth, the labourer really is the living embodiment of value – a living factor of the economy of time, a time’s carcass of surplus labour, a means of profit. From within the concept of capital, the labourer is the agent of unpaid surplus labour time. She belongs to a system of wealth that posits her necessary labour time as the contested foundation of surplus labour time. Labour has a utility only as a means of surplus value. The loss of labour time is a loss for surplus value. For the sake of profit, time cannot be wasted. Capitalist wealth depends on the imposition of necessary labour, as the constituent side of surplus labour, upon the world’s working classes. The relationship between necessary labour and surplus labour is a relationship between two mutually dependent and antagonistically related parts of the working day. Necessary labour is the foundation of surplus labour and the expansion of surplus labour entails the reduction of necessary labour as a

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 111

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

112

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

portion of the working day. This relationship between the time of necessary labour and the time of surplus labour expresses the class relationship between the buyers of labour power and the producers of surplus value. It entails not only the class struggle over the capitalist attempt at reducing the workers’ life-time (Lebenszeit ) to labour-time. Fundamentally, it entails the class struggle over the reduction of the workers’ life-time to surplus labour time. Within a given length of the working day, the reduction of necessary labour time relative to surplus labour time is a function of the increase in labour productivity, which cheapens the value of labour power by reducing the socially necessary labour time required for its reproduction. There is thus a relative increase in the time of surplus value production over the time necessary for the reproduction of the value of labour power. However, the increase in labour productivity also means that less and less socially necessary labour time is required to produce individual use-values. There is thus an increase in material wealth as more usevalues are produced in a given time. However, this increase in material wealth posits a problem for the capitalist form of wealth. The increase in ‘material wealth may correspond to a simultaneous fall in the magnitude of its value’.52 That is, with the increase in the productivity of labour, the socially necessary labour time for the production of a commodity declines with potentially crisis-ridden consequences, in the form, say, of overflowing markets, falling rates of profit, declining rates of accumulation as less profits are available for reinvestment into expanded production, leading to the intensification of competition to secure existing values, and to thus renewed efforts to increase labour productivity in an attempt at maintaining competitiveness on the pain of destruction.53 The capitalist does not decide by his own free will to produce surplus value for the sake of more surplus value. The decision is taken for him by the law of value that in the form of competition asserts ‘the immanent laws of capitalist production . . . as external coercive laws’.54 In order therefore to preserve his capital he is ‘compelled to keep on extending his capital’ and can only ‘extend . . . by means of progressive accumulation’, which in its effect makes the proletarian ‘merely a machine for the production of surplus value’ and the ‘capitalist too is merely a machine for the transformation of this surplus value into surplus capital’.55 For the labourer, the creation of greater social wealth is contradictory: The law ‘by which a constantly increasing quantity of means of production may be set in motion by a progressively diminishing expenditure of labour power, thanks to the advance in the productivity of social labour, undergoes a complete inversion, and is expressed thus: the higher the productiveness of labour, the greater the pressure of the workers on the means of employment, the more precarious, therefore becomes the condition of their existence, namely the sale of their own labour power.’56 That

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 112

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

113

is, the increase in the productivity of labour does not entail the shortening of the working day. It is only the shortening of the necessary labour time that is aimed for.57 The increase in the productivity of labour and a readily available reserve army of labour are two sides of the same necessity of curtailing the necessary labour time of the worker in favour of the surplus labour time that generates profits. Profit is a vanishing moment of capitalist social wealth. Sustaining it requires the progressive expansion of capital, that is, the ‘secret of the self-valorization of capital resolves itself into the fact that it has at its disposal a definite quantity of the unpaid labour’ of dispossessed workers.58 In sum, for the worker, the increase in her labour productivity manifests a great calamity. Every increase in labour productivity shortens the hours of labour but in its capitalist form, it lengthens them. The introduction of sophisticated machinery lightens labour but in its capitalist form, heightens the intensity of labour. Every increase in the productivity of labour increases the material wealth of the producers but in its capitalist form makes them paupers. Most important of all, greater labour productivity sets labour free, makes labour redundant. But rather than shortening the hours of work and thus absorbing all labour into production on the basis of a shorter working day, freeing life-time from the ‘realm of necessity’, those in employment are exploited more intensively, while those made redundant find themselves on the scrap heap of a mode of production that sacrifices ‘human machines’ on the ‘pyramids of accumulation’.59 That is, ‘the coercive character of society’ manifests itself as if by law of nature, which ‘consumes each one of us, skin and hair’.60 However, the circumstance that the capitalist and the labourer are both personifications of economic categories does not entail that they are both equally enslaved to an economic logic that asserts itself behind their backs. For the capitalist, the law of value is a means of great social wealth, whereas for the labourer it entails not only economic compulsion, labour market competition for wage-based access to subsistence, but also her existence as a human resource of surplus value. Although the capitalist is a mere personification of an economic system that asserts itself on the pain of bankruptcy, he ‘rules through it’.61 Social labour is held by invisible threads to the capitalist. Indeed, ‘in reality, the worker belongs to capital before he has sold himself to the capitalist’.62 Still, the trade in labour power does not violate the laws of the equivalent exchange. Equivalent is exchanged for equivalent and yet, ‘the content is the constant appropriation by the capitalist, without an equivalence, of a portion of the labour of others’, that is, the ‘constant sale and purchase of labour power’ is ‘a mere semblance belonging to the process of circulation’. There is then only an ‘apparent exchange’. Although the capitalist is assumed to buy labour power at its value, the capital that is exchanged for a wage ‘is itself merely a portion of the product of the labour of others which

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 113

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

114

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

has been appropriated without an equivalent’ and furthermore, the capital that the worker received as a wage ‘must not only be replaced by its producer, the worker, but replaced together with an added surplus’.63 Capital presupposes the wage labourer as the producer of surplus value; and the wage labourer not only presuppose the capitalist as the employer of labour power, she is also dependent on the capitalist as the buyer of her labour power. She lives by the sale of her labour power, and is incessantly forced ‘to sell [her] labour power in order to live, and enables the capitalist to purchase labour-power in order that he may enrich himself’.64 The one seeks to subsist, the other to make a profit. ‘And this is what is called: creating capital out of capital.’65 Adorno’s point that the capitalist rules through those same perverted economy categories that control him, is to the point: The separation of labour from the means of subsistence asserts itself in the form of an equivalent exchange between the compelled producer of surplus value and the owner of the means of subsistence. The antagonistic character of this relation manifests itself in the process of capitalist accumulation, in which the ‘working class creates by the surplus labour of one year the capital destined to employ additional labour in the following year’.66 The class relationship comprises not only the social antagonism between those who control the means of production and those who are divorced from them. It comprises also the buying of labour power with the money that the unpaid labour of the previous year made for the owner of the means of subsistence. That is, capital is ‘essentially command over unpaid labour’.67 Bourgeois society does not include the class antagonism as one of its moments. Rather, it is founded on it, and reproduces itself ‘through it’.68

Conclusion: Class and critique Class is not primarily a category of consciousness. It is a category of a perverse form of social objectification. In the person of the worker, capital encounters ‘the human material’ for the progressive accumulation of abstract wealth.69 The worker is the living embodiment of ‘personified labour time’ and, in reality, that is the surplus labour time of surplus value production.70 The separation of the labourer from the means of subsistence entails the common class experience of economic compulsion to sell her labour power to the ‘commander’ of ‘unpaid paid labour time’, which in time transforms into the money that buys another Man. Economic compulsion subsists in the form of the freedom of the labour market, which manifest the common class experience for class unity and collective action. It also manifests the

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 114

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

115

common class experience of labour market disunity as each individual seller of labour power competes against the other for employment as the condition of gaining access to the means of life. Primitive accumulation, this struggle that freed master from serf and serf from master is constitutive of the relation between capital and labour. It is therefore not just the case that ‘class practice ensues through perverted social forms’.71 Class struggle is also ‘the fundamental premise of class ’.72 Once the separation of labour from the means of production and subsistence is taken for granted, the capitalist social relations appear in the form of an abstract market structure whose empirical reality is mediated by class struggle.73 In this account, social class is condemned to carry the burden of classification.74 However, economic abstractions as such do not exist, except as a negative ontology of ‘perverted’ (verrückte ) social relations. It is only ‘in the last, most derivative forms that the various aspects of capital appear as the real agencies and direct representatives of production. Interest-bearing capital is personified in the moneyed capitalist, industrial capital in the industrial capitalist, rent-bearing capital in the landlord as the owner of land, and lastly, labour in the wage-worker.’ These enter into competition as ‘independent personalities that appear at the same time to be mere representatives of personified things’.75 In the relationship between things, of one commodity to another, labour’s social productive force is ‘invisible’. The appearance of the social individuals as members of distinct social groups that operate within the framework of an abstract market structure characterizes the ‘bewitched world’ of capital as the automatic social subject.76 It is this ‘bewitched world’ of personified economic categories that the competing sociologies of system theory and the theory of social action, or, in the terms of the classical Marxist tradition, the dialectics of economic structure and human agency, seek to render intelligible through analytical schemes of classification. This chapter argued that ‘class’ is the critical concept of the false society. Innate to its concept is the dispossessed labourer as a self-responsible personification of essentially unpaid labour time. Class exists in-itself as a relationship between antagonistic personifications of the law of value. It therefore also exists ‘for-itself’ because the relations between things presuppose the pre-positing action of separation that is reproduced by ‘active humanity’ in and through her class-divided social practice. Neither do things exchange themselves with themselves, nor do the naturally conceived forces of production exploit labour. It follows that class does not only exist in-itself and for-itself. It subsists also ‘against-itself’ as, on the one hand, a perverted social category and, on the other, as the living premise of its own reified world.77

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 115

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

116

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Notes 1 Theodor Adorno, ‘Seminar Mitschrift of 1962’, in Appendix to Hans-Georg Backhaus, Dialektik der Wertform (Freiburg 1997), p. 513. 2 Theodor Adorno, Gesellschaftstheorie und Kulturkritik (Frankfurt 1975), p. 15. 3 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 932, see also p. 92. 4 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. III (London 1966), p. 886. 5 See Jürgen Ritsert, Soziale Klassen (Münster 1998) for a useful account of this attempt, and its failure. 6 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 25, 92. 7 Dirk Braunstein, Adornos Kritik der politischen Ökonomie (Bielefeld 2011), p. 338. 8 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 743. 9 Adorno, ‘Mitschrift’, p. 508. 10 Karl Marx, Theories of Surplus Value, vol. 3 (London 1972), p. 492. 11 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory (Cambridge 1996), p. 153. Postone is right to say that it makes no sense to derive the value relations from the agents of value. What makes sense, though, is to comprehend by means of critique the autonomization of the social relations into seemingly separate forms of systemic structure and human agency. As I argued in Chapter 4, having cut off the genesis of the class relations from the existing social relations, Postone is left with a traditional conception of social structure and social action, and the perennial question of analysis is thus which of these conceptions determines the other. None is explained, and in line with traditional sociology, Postone opts for the social structure as the determinate force. 12 Simon Clarke, Marx, Marginalism and Modern Sociology (London 1991), p. 118. 13 This view is central to Erik O Wright’s account in Classes (London 1985) and Class Counts (Cambridge 1997). 14 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 644. 15 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 886. 16 On class and class fraction, see Nicos Poulantzas, Political Power and Social Classes (London 1973) and Classes in Contemporary Capitalism (London 1975). See Bob Jessop, Nicos Poulantzas: Marxist Theory and Political Strategy (London 1985) for a political reading of class fractions as the foundation of distinct hegemonic projects. For a critique along the lines developed in this book, see Simon Clarke, ‘Capital, Fractions of Capital and the State’, Capital & Class, vol. 2, no. 2 (1978), pp. 32–77. 17 These general classifications are usually called, with Weber, ideal types. 18 Theodor Adorno, Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge 2008a), p. 139.

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 116

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

117

19 Marx treats productive labour and unproductive labour as critical categories. They reveal the circumstance that in capitalism only that labour is productive that produces (surplus) value. 20 See, for example, Anthony Giddens, The Consequences of Modernity (Cambridge 1990), who argues that society comprises distinct institutional ‘complexes’, each of which develops through distinct conflicts that collide with one another, including the economic complex and the conflict between capital and labour, the military complex and the peace movement, the administrative complex and the human rights conflict, the industrial complex and the ecological conflict, etc. In this account, society comprises the interests of a multitude of colliding groups. 21 See Louis Althusser, Lenin and Philosophy (New York 1971), pp. 160–5, on how distinctive class places might be interpolated. 22 The shift from employment to employability is recent. In social theory, Anthony Giddens, The Third Way (Cambridge 1998) argued for it most strongly. Employability entails the disappearance of the idea of the worker as a proletarian. Instead, the term defines the worker as an entrepreneur of labour power. Ulrich Beck, ‘Die Seele der Demokratie’, Gewerkschaftliche Monatshefte, no. 6/7 (1998), pp. 330–5, brought this out neatly when he argued that the worker is a labour-force-employer. This idea goes back to the tradition of American neoliberalism, which perceived the worker as an investor into ‘human capital’. See, for example, Journal of Political Economy (vol. 66, no. 4, pp. 281–302 (1958), vol. 68, no. 6, pp. 571–83 (1960), vol. 70, no. 5, Part 2, pp. 1–157 (1962). In this tradition, capitalist society is a society of investors. Some invest into the means of production, some invest into financial markets, and others invest into labour capacity. In either case, each investor seeks a profitable return in the form of profit, interest and wage income. The term employability recognizes neither employment nor unemployment. It recognizes the worker as an entrepreneur of labour power; the worker ‘floats’ from this employment to that employment, seeking better investment opportunities for her human capital, that is, labour power. On this see, Werner Bonefeld, ‘Human Economy and Social Policy’, History of the Human Sciences, vol. 26, no. 2 (2013), pp. 106–25. 23 Ulrich Beck, Risk Society (London 1992), p. 100, puts this well when he argues that ‘class society will pale into insignificance beside an industrialized society of employees ’. Beck later clarified his position when he and his co-author argue that ‘the antagonisms between men and women over gender roles’ amount to ‘the “status struggle” which comes after the class struggle’; Ulrich Beck and Elisabeth Beck-Gernsheim, The Normal Chaos of Love (Cambridge 1995), p. 2. In seems that in the mind set of the Becks, their consciousness of gender struggle describes the fundamental character of the new social relations of status, replacing the relations of production. Marx’s critique of political economy does not derive the existence of classes from class-consciousness. He analyses the manner in which society organizes its social reproduction.

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 117

2/19/2014 3:39:05 PM

118

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

24 On immaterial labour see, Carlo Vercellone, ‘From Formal Subsumption to General Intellect: Elements for a Marxist Reading of the Thesis of Cognitive Capitalism’, Historical Materialism, vol. 15, no. 1 (2007), pp. 13–36. On the location, position and fractional differentiation of the working class see, for example, Poulantzas, Political Power and Wright, Classes. Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory, p. 316, rightly rejects Wright’s class theory as a ‘variegated picture of social groupings’. Yet, he, too, endorses a version of this theory. See Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory, pp. 314–16. 25 For a recent account, see Callinicos, ‘Is Leninism finished?’ Socialist Review, January 2013; http://www.socialistreview.org.uk/article. php?articlenumber=12210 (accessed 28 March 2013). See also Georg Lukács, Lenin: A Study in the Unity of His Thought (London 1997). 26 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory, pp. 153, 314, 153. 27 Terry Eagleton, Why Marx was Right (New Haven 2011), p. 43. 28 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 743. 29 The earlier quotation from Marx is relevant here: the ‘separation between the in-itself and the for-itself, of substance and subject, is abstract mysticism’. Karl Marx, Contribution to the Critique of Hegel ’s Philosophy of Law, in Collected Works, vol. 1 (London 1975), p. 62. 30 See Max Horkheimer, Kritische und Traditionelle Theorie (Frankfurt 1992), p. 246. 31 Max Horkheimer, Zur Kritik der instrumentellen Vernunft (Frankfurt 1985), p. 84. 32 Adorno, Gesellschaftstheorie, chap. 6. 33 Marx, Capital, p. 740. 34 Richard Gunn, ‘Notes on Class’, Common Sense, no. 2 (1987), p. 18. 35 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 280. 36 Theodor Adorno cited in Braunstein, Adornos Kritik, p. 217. 37 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 885. 38 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Hegel ’s Dialectics (New Haven 1982), p. 42. 39 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 719. 40 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 763. 41 See Marx, Capital, vol. III, chap. 48. 42 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 880. 43 According to Holloway, Change the World without Taking Power (London 2002) and Crack Capitalism (London 2010), the class struggle not only belongs to bourgeois society, it also points beyond bourgeois society. I reckon the crux of the matter is what this ‘beyond’ might be. The class struggle for subsistence does not foretell the future. It does however entail a profound judgement on the existing relations of social wealth. See

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 118

2/19/2014 3:39:06 PM

119

CLASS AND STRUGGLE

Horkheimer, Kritische, p. 244, for an argument that the critical theory of society amounts to ‘an unfolded judgment on existence’. The notion ‘sheer unrest of life’ is Hegel’s; see Chapter 3, fn. 41. Its employment here does not contradict the argument about the forces of economic compulsion. It suggests, on the contrary, that economic compulsion is not some abstract idea. It is an experienced ‘life’-category. On this, see Oskar Negt and Alexander Kluge, Public Sphere and Experience (Minneapolis, MN 1993). 44 Marx, Capital, vol. III, chap. 48. 45 The socialist idea of distributive justice focuses on this moral element as the basis of achieving a just society. See Gerald A. Cohen, ‘Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 26, no. 1 (1997), pp. 3–30. Affluent workers do not come into possession of the means of subsistence. In the language of Weber, as traders of their own labour power, they have achieved a favourable market situation. 46 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 719. 47 Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Indianapolis 1981), p. 91. Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 344. 48 Adorno, ‘Mitschrift’. 49 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 458. 50 I discuss the time of capitalist wealth in Chapter 6. 51 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 672. 52 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 137. 53 On the crisis-ridden character of capitalist reproduction, see Simon Clarke, Marx ’s Theory of Crisis (London 1994). Joseph Schumpeter’s, Capitalism, Socialism & Democracy (London 1992) notion that the process of capitalist wealth is one of ‘creative destruction’ recognizes its crisis-ridden character, and without further ado defines it as a ‘creative’ force. See Chapter 7 for an account of capitalist crisis. 54 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 739, see also p. 391. 55 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 739, 742. 56 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 798. 57 See Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 437–8. 58 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 672. 59 I owe this expression to Ferruccio Gambino, ‘A Critique of the Fordism of the Regulation School’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Revolutionary Writing (New York 2003). On the calamities of greater labour productivity, see Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 568–9. 60 Adorno, Gesellschaftstheorie, p. 24. 61 Adorno, Gesellschaftstheorie, p. 19. 62 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 723. 63 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 729. 64 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 723.

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 119

2/19/2014 3:39:06 PM

120

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

65 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 729. 66 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 729. 67 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 672. 68 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 337. 69 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 740. 70 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 352–3. 71 Helmut Reichelt, ‘Social Reality as Appearance: Some Notes on Marx’s Concept of Reality’, in Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism, ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis (Aldershot 2005), p. 65. 72 Gunn, ‘Notes on Class’, p. 16. See also Clarke, Marx, Marginalism. 73 Jacques Bidet’s structuralist interpretation of Capital develops this view with great sophistication. Bidet, Exploring Marx ’s Capital: Philosophical, Economic and Political Dimensions (Chicago 2009). Postone’s account reaches the same conclusion. 74 Louis Althusser, Essays in Self-Criticism (London 1976), pp. 129, 202–3, thus identifies the social individuals by their function and fits them into the economic structure as ‘bearers’ of structural properties. 75 Marx, Theories, p. 514. 76 Marx, Theories, pp. 467, 514. 77 In the language of Adorno’s negative dialectics, the ‘living premise’ is the non-conceptual content of the (economic) concept; see Chapter 3.

9781441161390_Ch05_Final_txt_print.indd 120

2/19/2014 3:39:06 PM

6 Time is money: On abstract labour Introduction Abstract labour is the pivotal concept of the critique of political economy – it is the value-producing labour. Marx’s account of abstract labour is ambivalent.1 On the one hand, he conceives of it as ‘a specific social form of labour’.2 Its reality is ‘purely social’ and it appears in the social relations of ‘commodity to commodity’.3 On the other hand, he defines it physiologically as ‘productive expenditure of human brains, nerves, and muscles’.4 Physiologically conceived, abstract labour is as Makato Itoh put it, a natural property that comprises the ‘general economic norms or rules common to all the forms of society’. In capitalism, it is ‘embodied in commodities’ and measured by labour time.5 In this view, abstract labour denotes the expenditure of human energy in production. Massimo de Angelis also locates abstract labour in production.6 Yet, he sees it as a specifically capitalist form of labour that results from a history of class struggle over the control of the labour process, leading to the progressive deskilling of labour. He thus conceives of abstract labour in terms of a general labour that can be applied in every labour process, whatever the specific product might be. It is an abstract labour because it abstracts from the specific content of work, and is thus truly general in its character.7 In distinction to these interpretations, this chapter develops abstract labour as a socially determined, specifically capitalist form of labour that manifests itself in exchange and, instead of being ‘the’ labour of muscles and nerves, it argues that the materiality that holds sway in its concept is not some discernible substance. Rather, it comprises the time of value, that is, socially necessary labour time. This approach to abstract labour goes back to Isaak

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 121

2/19/2014 3:44:07 PM

122

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Rubin’s work on value, which was re-discovered in the early 1970s. Rubin had argued that one of two things is possible: if abstract labour is an expenditure of human energy in physiological form, then value has a reified-material character. Or value is a social phenomenon, and then abstract labour must also be understood as a social phenomenon connected with a determined social form of production. It is not possible to reconcile a physiological concept of abstract labour with the historical character of the value which it creates.8 For the critical tradition, the ‘determination of abstract labour as a physiological expenditure of labour-power leads to the crudest understanding of value and the loss of the socially specific character of value-creating labour’.9 De Vroey thus rejected the physiological definition of abstract labour as a ‘naturalistic deformation of the social reality of capitalism’, one which develops Marx’s theory of value as a refined and improved version of Ricardo’s labour theory of value.10 Ricardo’s labour theory of value did not distinguish between concrete labour and abstract labour.11 Instead, it treated labour as an undifferentiated category that holds true for all societies. The capitalist form of labour appears thus as a manifestation of ‘the’ labour, that is, as ‘the productive activity of human being in general, by which they promote the interchange with nature, divested not only of every social form and determinate character, but even in its bare natural existence, independent of society, removed from all societies’.12 Capitalist labour appears trans-historical because of its concrete, use-value producing character. However, this concrete, use-value producing labour is not the labour that produces capitalist wealth. The labour that produces the exchange value of commodities is abstract labour. The capitalist form of labour is a directly social labour in that it produces for exchange, and the value of this labour is therefore its exchange value. Exchange value is thus not something that is embodied in individual commodities. It is a ‘social value’. The value-validity of the labour expended in production is therefore established in exchange.13 In distinction to the physiological definition of abstract labour as a trans-historical materiality of economic production the value-producing labour is historically specific. It comprises what Marx calls the ‘double character of labour’ as both concrete labour and abstract labour. This labour contains ‘the whole secret of the critical conception’.14 Indeed, the fetishism of commodities ‘arises from the peculiar social character of the labour which produces them’.15 Postone argued, therefore, that the critique of political economy does not criticize capitalism from the standpoint of labour. Rather, it amounts to a critique of labour.16 This chapter develops this

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 122

2/19/2014 3:44:07 PM

TIME IS MONEY

123

insight towards a critique of the double character of labour. For Marx, ‘all understanding of the facts ’ depends on it.17 The understanding of the double character of labour rests on the comprehension of abstract labour. Marx staggers about from naturalized conceptions of abstract labour to its characterization as a purely capitalist form of labour. Most recently, Axel Kicillof and Guido Starosta have offered a vigorous defence of the physiological conception of abstract labour, which they develop as a trans-historical category that in capitalism is ‘represented’ by the value-form. The next section introduces their account and examines their critique of the contributions by de Angelis and Arthur, who, for different reasons, see abstract labour as a specifically capitalist category. These three accounts represent the spectrum of debate about abstract labour.18 Notwithstanding the ambivalence in Marx’s own text, the final section expounds abstract labour as a specifically capitalist form of labour, one that expresses an entirely invisible substance – socially necessary labour time.

Abstract labour and its social form Axel Kicillof and Guido Starosta see abstract labour as the material foundation of the human metabolism with nature. Man has to exchange with nature, and they characterize this exchange as the ‘generic determination of labour’. However, the circumstance that Man has to exchange with nature does not say anything about the mode of production. Nor is labour in the abstract possible. The reality of labour is always concrete. They therefore argue that the trans-historical nature of abstract labour expresses itself differently in distinct modes of production. Its trans-historical materiality obtains thus through historically specific social forms. In capitalism, abstract labour entails therefore ‘both a generic material determination and a historically-specific role as the substance of value’. They thus argue that ‘the real “genuine” object of the critique of political economy [is] not the pure realm of social forms, but the contradictory unity between the materiality of human life and its historicallydetermined social forms’. They thus see abstract labour as a general economic category that manifests itself in capitalism as the historically specific labour of abstract social wealth, of value.19 Their exposition focuses only on the capitalist form of abstract labour, which provides the illustration for both its historically specific existence as the substance of value and its natural, trans-historical materiality of production in general. This then begs the question whether it reveals the ontology of abstract labour or whether it naturalizes capitalist economic categories. For Starosta,

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 123

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

124

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

abstract labour comprises an expenditure of bodily energy – in production, in exchange with nature, indifferent to concrete purposes, a mere expenditure of ‘corporeal power’.20 As physiological expenditure of human energy, labour appears as an enduring economic law regardless of the time and the content of ‘the’ labour. Makato Itoh puts this point most clearly when he says that the recognition of ‘the’ labour ‘was made possible by the development of modern capitalist commodity economy. However, once obtained, the recognition can possibly be applicable to other social formations.’21 Thus, akin to the structuralist account, Marx’s analysis of capitalism is said to have led him to the discovery of general historical laws, which, in the case of abstract labour, established its ontological significance. Marx, says Itoh, recognized the basic condition ‘of the metabolism between human beings and nature as general economic norms in the analysis of the labour-and-production process’.22 Since abstract labour is viewed as a natural condition of human existence, its critique amounts fundamentally to a critique of its capitalist form as an ‘as if’ of socialist rationalization. If abstract labour really is expenditure of bodily energy, then it can indeed be defined without further ado in precise physiological terms. That is, ‘muscles burn sugar’.23 Muscles have burned sugar since time immemorial and will continue to do so, indifferent to historical development – and in this way expenditure of bodily energy appears indifferent to concrete purposes and distinct modes of production, and thus truly abstract. For Kicillof and Startosta the physiological determination is the only meaningful definition of abstract labour, which, as much as its concrete aspect, is a purely material form, bearing no social or historical specificity. And yet, when performed privately and independently, and once congealed in the natural materially of the product of labour, that purely material form acquires the form of value of the commodity, i.e. a purely social form that embodies ‘not an atom of matter’. Their critique of Rubin’s form of analysis is thus easily understood. Rubin did not ask how, in capitalism, labour ‘in the physiological sense becomes specific in terms of value’. His mistake was thus to ‘surrender to the selfevident fact that the identity between different concrete labours contains a physiological or material determination’.24 There is thus need to trace the social form of abstract labour back to its natural foundation – one that bears no social and historical specificity. Kicillof and Starosta maintain that the conception of abstract labour as substance of value ‘does not answer the question about the “specific social character of the labour which produces” commodities’. It merely tells us

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 124

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

125

about ‘the material determination . . . of that which is socially recognised in the form of value’. In short, ‘the analytical reduction of value to its substance’ reveals only the capitalist representation of abstract labour25 – it does not tell us anything about its ‘generic materiality’.26 In their view, Marx discovered this materiality in the opening pages of Capital, which, they say, tell us that ‘in any form of society human beings productively expend their corporeal powers’.27 At the start of Capital Marx is therefore not concerned, says Starosta, with the ‘common property in commodities’, nor with the specifically capitalist form of wealth. ‘Rather, he is searching for (i.e., not yet unfolding) the specific determination defining the potentiality of the commodity as a historical form of social wealth.’28 That is, rather than conceptualizing the capitalist social relations, Marx is said to establish the general, trans-historical properties of labour, and according to Starosta, he discovered them in abstract labour – the worker’s labour obeys the laws of nature, expenditure of labour is expenditure of human energy that is expended purposefully in exchange with nature. Starosta therefore argues that Marx ‘[discovered] abstract labour as the substance of labour in the first pages of Capital ’.29 This ‘analytical discovery of (congealed) abstract labour’, he argues, ‘revealed . . . the material determination of that which in capitalist society is socially represented in the form of value’. In other words, before developing the capitalist categories, Marx first sought to ‘discover’ their ontological foundation, which he is said to have found in the ‘general character’ of ‘productive labour’, that is, ‘abstract labour’.30 Marx is thus said to have discovered the source of capitalist wealth in something that is not specifically capitalist in character: the apparent trans-historical materiality of labour, its nature, its general existence as ‘homogeneous human labour, i.e., human labour expended without regard to the form of its expenditure’. Once Marx had established the trans-historical materiality of abstract labour, he was able to develop the commodity form as the capitalist ‘representation’ of the productive expenditure of human energy. For Kicillof and Starosta, the development of the commodity form entails the analysis of ‘the very social determination of the revolutionary action of the working class’ seemingly to achieve a socialist substantiation of the manner in which human energy is expended.31 In distinction, both de Angelis and Arthur argue that abstract labour is a specific social form of labour that has no trans-historical validity. Massimo de Angelis emphasizes abstract labour as a form of class struggle. Like Kicillof and Starosta, he disputes Rubin’s critical value theory, which argues that abstract labour is established through exchange. Instead, he holds that the abstract character of labour is ‘a direct consequence of the character of labour in capitalism’.32 Abstract labour is expended at the point of production, and is ‘imposed’ on workers.33 Class struggle over the imposition of abstract

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 125

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

126

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

labour has led towards an increasing homogeneity of concrete labouring, by means of deskilling and replacement of living labour by machinery. De Angelis thus conceives of abstract labour as homogenized expenditure of labour in production. He also conceives of it as an abstraction from the lived experience of workers in that it relates to subjective feelings such as boredom at work. De Angelis confuses a particular form of concrete labour with abstract labour. Chris Arthur argues similarly in his assessment of Braverman’s notion of abstract labour as monotonous, repetitive, homogenized labour. That is, boring assembly line work is boring concrete labour, not abstract labour.34 The labour that De Angelis discusses is general labour or labour sans phrase: this is a labour, which is ‘merely mechanical and thus indifferent whatever its specific form, merely formal activity’ that allows the individuals to move from this labour to that labour with ease.35 Nevertheless, and however indifferent to concrete purposes, this labour is a use-value producing labour.36 Kicillof and Starosta agree with de Angelis on the centrality of production, as opposed to exchange, and commend him for his critique of Rubin. They criticize him for failing to connect properly abstract labour to class struggle. Since de Angelis conceives of abstract labour as a result of class struggle, he is criticized for ontologizing class struggle.37 According to Kicillof and Starosta, class struggle rests on the fundamental contradiction between ‘transhistorical materiality and its substantiation in distinct social forms’. They thus argue that class struggle unfolds within the ‘contradictory unity between materiality and social form’.38 Class struggle is thus the movens of the contradictory relationship between the trans-historical forces of production and the historically specific social relations of production. Since this approach argues that the forces of production are not social-form determined but are, rather, the determinant of the relations of production, the class struggle does not bring about abstract labour, as de Angelis argues. Rather, the class struggle is about the capitalist modality of abstract labour and its further development towards socialism. Chris Arthur develops abstract labour in the context of debates on the ‘systematic’ dialectics. He holds that ‘there is not only a split between form and content, but the former becomes autonomous and the dialectical development of the structure is indeed form-determined’. He thus sees the value form as expressing the abstract essence of capitalism, that is, value. Value is essence and essence appears in the value form. He therefore argues that the ‘ontological foundation of the capitalist system’ is the material reality of abstraction in exchange (value). This process generates an ‘inverted reality’ in which commodities ‘simply instantiate their abstract essence as values’.39 Kicillof and Starosta dismiss Arthur’s account as pure formalism. It ‘overlooks the materiality of value-producing labour as a historical form of development

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 126

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

127

of human productive subjectivity’.40 In their view, Arthur’s stance is indifferent to material contents and disconnects abstract labour from the material world of production, class and struggle. For them, Arthur’s conception of abstract labour as a labour that manifests itself in exchange lacks materiality – Arthur, they suggest, deals with the ideal. Arthur’s ontological conception of value does not interest us here.41 His delivery of abstract labour as a specific social form reveals important insights. Especially his point ‘that capitalist production posits living labour processes as abstract activity, pure motion in time’ opens up a novel, temporally conceived conception of abstract labour that overcomes the – false – dichotomy between production and exchange.42 Arthur posits the materiality of abstract labour as a specifically capitalist materiality, a materiality of what Adorno called ‘socially necessary abstract labour time’.43 Marx developed the connection between abstract labour and motion in time in his Critique of 1859. Capital is not as explicit on this connection, but in my view presupposes it. He quotes from his Critique in Capital volume one: ‘As values, all commodities are only definite masses of congealed labour-time.’44 In his Critique he argues that ‘[o]n the one hand, commodities must enter the exchange process as objectified universal labour time, on the other hand, the labour time of individuals becomes objectified universal labour time only as a result of the exchange process’.45 ‘Time is money’, said Benjamin Franklin, and one might add that therefore money is time. If then, capitalism reduces everything to time, an abstract time, divisible into equal, homogeneous and constant units that move on from unit to unit, dissociated from concrete human circumstances and purposes, then, time really is everything. If ‘time is everything, [then] man is nothing; he is, at the most, time ’s carcase ’.46 Marx expresses the same idea in Capital, arguing that the worker is ‘nothing more than personified labour-time’.47 In short, Arthur’s argument points towards a temporal conception of abstract labour – a labour time made abstract and thus a time that manifests a ‘real abstraction’, one that holds sway in the conceptuality of value as the seemingly self-moving essence of social wealth.48 This time, as Debord put it, ‘has no reality apart from its exchangeability ’.49 Abstract labour is the substance of value not because it has a ‘particular useful content, but because it lasts for a definite length of time’.50 This is not the time of the concrete expenditure of muscles, brain and nerves. Rather, it is the time of socially necessary labour, which is a social abstraction. It is expenditure of muscle within socially necessary labour time and measured by socially necessary labour time.51 The next section argues that abstract labour is a temporal category of social labour. Only as socially necessary labour time does labour expended in production achieve value-validity in exchange. In

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 127

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

128

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

this sense, then, ‘capital posits labour time . . . as sole measure and source of wealth’.52

Value form and abstract labour About the double character of labour The distinction made by Kicillof and Starosta between generic materiality and social form is ordinarily discussed by the classical Marxist tradition in terms of a separation between first nature and second nature, that is, the historically specific relations of production and the trans-historical forces of production. This account presumes that the capitalist social forms can be traced back to some natural basis, which subsists through distinct modes of production as the historically overdetermined forms of natural necessity. In distinction, the critical theory tradition argues that the capitalist economic categories are socially constituted. They manifest the laws of necessity of the capitalistically constituted forms of social relations. What does this hold in relation to labour? In relation to use-value producing concrete labour, its social constitution is easily understood, despite the fact that use-values ‘constitute the material content of wealth, whatever its social form may be’. Use-values are the ‘basis of social progress’. The increase ‘in the quantity of use-values constitutes an increase of material wealth’.53 Furthermore, although ‘hunger is hunger . . . the hunger gratified by cooked meat eaten with a knife and a fork is a different hunger from that which bolts down raw meat with the aid of hand, nail and tooth.’54 For the capitalist to produce commodities, he has to produce use-values for others, ‘social usevalues’.55 That is, use-value is ‘historically-specific [in] character’.56 Use value in general cannot be produced, has no material existence and does not satisfy human needs. Man has needs only as concrete Man, and concrete Man is Man in her definite social relations. In the actual relations of capitalist life, concrete use-values are produced to facilitate the valorization of value, that is, the use-value producing labour creates material wealth that obtains as a mere depository of exchange value. Socially necessary labour time and the time it took to produce this or that commodity do not necessarily coincide. ‘Only socially necessary labour time counts towards the creation of value.’57 Socially necessary labour time thus determines whether the labour expended on the production of a particular use value is socially valid, and whether therefore the ‘social use-value’ represents value in exchange, and if it does not, it has no value, and what has no value

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 128

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

129

is discarded. The point of departure is therefore not individual production and associated notions of abstract labour as some substance that is ‘embodied’ in commodities. Value is a social category and the point of departure is thus ‘socially determined individual production’.58 Marx thus argues that since the producers do not come into social contact until they exchange the products of their labour, the specific social characteristics of their private labours appear only within this exchange. In other words, the labour of the individual manifests itself as an element of the total labour of society only through the relations which the act of exchange establishes between the products, and, through their mediation, between producers. To the producers, therefore, the social relations between their private labours appear as what they are, i.e. they do appear as direct social relations between persons in their work, but rather as material [dinglich] relations between persons and social relations between things. As use-values, commodities are combinations of ‘two elements, the material provided by nature and labour. If we subtract the total amount of useful labour of different kinds which contained in [them] . . . a material substratum is always left. This substratum is furnished by Nature without human intervention.’ In distinction, as exchange values commodities are the products of abstract labour, which is ‘purely social’. Indeed, if we abstract from the useful labour expended on a product, we do not discover the so-called generic materiality of abstract labour. What we find is matter, something for use, furnished by Nature. Labour therefore ‘is not the only source of material wealth’.59 Nature produces use-values, too. However, the labour that is decisive in the production of capitalist wealth, value, is abstract labour. It does not produce material wealth in the form of concrete things. It produces value as the socially constituted force of more value, measured by the rate of return. The concrete labour that produces social use-values is valid as value in exchange only as abstract labour, as socially necessary labour measured by time. Against Adam Smith, Marx emphasizes that this labour is an abstraction ‘forcibly brought about’ by exchange.60 What Marx means here by exchange is not ‘exchange with nature’ but the exchange of commodities in capitalist society.61 Abstract labour is the substance of value and this substance is unlike any other. Fundamentally, it is an invisible substance, one that exists as the ‘ghostlike objectivity of value’, in which ‘all sensuous aspects are eliminated’.62 Value, then, comprises the supersensible existence of the commodity. It cannot be the substance of a single commodity. Value expresses a social relationship between commodity and commodity and the labour that posits this relationship ‘is a specific social form of labour’.63 In distinction to

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 129

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

130

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

trans-historical, and in any case ontological definitions of the economic forces, Marx rejects the idea of production in general as a ‘mere spectre . . ., which is nothing but an abstraction and taken by itself cannot exist at all’.64 The notion that abstract labour, as the trans-historical materiality of all labour, assumes different social forms in distinct societies transposes ‘the truth of the law of appropriation of bourgoies society . . . to a time when this society did not yet exist ’.65 What therefore needs analysis is the specific social character of labour that manifests itself in the value form. Marx praises classical political economy for its analysis of value and the magnitude of value, and discovery of the hidden content of forms, ‘however incompletely’. Yet, he continues, ‘it never once asked the question why this content has assumed that particular form, that is to say, why labour is expressed in value, and why the measurement of labour by its duration is expressed in the magnitude of the value of the product’.66 That is to say, labour is the content of the capitalist social forms, and he thus asks why it assumes that form. This passage thus suggests that labour has to be analysed as the ‘content of that form’. Furthermore, he charges that political economy, especially Ricardo, nowhere distinguishes explicitly and with clear awareness between labour as it appears in the value of a product, and the same labour as it appears in product’s use-value. Of course, this distinction is made in practice, since labour is sometimes treated from its quantitative aspect, and at other times qualitatively. But it does not occur to the economists that a purely quantitative distinction between the kinds of labour presupposes their qualitative unity or equality, and therefore their reduction to abstract human labour.67 In distinction to the classical notion of an economic nature that expresses itself in overdetermined social forms, Marx does not differentiate between an abstract ‘labour that is represented by value’ and an abstract labour that is the ‘material content of social forms’.68 There is only one abstract labour, that is, the purely social labour of capitalist wealth. In comparison with Marx’s conception of abstract labour as a specifically capitalist form of labour, his physiological definition of abstract labour is entirely uncritical and traditional in its conception.

Concrete labour and abstract labour: On difference and equivalence There is only one social labour and this labour doubles into concrete labour and abstract labour. As use-values, products are the natural form of concrete

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 130

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

131

labour. As exchange values, commodities are the social form of abstract labour. Here ‘no trace is left behind’ that might distinguish one commodity from the other.69 One commodity is the same as any other. It is this ‘equivalence between different sorts of commodities which brings to view the specific character of value-creating labour’. Abstract labour comprises relations of equivalence. It is not some substance that hides in individual commodities. It comprises an ‘identical social substance’, which can be expressed only in the form of an exchange between one commodity and another. This exchange is ‘characterised precisely by its total abstraction from their use-values’. That is to say, ‘one sort of wares are as good as another, if the values be equal’. Exchange is a matter of equality in exchange, and equality expresses thus an equivalence that renders distinct commodities commensurable. Equality, too, becomes abstract in that it is indifferent to quality, distinction, specificity, purpose and indeed judgement and reason. ‘There is no difference or distinction in things of equal value. One hundred pounds worth of lead or iron, is of as great a value as one hundred pounds worth of silver or gold.’ This equality is the equality of labour in the abstract, of a labour that is the ‘same as any other’.70 Value equivalence is ‘purely social’ in character. It manifests nothing concrete. It ‘cannot be either a geometrical, physical, chemical or other natural property of commodities. Such properties come into considerations only to the extent that they make the commodities useful, i.e., turn them into usevalues.’ What the commodities have in common therefore is human labour in the abstract, and this labour comprises a purely social reality. So far no chemist has ever discovered exchange value either in a pearl or a diamond. The economists who have discovered this chemical element, and who lay claim to critical acumen, nevertheless find that the usevalue of material objects belongs to them independently of their material properties, while their value, on the other hand, forms a part of them as objects. What confirms them in this view is the peculiar circumstance that the use value of a thing is realised without exchange, i.e. in a direct relation between the thing and man, while, inversely, its value is realised only in exchange, i.e. in a social process.71 For example, Smith ‘mistakes the objective equalisation of unequal labours forcibly brought about by the social process for the subjective equality of the labours of individuals’.72 As values, commodities are all the same, manifestations of abstract labour. As ‘crystals of this social substance’ they are ‘merely congealed quantities of homogeneous human labour’. They comprise thus a ‘phantom-like objectivity’ in that the materiality of abstract labour is in fact invisible.73

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 131

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

132

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

The phantom-like objectivity of value has to do with the double character of labour. The real existence of labour is always concrete. That is, physiological expenditure of labour entails a specific productive application, and is thus concrete. Concrete labour is productive labour. ‘Variations of productivity have no impact whatever on the labour itself represented in the value. As productivity is an attribute of labour in its concrete useful form, it naturally ceases to have any bearing on that labour as soon as we abstract from its concrete useful form.’74 Muscles do not burn sugar in the abstract. Labour is always concrete labour. Labour cannot be performed in the abstract. What, then, is specific about capitalism is that concrete labour has to take the form of its opposite, undifferentiated and identical, phantom-like abstract labour, to count as socially necessary labour, thus achieving value-validity. Abstract labour is not a substance that one can touch, see, smell or eat. As exchange values, commodities do ‘not contain an atom of use value’.75 As use-values commodities do not contain exchange value. ‘As exchange values all commodities are merely definite quantities of congealed labour time ’ and the ‘labour which posits exchange value is a specific social form of labour’.76 Commodities exist in the form ‘of use-values or material goods . . . This is their plain, homely, natural form’. They are commodities only ‘in so far they possess a double form, i.e. natural form and value form’. Finally, ‘not an atom of matter enters the objectivity of commodities as values; in this it is the direct opposite of the coarsely sensuous objectivity of commodities as physical objects’. Commodities acquire a purely social reality insofar as they are expressions ‘of one identical social substance, human labour . . . it follows self-evidently that it can only appear in the social relation between commodity and commodity’.77 That is to say, no single commodity has ‘value-objectivity for itself, but each has it only in so far as it is a common objectivity. Outside their relation to each other – outside the relation, in which they count as equal – neither coat nor linen possess value-objectivity as congealed human labour as such.’78 Marx has great trouble in expressing value-objectivity.79 As a social thing it is a sensuous supersensible thing, a real abstraction. And he speaks not only of a ‘phantom-like objectivity’.80 He also says that value comprises a ‘purely fantastic objectivity’ and that it is ‘invisible’ in commodities.81 Or as Bellofiore put it, strictly speaking value ‘is a ghost ’.82 It is through money that ‘concrete labour becomes abstract labour’. The money form makes the ghost of value visible. 83 It manifests the ‘continually vanishing realisation of value’;84 once value is expressed in the form of money, it has to be posited again and again to maintain its occult quality to be unequal to itself, conquering the world of social wealth by extending its sway over the ‘exploited human material’ to the detriment of the two sources of social wealth, ‘the soil and the worker’.85

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 132

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

133

Ghost and vampire: On atoms of time What does it mean to say that value is invisible, like a ghost? What expenditure of labour are we dealing with? This section argues that abstract labour is a realtime abstraction. This time appears in abstract units that add to themselves, seemingly from time-immemorial to eternity. Time appears as a force of its own progress, moving forward relentlessly by adding units of time to itself, as if it were a force of nature that ticks and tocks dissociated from the time of actual events. This appearance is real. In capitalism, ‘time is ontologised’.86 This ontologized time is the time of value, and the time of value is the time of abstract labour. The holy trinity of abstract labour, time and value is invisible. Their objectivity is spectral. Nevertheless, the ‘ghost of value’ becomes visible in the money form; back in production the ghost turns into a vampire that feeds on living labour as a ‘time carcase’ of value. Actual labour is always labour in motion, that is, it ‘has in actual fact been expended’.87 ‘Just as motion is measured by time, so is labour by labour time . . . [it] is the living quantitative reality of labour.’88 This is the time of abstract, constant and equal time units, measured by clock time. ‘Direct labour time [is the] decisive factor of wealth.’89 Each commodity represents a specific quantity of ‘materialised universal labour-time’.90 Clock time is dissociated from the actual human affairs that it measures in homogenous, equal, divisible, constant, temporal units – how long did it take? Yet, however dissociated, it appears as the substance of the very same activity that it measures. Thus ‘time appears simultaneously as a measure of value and as its substance’.91 From the tick to the tock, clock time measures human activity regardless of specific contents. In clock time, the expenditure of labour does not occur in time. It occurs within time. Conventionally this notion of time is defined as linear time. Here time exists as an independent framework for motion, events and activities. As such a framework it is itself devoid of any specific content. Its content is merely formal in that it moves forward relentlessly ‘into time’.92 Time measures activities but is dissociated from them. ‘Homogeneous time is empty time’: it measures what it is not, it measures concrete expenditure whatever its content.93 It is also a reified time in that it appears timeless, without beginning or end, immanent to itself, purely abstract and irresistible. As a timeless time it is nothing – yet its passing ticks and tocks human labour, measuring its value. Labour time, which is always concrete as an activity in time, appears as its opposite – as an abstract time that is founded on itself and passes by itself.94 It is not the individuals who meet their needs in time. Rather time subsumes them, as if by fate or natural necessity, and organizes

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 133

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

134

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

her labour according to an economy of time that is homogenous as a time without quality, forever moving forward from time unit to time unit, restless, in constant motion, encompassing no playfulness and lacking in a federated present, from the tick to the tock it measures the productive expenditure of labour time in ‘hours’.95 What is not completed within the time of value has no exchange value. Regardless of the human needs that this or that usevalue might satisfy, things without exchange value have no value-validity. Valueless things are burned. The identification of use-values as depositories of objectified social labour time is an ‘abstraction that is made every day in the social process of production. The conversion of all commodities into labourtime is no greater an abstraction, but is no less real, than the resolution of all organic bodies into air.’96 This identification of use-values as depositories of valuable social labour time is real – on the pain of ruin, concrete labour really has to be completed within the time of ‘socially necessary abstract labour time’.97 Labour is the existing reality of labour time. That is, with reference to use-value, the labour contained in a commodity counts only qualitatively, with reference to value it counts only quantitatively, once it has been reduced to human labour pure and simple. In the former case, it was a matter of the ‘how’ and the ‘what’ of labour, in the latter of the ‘how much’, of the temporal duration of labour.98 How long, then, did it take? Concrete labour takes place in time, and has a concrete temporality. For this labour to count as socially necessary labour, it has to achieve value-validity in exchange. That is, its concrete labour-time has to occur within the time of a real abstraction. Concrete labour time is compelled to occur within the time of its abstract measure. There is no time to waste. Commodities have to be produced within the time of value, and the time of value is the time of socially necessary labour time. If the expenditure of labour does not occur within the time of value, it is valueless, with potentially ruinous consequences. In sum, expenditure of labour is expenditure of concrete labour. For it to count as a labour that produces social use-values, it has to occur within a socially determined time frame, which determines the exchange value of commodities. The validity of concrete labour manifests itself in its opposite as abstract labour. That is, it has to be objectified as abstract labour in exchange. Thus, the value of a commodity is ‘its social value; that is to say, its value is not measured by the labour-time that the article costs the producer in each individual case, but by the labour time socially required for its production’.99 Whether the expenditure of concrete labour-time has value-validity depends on whether it is a socially valid labour time and this labour time is distinct

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 134

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

135

form the individual production process, which it measures. Marx’s familiar definition of the measure of value – ‘socially necessary labour time is the labour-time required to produce any use-value under the conditions of production normal for a given society and with the average degree of skill and intensity of labour prevalent in that society’ – expresses the social character of the capitalist form of labour in the form of a universal commensurability of a time made abstract.100 ‘Only because the labour time of the spinner and the labour time of the weaver represent universal labour time and their products are thus universal equivalents, is the social aspect of the labour of the two individuals represented for each of them by the labour of the other.’ In this sense, the individual characteristics of the labourers are obliterated. As Marx put it in his Critique, ‘labour, which is thus measured by time, does not seem, indeed, to be the labour of different subjects, but on the contrary the different working individuals seem to be mere organs of this labour . . . [of] human labour in general.’ Different labours appear thus as different expenditures of the same social labour time. Objectified social labour is the objectified labour of a working individual that is ‘indistinguishable from all other individuals’.101 Labour time is objectified only once. It ‘is both the substance that turns them into exchange values and therefore into commodities, and the standard by which the precise magnitude of their value is measured.’102 The circuits M . . . C . . . M’ and M . . . P . . . M’ encompass this reality of labour time. Its elementary form, M . . . M’, encompasses it, too, as a mortgage on the future appropriation of surplus labour time or, I argue in Chapter 7, as presently fictitious wealth. Labour time as the measure of the magnitude of value is not fixed and given. The labour time that ‘was yesterday undoubtedly socially necessary for the production of a yard of linen, ceases to be so to-day’.103 Whether the concrete expenditure of time is valid as socially necessary labour time can only be established post-festum. The expenditure of concrete labour is thus done ‘in the hope, rather than the assurance, that [it] will turn out to be socially required’.104 Our capitalist, this personification of ‘value in process, money in process, and as such capital’, is thus spurred into action, frantically seeking to make the expenditure of concrete labour-time under his command count socially as expenditure of necessary social labour time. There he expropriates unpaid social labour time, here he seeks to make his fortune as seller of objectified social labour-time. Socially necessary labour time as the measure of wealth is also the substance of wealth. That is to say, time as a measure of its own substance ‘must itself be measured’, in the form of profit, the rate of return on expropriated unpaid labour-time.105 For the labourer, the consequences are formidable. Upon the sale of labour power, the labourer enters a race for time that expresses itself in the

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 135

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

136

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

demand for increased labour productivity. This is a race without winners. It is a race for economic progress to avoid economic ruin. That is, ‘labour time is the living state of existence of labour’.106 As the personification of labour time, she produces social wealth in the form of capital. Wealth manifests itself as time ‘command’. How much labour went in to it? How long did it take? Time is money. No time to waste, more time to catch. This, then, is the ‘nibbling and cribbling at meal times’ as ‘moments are the elements of profit’. Pace de Angelis, abstract labour is imposed: work has to be performed not in its own good time, but within the time of value-validity, a validity of socially necessary labour time. Work that is not completed within this time of value-validity is wasted, valueless, regardless of the labour time that went into it, the sweat and tears of its productive efforts, the usefulness of the material wealth that was created, and the needs that it could satisfy. From the appropriation of unpaid labour time to the endless struggle over the division between necessary labour time and surplus labour time, from the ‘imposition’ of labour-time by time-theft, this ‘petty pilferings of minutes’, ‘snatching a few minutes’, to the stealing from the worker of additional timeatoms of unpaid units of labour time by means of greater labour flexibility and ‘systematic robbery of what is necessary for the life’ of the worker, the life-time of the worker is reduced to the relentless tick and tock of the time of value. The worker then appears as ‘nothing more than personified labourtime’ – a time ’s carcase.107 That is to say, value-validity is the validity of a time of labour made abstract.

Conclusion Marx’s account on abstract labour is ambivalent. On the one hand he defines abstract labour in physiological terms, arguing that value is the crystallization and congealment of the expenditure of human muscles, etc. On the other he treats it as a specifically capitalist form of labour, arguing that commodities are such crystallizations only because they objectify socially necessary labour time. Classical Marxist theory develops the first aspect with great clarity and, against critical approaches that stress the veracity of the latter, purport this second aspect to be the capitalist objectification of the former. In this manner, it conceives of abstract labour as an ontological condition or general economic law, one that manifests ‘a purely material form, bearing no historical specificity’.108 Critically conceived abstract labour is a specific capitalist form of labour. Its materiality is a socially constituted real abstraction of socially necessary labour time. This time is the time of value. It achieves value validity

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 136

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

137

in the form of money, in which the materiality of labour becomes visible – as money that chases more money for the sake of maintaining its value-validity. By defining abstract labour as a trans-historical category, the classical Marxist tradition fetishizes it.109 The trans-historical treatment of abstract labour turns upside down the critical insight that the double character of labour is specific to capitalism. Trans-historically conceived, abstract labour becomes the foundation of all social life. In this round-about-way, concrete labour would figure as a specifically capitalist form of labour! Rejecting this absurd notion would mean that concrete labour, too, is treated as a condition independent of all forms of society. The double character of labour would thus cease to be capitalism’s determining characteristic, and akin to Ricardo’s undifferentiated category of labour, the differences in the modes of production would thus be reduced to distinctions in the social organization and technical division of labour, say, from the organization of labours’ corporeal power in the society of hunters and fishers via its capitalist organization to its socialist rationalization. Itoh expresses this view with great clarity: abstract labour ‘can be expended in various forms of useful labour according to the differing purposes aimed at, which can themselves be flexibly altered and widened in scope of coverage on the grounds of human intellectual ability’. This holds, he argues, ‘irrespective of whether . . . abstract and concrete labour are carried out consciously in socialist planning or unconsciously in a capitalist commodity economy’.110 Kicillof and Starosta’s trans-historical treatment of abstract labour leads to similar conclusions, that is, the ‘material specificity of [capitalism] . . . consists, precisely, in the development of the human productive capacity to organise social labour in a fully conscious fashion’.111 Rubin’s turn towards a critical theory of value argued against its transhistorical naturalization and in favour of its conceptualization as a specifically capitalist form of labour.112 Politically, this turn renounced the idea of socialism as a well-ordered republic of labour, which on closer inspection is in its entirety tied to capitalist realities, from the materiality of labour to the philosophy of progress.113 The time of abstract labour is the time of the ghostlike existence of social labour in the form of value, which, once made visible in the form of money, reveals its reason as the unreason of more money. Holloway’s point that the critique of abstract labour finds its positive resolution only in the abolition of abstract labour focuses the political implications of the critical theory of abstract labour with great clarity.114 The time of human emancipation is the time of human purposes. Freely disposable time is the very content of life. This time posits a form of human wealth that is entirely at odds with the idea that time is money.

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 137

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

138

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Notes 1 On this see, Michael Heinrich, ‘Reconstruction or Deconstruction?’ in ed. Riccardo Bellofiore and Roberto Fineschi, Re-reading Marx. New Perspectives after the Critical Edition (London 2009); Helmut Reichelt, Neue Marx-Lektüre. Zur Kritik sozialwisschenschaftlicher Logik (Hamburg 2008). The new reading recognizes the importance of Marx’s social form analysis of abstract labour and sought to reconcile it with his naturalistic definition, to the detriment of a critical conception. Postone recognized the central importance of abstract labour as a socially specific labour, and analysed it in systemic terms by inserting it into his theory of capitalism as a labour-mediated system of social reproduction. 2 Karl Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (London 1971), p. 36. 3 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 139. 4 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 134. 5 Makato Itoh, The Basic Theory of Capitalism. The Forms and Substance of the Capitalist Economy (London 1988), pp. 116, 114. 6 Massimo de Angelis, ‘Beyond the Technological and the Social Paradigms: A Political Reading of Abstract Labour as the Substance of Value’, Capital & Class, vol. 19, no. 3 (1995), pp. 107–34. Massimo de Angelis, ‘Social Relations, Commodity-Fetishism and Marx’s Critique of Political Economy’, Review of Radical Political Economics, vol. 28, no. 4 (1996), pp. 1–29. 7 De Angelis apart, see also Harry Braverman, Labour and Monopoly Capital (New York 1974). Jean-Marie Vincent, Abstract Labour: A Critique (London 1991). In their ‘Elements of anti-Semitism’, Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment (London 1979), p. 207, conceive of abstract labour in similar terms, describing it as ‘the universal reduction of all specific energy to the one, some abstract form of labour, from the battlefield to the studio’. 8 Isaak Rubin, Essays on Marx ’s Theory of Value (Detroit 1972), p. 135. 9 Michael Eldred and Marnie Hanlon, ‘Reconstructing Value-Form Analysis’, Capital & Class, vol. 5, no. 1 (1981), p. 40. 10 Michel de Vroey, ‘On the Obsolescence of the Marxian Theory of Value’, Capital & Class, vol. 6, no. 2 (1982), p. 44. 11 On this, in the context of Marxian economics, see Maurice Dobb, Political Economy and Capitalism (London 1940), and Ernest Mandel, The Formation of the Economic Thought of Karl Marx (New York 1971). For critique, see Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory (Cambridge 1996), pp. 43–58. 12 Marx, Capital, vol. III (London 1966), p. 815. Translation altered. 13 On this see, especially, Reichelt, ‘Social Reality as Appearance: Some Notes on Marx’s Concept of Reality’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 138

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

139

Capitalism (Aldershot 2005); Michael Heinrich, An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital (New York 2012). 14 Karl Marx, ‘Letter to Engels’, 8.1.1868, MEW 32 (Berlin 1963), p. 11. 15 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 165. 16 Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory, see, for example, pp. 58ff. 17 Marx, ‘Letter to Engels’, 24.8.1867, p. 407. 18 For a recent debate about these contrasting accounts, see Werner Bonefeld, ‘Debating Abstract Labour’, Capital & Class, vol. 35, no. 2 (2011), pp. 475–79, Guglielmo Carchedi, ‘A Comment on Bonefeld’s “Abstract Labour”’, Capital & Class, vol. 35, no. 2 (2010), pp. 307–9, and Axel Kicillof and Guido Starosta, ‘On Value and Abstract Labour’, Capital & Class, vol. 35, no. 2 (2010), pp. 295–305. The origin of this chapter goes back to Werner Bonefeld, ‘Abstract Labour: Against its Nature and on its Time’, Capital & Class, vol. 34, no. 2 (2010), pp. 257–76. 19 Axel Kicillof and Guido Starosta, ‘On Materiality and Social Form’, Historical Materialism, vol. 15, no. 3 (2007), pp. 23, 24, 34–5. 20 Guido Starosta, ‘The Commodity-form and the Dialectical Method’, Science and Society, vol. 72, no. 3 (2008), p. 31. 21 Itoh, Basic Theory, p. 114. 22 Itoh, Basic Theory, p. 121. 23 Wolfgang Fritz Haug, Vorlesungen zur Einführung ins ‘Kapital’ (Hamburg 2005), p. 108. Haug’s biological definition of abstract labour as sugarburning is apt, to the point and simple in its nature. See also Guglielmo Carchedi, ‘The Fallacies of “New Dialectics” and Value-Form Theory’, Historical Materialism, vol. 17, no. 1 (2009), pp. 145–69, whose robust assertion of the physiological definition of abstract labour leads him to argue that the determination of value by abstract labour has to do with the consumption of calories during the production process, as measured against labour time – how many calories per hour of labour is embodied in the commodity? The biological fact that muscles burn sugar does not explain any form of society whatsoever. 24 Axel Kicillof and Guido Starosta, ‘On Materiality and Social Form’, pp. 34–5, 22. 25 Kicillof and Starosta, ‘On Materiality and Social Form’, p. 22. 26 Kicillof and Starosta, ‘Value Form and Class Struggle’, Capital & Class, vol. 31, no. 2 (2007), p. 16. 27 Starosta, ‘The Commodity-form and the Dialectical Method’, p. 31. This is a trivial discovery, by any standards. Against the abstract materialism of the general historical laws of nature, the categories of political economy need to be developed from within the actual relations of life. Historical materialism is not a metaphysics of society as the being and becoming of some abstract economic nature. 28 Starosta, ‘The Commodity-form and the Dialectical Method’, p. 25.

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 139

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

140

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

29 Starosta, ‘The Commodity-form and the Dialectical Method’, p. 21. Fred Schrader, Restauration und Revolution (Hildesheim 1980) argues that Marx developed the category in his critique of Benjamin Franklin. Unlike the category of labour sans phrase in the Grundrisse, the later category of abstract labour would thus refer to the equalization of qualitatively distinct concrete labours in terms of value. This is what Franklin was after, and following Schrader, it was in this context that Marx left aside his earlier conception of general labour, or labour sans phrase, and instead developed the category of abstract labour as a purely social form. See also Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 142, fn. 18. I owe this reference to Reichelt, ‘Social Reality’. In this same context, Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory, p. 56, makes clear that in distinction to Marxian economics, and in any case ontological conception of economic nature, the first pages of Capital establish the distinctive character of Marx’s critical theory of capitalism. 30 Starosta, ‘The Commodity-form and the Dialectical Method’, pp. 16, 28. 31 Axel Kicillof and Guido Starosta, ‘On Materiality and Social Form’, Historical Materialism, vol. 15, no. 3 (2007b), p. 41. 32 de Angelis, ‘Social Relations, Commodity-Fetishism and Marx’s Critique of Political Economy’, Review of Radical Political Economics, vol. 28, no. 4 (1996), pp. 18–19. 33 de Angelis, ‘Beyond the Technological and the Social Paradigms: A Political Reading of Abstract Labour as the Substance of Value’, Capital & Class, vol. 19, no. 3 (1995), p. 111. 34 Chris Arthur, ‘Value, Labour, and Negativity’, Capital & Class, vol. 25, no. 1 (2001), pp. 15–39. Braverman, Labour and Monopoly. See Geoff Kay and James Mott, ‘Concept and Method in Postone’s Time Labour and Social Domination ’, Historical Materialism, vol. 12, no. 3 (2004), pp. 169–87 for a neat account of the circumstance that abstract labour has no concrete – labouring – existence. 35 Karl Marx, Ökonomische Manuskripte 1857/58 , MEGA II.1.1 (Berlin 1976), p. 217. 36 See Helmut Reichelt, ‘Die Marxsche Kritik ökonomischer Kategorien. Überlegungen zum Problem der Geltung in der dialektischen Darstellungsmethode im Kapital ’, in ed. Iring Fetscher and Alfred Schmidt, Emanzipation und Versöhnung. Zu Adornos Kritik der ‘Warentausch’Gesellschaft und Perpektiven der Transformation (Frankfurt 2002), p. 173. In contrast, Backhaus confuses abstract labour with general labour. He conceives of it as ‘the’ labour, which is neither that labour nor this labour, and yet, both at the same time. Abstract labour, he suggests, comprises the general character of all specific forms of labour. Hans-Georg Backhaus, ‘Der widersprüchliche und monströse Kern der nationalökonomischen Begriffsbilding’, in ed. Iring Fetscher and Alfred Schmidt, Emanzipation und Versöhnung. Zu Adornos Kritik der ‘Warentausch ’-Gesellschaft und Perpektiven der Transformation (Frankfurt 2002), pp. 130–1. See also Chapter 4, fn. 56. 37 Kicillof and Startosta, ‘Value Form and Class Struggle’, p. 22.

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 140

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

TIME IS MONEY

141

38 Kicillof and Startosta, ‘On Materiality’, p. 34. 39 Chris Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital (Leiden 2004a), pp. 81, 80. 40 Kicillof and Startosta, ‘Value Form and Class Struggle’, p. 17. 41 There is only one reality, not two, and content is the content of forms, however split reality might seem. There is no two-world distinction between the sensuous world of contents and the super-sensible world of value-things. Rather, the sensuous world subsists through the super-sensible world and belongs to it. Arthur’s ontological conception of value develops aspects of Adorno’s negative ontology, that is, the self-moving essence of value is the social necessity of a negative world. Its necessity appears like a force of nature. Yet, it is a solely social necessity. 42 Arthur, ‘Value, Labour, and Negativity’, p. 23. Arthur’s ‘process of abstract activity’ does not connect with de Angelis’s reading of abstract labour. The former conceptualizes the movement of the world behind the backs of its producers, the latter describes a specific concrete labour. See also his ‘The Practical Truth of Abstract Labour’, in ed. Ricardo Bellofiore, Guido Starosta and Peter Thomas, In Marx ’s Laboratory (Leiden 2013). 43 Theodor Adorno, ‘Seminar Mitschrift of 1962’, in Appendix to Hans-Georg Backhaus, Dialektik der Wertform (Freiburg 1997b), p. 507. 44 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 130. 45 Marx, A Contribution, p. 45. 46 Karl Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy, Collected Works, vol. 6 (London 1975), p. 127. 47 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 352–3. 48 I owe the reference to time as a real abstraction to Reichelt, Zur logischen Struktur des Kapitalbegriffs bei Marx (Freiburg 2001), p. 169. 49 Guy Debord, Society of the Spectacle (New York 1994), p. 87. 50 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 308. 51 Daniel Bensaid, Marx for our Time (London 2002) conceives of time as capitalist matter. See also Eric Alliez, Capital Times (London 1996). 52 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 706. 53 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 126, 293, 136. 54 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 92. 55 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 131. 56 Marx, ‘Randglossen’, p. 370. 57 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 296. 58 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 83. 59 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 165–6, 133, 139, 134. 60 Marx, A Contribution, p. 59. 61 Karl Marx, Ergänzungen und Veränderungen, MEGA, II.6 (Berlin 1987), p. 41, states clearly that ‘[t]he reduction of different concrete private

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 141

2/19/2014 3:44:08 PM

142

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

labours to this same abstract labour manifests itself only in exchange, which renders equivalent distinct products of labour’. 62 Marx, Ergänzungen und Veränderungen, p. 283. 63 Marx, A Contribution, p. 36. 64 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 954. 65 Marx, From the Preparatory Materials, in Marx Engels Collected Works, vol. 29 (London 1987), p. 463. Translation altered. 66 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 173–4. 67 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 173, fn. 33. 68 This part draws on Reichelt, Neue Marx-Lektüre, pp. 97–8. On the face of it, the argument seems to clash with Murray’s observation that Marx operates with different concepts of abstract labour. Murray distinguishes between (1) ahistorical labour akin to conceptions of labour as general exchange with nature, (2) homogenized general labour, that is, abstractified concrete labour of the sort discussed by de Angelis and (3) ‘practically abstract labour’. The last one is equivalent to value-producing labour, and is what Rubin calls ‘abstract labour’. For Murray ‘practically abstract labour’ is ‘truly social’. Patrick Murray, ‘Marx’s “Truly Social” Labour Theory of Value’, Historical Materialism, vol. 6 (Summer 2000), pp. 27–65. 69 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 187. 70 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 142, 138, 127, 127–8, 129. 71 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 139, 127, 177. 72 Marx, A Contribution, p. 59, translation amended. 73 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 128. 74 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 137. 75 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 128. 76 Marx, A Contribution, pp. 30, 36. 77 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 138, 138–9. 78 Marx, Ergänzungen, p. 30. 79 For an account see Michael Heinrich ‘Reconstruction or Deconstruction’ and ‘Enstehungs- und Auflösungsgeschichte des Marxschen “Kapital”’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Michael Heinrich, Kapital & Kritik (Hamburg 2011). 80 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 128. 81 Marx, Ergänzungen, pp. 32, 820. 82 Ricardo Bellofiore, ‘A Ghost Turning into a Vampire’, in ed. Riccardo Bellofiore and Roberty Fineschi, Re-reading Marx. New Perspectives after the Critical Edition (London 2009), p. 185. On the invisibility of value, see also De Vroey, ‘On the Obsolescence of the Marxian Theory of Value’, p. 41. 83 Geoffrey Kay, ‘Why Labour is the Starting Point of Capital ’, in ed. Diane Elson, Value. The Representation of Labour in Capitalism (London 1979), p. 58. See also Bellofiore, ‘A Ghost Turning into a Vampire’; Reichelt, ‘Zur

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 142

2/19/2014 3:44:09 PM

143

TIME IS MONEY

Konstitution ökonomischer Gesellschaftlichkeit’; Geoff Kay, ‘Abstract Labour and Capital’, Historical Materialism, vol. 5, no. 1 (1999), 255–80. 84 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 209. 85 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 740, 638. 86 Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London 1990), p. 331. 87 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 143. 88 Marx, A Contribution, p. 30, translation amended. 89 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 704. 90 Marx, A Contribution, p. 46. 91 Bensaid, Marx for our Time, p. 80. 92 Including the time of history, conceived of as the force of its own being and becoming. On this, see Chapter 10. 93 Bensaid, Marx for our Time, p. 82. 94 On this see, Hans-Jürgen Krahl, Vom Ende der abstrakten Arbeit (Frankfurt 1984), p. 29. 95 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 129. 96 Marx, A Contribution, p. 30. 97 Adorno, ‘Seminar Mitschrift’, p. 507. 98 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 136. 99 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 434. 100 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 129. 101 Marx, A Contribution, pp. 33, 30–1, 32; translation amended. 102 Marx, A Contribution, p. 30. 103 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 202. 104 Tony Smith, The Logic of Marx ’s Capital (Albany 1990), p. 69. 105 Bensaid, Marx for our Time, p. 75. 106 Marx, A Contribution, p. 30. 107 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 352, 553, 352–3. 108 Kicillof and Startosta, ‘On Materiality’, pp. 34–5. See also Itoh, Basic Theory, pp. 113–21, 363. 109 This formulation draws on Chris Arthur, ‘Arbeit, Zeit und Negativität’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Michael Heinrich, Kapital & Kritik (Hamburg 2011). 110 Itoh, Basic Theory, pp. 363, 121. 111 Kicillof and Startosta, ‘On Materiality’, p. 36. 112 Rubin’s Essays on Marx ’s Theory of Value, first appeared in 1924. During the course of the Great Purge he was executed in 1937. 113 Karl Marx, ‘Critique of the Gotha Programme’, in Marx Engels Selected Works, vol. 3 (Moscow 1970); Walter Benjamin, ‘Theses on the Philosophy of History’, in Illuminations (London 1999). 114 John Holloway, Crack Capitalism (London 2010), p. 143.

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 143

2/19/2014 3:44:09 PM

9781441161390_Ch06_Final_txt_print.indd 144

2/19/2014 3:44:09 PM

7 State, world market and society Introduction The world market is the categorical imperative of capitalist wealth. Valuevalidity entails the world market validity of value. The abstract labour of value production comprises thus the homogenization of time as a world-market reality of socially necessary abstract time. The law of value annihilates space by time. The critical insight that in capitalism the social individuals are controlled by the products of their own hand asserts itself in the form of the world market as an ‘objective coercive force’ – Sachzwang Weltmarkt.1 Even Chinese walls crumble in the face of the heavy artillery of the world market price.2 In contemporary political economy, the world market has since the early 1990s been discussed under the heading ‘globalization’. In this discussion, the world market was viewed as a recent development of capitalism. Until the late 1980s, the global economy was seen as an interstate system comprising inter-national trade relations and an inter-national system of the division of labour, which was organized and held together by the forces of US imperialist power that organized the international system of the West in its own image. As a consequence of the ostensibly nationally based neoliberal strategies associated with Thatcherism and Reaganism, the post-war political economy underwent an ‘epochal shift’3 towards a seemingly new capitalist formation that replaced the old state-centric system by the ‘creation of the world market’ as an independent force over and above the inter-national state system.4 In this new formation, says Stephen Gill, the ‘power of capital attains hegemonic status’.5 In this account of political economy, discussion of the conceptuality and dynamic of the capitalist social relations, the specific capitalist form of wealth and its production, circulation and reproduction, is set aside for an argument about the relationship between two seemingly distinct structures of social organization, that is, state and economy. The perennial question of

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 147

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

148

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

analysis is thus whether the state has relative autonomy over the economy, forcing back the power of capital, or whether the economy has power over the state, establishing the hegemony of capital. State and economy are seen as independent structural domains that achieve concrete materiality as a consequence of the shifts and changes in the balance of the social forces. Within this analytical frame, ‘the power of the state is the power of the forces acting in and through the state’.6 In the meantime, the crisis of 2008 is said to have let to the resurgence of the national state in its relationship vis-à-vis the economy.7 However, this resurgence is seen to manifest the continued hegemony of the neo-liberal forces as the financial losses are nationalized and the costs of the rescue socialized by means of a politics of austerity.8 The chapter argues that Marx’s work entails a critique of the world market as the categorical imperative of the capitalist form of wealth, and its production. Robert Cox’s characterization of the global economy as a nebuleuse serves as its starting point.9 Cox argued that the competitive logic of capital on a world scale entails the subordination of domestic economies to the perceived exigencies of a global economy. States willy nilly become more effectively accountable to a nebuleuse personified as the global economy; and they were constrained to mystify this external accountability in the eyes and ears of their own publics through the new vocabulary of globalisation, interdependence, and competitiveness.10 Cox perceives the global relations of trade, production and finance as constituting a global economy, which he characterizes as something invisible – a nebuleuse – to which, he says, national states are accountable. The chapter explores Cox’s intriguing notion of the global economy as a nebuleuse in three sections. The first introduces Marx’s account of the world market and the second explores the critique of commodity fetishism as a critique of the worldmarket society of capital. The third section examines the relationship between the world market and crises. The conclusion argues that the world market is not something extra-national and that the national state subsists through the world market. The chapter contends that capitalist society is fundamentally a worldmarket society and the national state is the political form of this society.

World market and society Marx never wrote his planned books on the state and the world market. Nevertheless, a cursory reading of his writings and a brief look at various

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 148

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

STATE, WORLD MARKET AND SOCIETY

149

outlines of his work reveal that both the state and the world market are always present. In his outline of 1857, the world market is posed as the final and concluding part of his investigation, coming after the international relation of production and ‘the concentration of bourgeois society in the form of the state’.11 Furthermore, the anticipated examination of ‘crises’ is associated with the projected study of the world market. The theme, then, is ‘the world market and crises’. Moreover, according to his outline, the world market is distinct from the inter-national relations of production. His outline suggests that capitalist crises can be conceptualized adequately only in a world-market dimension. The capital relations do therefore not equate with the inter-national relations between states. Instead, the outline suggests that the world market is the condition of the inter-national state system. The inter-national relations subsist in and through the world market. The world market condenses the distinctive social histories into the one single world-market history. The history of capitalist society is a world-market history. The world market forms not only the ‘basis for this mode of production’.12 It is also ‘directly given in the concept of capital itself’.13 The conception of the world market as the ‘basis’ of the capitalist social relations entails its distinction from the ‘inter-national relations’ of economic interdependency. Capitalist production is unthinkable without foreign trade.14 This seems to suggest that the ‘world market’ is coterminous with the international state system. However, the ‘relations of industry and trade within every nation are dominated by their intercourse with other nations, and are conditioned by relations with the world market’.15 The world market is therefore not coterminus with the sum of the many national economies.16 Rather it comprises the relations of capitalist social reproduction within, between and beyond national borders. Trade and industry within and between national borders amount, therefore, to trade and industry at a world-market level. The productivity, then, of ‘domestic’ labour acquires its livelihood in and through the world-market relations of value in process, money in process and as such capital. Locality is a world-market locality. It is through the world market that the ‘domestic’ valorization of social labour is confirmed and contradicted, that is, it is in and through the world market that expended labour acquires valuevalidity as an expenditure of socially necessary labour time. Therefore, ‘the entanglement of all peoples in the net of the world market, and, with this, the international character of the capitalist regime’ entails that whoever wants to speak about the division of labour has to speak about the world market.17 The domestic division of labour entails the world-market division of labour; the former cannot be conceived of without the latter. Marx’s account of the global division of labour does not develop Ricardo’s idea of ‘comparative advantages’.18 Ricardo seeks to supply an argument that

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 149

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

150

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

renders the ‘complexity’ of the inter-national relations of production coherent and capable of rational organization. Marx does not focus on inter-national comparative advantages as the basis of a system of mutually beneficial trade relations. Rather, he expounds the conceptuality of value. Value-validity is the validity of more value, measured by the rate of return in the form of profit. The rate of profit obtains as the world market rate of profit. Similarly, the productivity of labour is a world-market productivity of labour, which appears in the form of world-market price movements. This then entails the unleashing of the ‘heavy artillery’ of cheaper prices upon national states should the valorization of value, that is, the extraction of surplus value within their jurisdiction, fall below the average world-market rate of profit, which asserts the need for greater labour productivity to withstand competitive pressures.19 This heavy artillery that demands the surrender of additional atoms of surplus labour time makes itself felt through pressures on the exchange rate, the accumulation of balance of payments deficits and drains on national reserves. It is through the movement of money as capital that the global conditions of accumulation impinge on ‘national economies’, asserting pressure to ‘force down wages and transform the forces of production in order to survive’. 20 World money is not just a means of exchange or a means of payment; it obtains, fundamentally, as the world-market form of value. That is to say, for world money to assert itself as capital, it has to possess the ‘occult quality to add value to itself’. It must lay ‘golden eggs’ and it does so by diminishing the necessary labour time of the worker as the condition of increasing the surplus labour time for the production of surplus value. 21 That is, the ‘everyday struggle over the production and appropriation of surplus value in every individual workplace’ manifests itself in the world-market form as price competitiveness, (dis)investment and (un)employment. 22 The circumstance that the equalization of the rate of profit obtains as a world-market equalization transforms the apparently local conditions into world-market conditions. The validity of the ‘national industry’, ‘national employment’ and ‘national wealth’ belongs to the world market. Whatever its specific concrete character and wherever it occurred, social labour is productive of capitalist wealth only on the conditions that it produces not only value but, fundamentally, surplus value in the form of profit at a global scale.23 Within this context, ‘world trade’ is exclusively driven by the satisfaction of ‘needs’, that is, the need of the ‘seemingly transcendental power of money’ to add value to itself.24 Bourgeois society is governed by the law of the constant expansion of abstract wealth, of money chasing more money. For money to assert itself as capital, it has to beget more money, and it begets more money by valorizing the life-time of the worker as a human resource of essentially surplus labour time. Money is the ‘universal form of labour’.25 It transcends

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 150

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

STATE, WORLD MARKET AND SOCIETY

151

national boundaries and asserts itself upon territorialized labour relations as the force of abstract wealth, requiring greater labour productivity as a means of preventing competitive erosion. The ‘cheapness of provision’ is a necessity of global wealth.26 In and for itself, the commodity therefore exists beyond every religious, political, national and linguistic barrier. It speaks the language of ‘profit’, and its community is the community of abstract wealth, and its common good comprises the progressive accumulation of capital for its own sake. Thus, capital, whether in the form of commodity capital, money capital or productive capital, has neither a national character nor a patriotic affiliation. Its patriotism is money, that is, ‘the private interest within each nation divides itself into as many nations as it has “fully grown individuals”’.27 Therefore, the term ‘bourgeois society’ does not stand, and has never stood, for a ‘national’ society. The attribute ‘national’ indicates some sort of homogeneity of interest and shared values, which is neatly summoned by the metaphor of the ‘one national boat’ that Robert Reich refers to in his attempt at defining the cohesion and equality of the national societies before the onset of globalization. In this view, globalization forced the ‘one-national boat’ apart, leading, as Joachim Hirsch argued, to a society ‘increasingly fractured on socio-economic lines’.28 On the contrary, the term ‘bourgeois society’ stands, from its inception, not only for a class-divided society, it stands also for the global freemasonry of capital. Just as money, general exchange, subsists as world money, as global exchange, so the owner of commodities, the bourgeois, is a cosmopolitan.29 In the Communist Manifesto, the life of the bourgeoisie is portrayed in terms of the global existence of capital: old industries are destroyed and replaced by new industries whose introduction is a question of survival within the global system of production and division of labour, ‘giving a cosmopolitan character to production and consumption in every country’.30 The notion, then, of a ‘national economy’ makes little sense; it is a regressive concept that lends itself, at best, to ideas of national developmental methods associated with the theory and practice of economic nationalism31 or, at worst, and as Chapter 9 sets out, to the reactionary ideas and practices of nationalism that in reaction to world-market disturbances assert the regressive equality of the imagined national community as the rallying cry against the external enemy within. Of course, protectionism remains a very powerful device to protect a ‘national economy’. However, the national economy is neither independent from the world market nor does it merely exist in relation to the world market. Rather, the national economy subsists in and through the world market. Protectionism, then, amounts to a ‘measure of defence within free trade’.32 In distinction to the debate on globalization, capital is not some domestic economic force that responded to national constraints by ‘globalizing’ itself.

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 151

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

152

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Rather, ‘the world market, international capitalism, the global system of social relations that has grown up for the first time in history’ emerged at the same time as the national state.33 In this way, then, ‘the question of the national integration of the state could not be divorced from that of the integration of the international state system’.34 This ‘system’ of inter-state relations is founded on ‘the international relations of production. International division of labour. International exchange and import. Rate of exchange.’35 Furthermore, from its inception this inter-state system has been embedded within the ‘global context of production and exchange in which capital is in the process of constituting itself as historical real world capital’. In other words, the ‘world market is integrated into the national economy’.36 The world market, then, is not the sum of distinct national economies or national capitalisms. Rather, the world market is the premise and condition of the capitalist form of wealth, and its production. Its conceptuality holds sway in and through the national states that form the inter-national state system, which comprises the relations of political competition and mutual dependency, rivalry and dependency, national assertion and imperial power, war and trade. The notion of the national state entails the inter-national relations, and these inter-national relations are founded on the world-market relations of price and profit. That is to say, the global flow of capital prevails over, and also in and through, the national state and the inter-national state systems, and conversely, the national state and the inter-national state systems manifest the nodal point of the global flow of capital.37

World market and fetishism I have argued that social labour manifests itself in exchange as abstract labour in the form of money. Human cooperation subsists in the form of a monetary relationship that establishes and disrupts the interconnection between ‘the individual with all’ other individuals on the basis of a constant effort at achieving greater social wealth in the form of value.38 The world market is the most developed form of this abstract interconnectedness. It does therefore not only include ‘the activity of each individual’ it is, also, ‘independent of this connection from the individual ’. The concept of capital entails, therefore, not only the complete independence of the individuals from one another but also their complete dependence on the seemingly impersonal relations of the world market. Thus, the independence of the individual is an ‘illusion, and so more accurately called indifference’. Their independence is that of atomized market agents who are ‘free to collide with one another and to engage in

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 152

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

STATE, WORLD MARKET AND SOCIETY

153

exchange within this freedom’; and their indifference to each other is one of human factors of production inasmuch as their continuous ability to sell their labour power for a wage depends on the profitable realization of their surplus labour-time in the form of profit on the markets of the world.39 The worker’s dependency on continuous employment, which is the condition of her sustained access to the means of subsistence, is a matter of the profitable expenditure of her labour in competition with her fellow producers of surplus value on a global scale. This, then, is the invisible thread by which the social individual is entangled in the world market, this real abstraction of capitalist society that asserts itself behind the backs of those same social individuals who produce and sustain it with their own hands. The impersonal relations of world-market dependency appear as a ‘spontaneous interconnection, a material and mental metabolism which is independent of the knowing and willing of individuals, and which presupposes their reciprocal independence and indifference’.40 The validation of value in the form of money acquires a livelihood in the apparent ‘autonomisation of the world market’ as the ‘objective coercive force’ of the capitalist social relations. The ‘individuals are now ruled by abstractions ’ and these abstractions subsist in the form of world-market conditions that ‘are independent of the individual and, although created by society, appear as if they were natural conditions, not controllable by individuals’. There is thus a constant pressure to secure the value-validity of committed labour, and yet this pressure is ‘brought out of him by his labour’. It is therefore ‘an insipid notion to conceive of this merely objective bond as a spontaneous, natural attribute inherent in individuals and inseparable from their nature . . . This bond is their product. It is a historic product.’41 Thus, to conceive of the world market as an objective force that compels the individuals to adjust to its movement is both perceptive of the existing conditions and misleading. The constituted world is indeed hostile to the individuals. However, to conceive the world market as an ‘objective coercive force’ alone, as a Sachzwang, is to derive human social practice from hypothesized social structures whose social constitution remains a mystery – a nébuleuse. That is, the world of invisible principles gives back to Man what Man has put into them.42 Taken by itself, the understanding of world market as an objective coercive force obscures rather than reveals its social constitution. It does not include ‘human natural force’.43 This force is the productive power of labour. ‘Labour is value creating’44 and ‘the specific social character of . . . labour [appears] only within . . . exchange.’45 Capital, as Marx insists, ‘only appears afterwards, after already having been presupposed as capital – a vicious circle – as command over alien labour ’.46 Capital appears only afterwards because it is through exchange that concrete labour is validated; it achieves value-

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 153

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

154

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

validity as the abstract labour of socially necessary labour time. Capital is neither an economic thing, nor can it be identified with individual companies that represent this fraction or that fraction of capital, nor does it result from the wishes of capitalists, however multinational or powerful they might be. Capital is ‘a definite social production relation’. Its concept contains its presupposition in social labour as the disappeared premise of its constituted economic identity. Every capital is therefore the capital, and the capital is a ‘perennial pumping-machine of surplus labour’.47 Value is a product of living labour and living labour vanishes in the form of the ‘money-subject’. This subject pulls the ‘national ground from the foundation of every industry’ and transfers the ‘conditions of production outside itself, into a general context’ of exchange. That is, the ‘general foundation of all industry comes to be general exchange itself, the world market, and hence the totality of all activities . . . of which it is made up’. The value-validity of expended labour is a worldmarket validity. That is, the devaluation, liquidation or realization of value is a world-market reality. This, then, establishes a ‘vicious circle’ of ‘command ’ over living labour, which is founded on the practical understanding that the extraction of additional atoms of surplus labour-time is not only the basis of ‘the elements of profit’ but also the difference between value devaluation and value realization, bankruptcy and economic success, redundant labour and employment of labour.48 For the sake of achieving value-validity, labour has to appear in the form of value. Value becomes visible in the form of money and in this appearance the value creating labour ‘disappears’.49 Exploitation is not visible in the form of an equivalence exchange. Exchange takes the form of a relationship between coins, in which the manner of its coinage disappears, by which, say, the circumstance that ‘a great deal of capital, which appears today in the United States without birth-certificate, was yesterday, in England, the capitalist blood of children’ appears therefore as more money, more commerce, greater national wealth, more civilization, etc. It appears, in short, as economic growth.50 The disappearance of labour and the appearance of money as a selfexpanding value (M . . . M’) are two sides of the same process that validates social labour by converting it ‘into a social hieroglyphic’. This conversion is a world-market conversion. ‘It is in the markets of the world that money first functions to its full extent as . . . the directly social form of realization of human labour in the abstract.’51 Value is a social relationship between people appearing in the form of things. As such a thing, its movement manifests itself as an ‘automatic’ subject that acts ‘with the force of an elemental natural process’.52 Its world-market movement is adequate to its concept – it identifies space as a category of the time of value, and it thus asserts itself essentially as a coercive force of ‘unpaid labour’ time.53

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 154

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

STATE, WORLD MARKET AND SOCIETY

155

In conclusion, the world market is not just the most spacious expansion of capitalist society but, also and importantly so, the categorical imperative of capitalist wealth. It comprises the ‘totality of the activities, intercourse, needs, etc., of which it is made up’.54 The category of the world market is, thus, not a category among others. It is ‘at once the pre-condition and the result of capitalist production’.55 It is thus the conclusion ‘in which production is posited as a totality together with all its moments, but within which, at the same time, all contradictions come into play. The world market, then, forms the presupposition of the whole as well as its substratum.’56 It manifests the substratum of a topsy-turvy world in which Monsieur le Capital and Madame la Terre do their ghostwalking for the sake not just of profit but, fundamentally, for more profit, restlessly accumulating the extracted surplus value for the sake of progressive accumulation. The risk is bankruptcy and bloodshed.

World market and crises Every individual capitalist ‘always has the world-market before him, compares, and must constantly compare, his own cost-prices with the market-prices at home, and throughout the world’.57 This constant comparing and continual search for ‘cheaper’, more effective means of valorizing value is inherently crisis-ridden. Capitalist crisis is not some extraordinary thing, however painful its consequences for the sellers of labour power. Crisis is a necessary form of capitalist social reproduction. It belongs to its conceptuality and holds sway in its reality. On the pain of ruin, each individual capitalist has constantly to expand ‘his capital, so as to preserve it, but he can only extend by means of progressive accumulation’.58 Thus each individual capitalist is spurred into action to maintain his connection to abstract wealth by means of greater surplus-value extraction, on the pain of avoiding the competitive erosion and liquidation of existing values. Each individual capitalist is therefore compelled to compress necessary labour so as to increase the surplus labour time of surplus value production by means of multiplying the productive power of labour. The cheapening of the products of labour thus goes hand in hand with the progressive accumulation of capital. A crisis of capitalist reproduction is not simply a crisis of overproduction or underconsumption. Fundamentally, it expresses an over-accumulation of abstract wealth that fails to retain the value validity of money as more money, depressing the rate of accumulation, or in the parlance of economic theory, the rate of economic growth. The incessant effort of increasing the productivity of labour leads to a relative decline of living labour in relation to the means of production, which

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 155

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

156

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

concentrates a growing outlay of capital. Less living labour thus produces a greater amount of material wealth in the form of use-values within a given time. At the same time as the accumulation of capital expands progressively, the value of a commodity declines as the socially necessary labour time for its production falls.59 Crisis, then, expresses the ‘contradiction between the capitalist tendency to develop the forces of production without limits, and the need to confine accumulation within the limits of the social relations of production’.60 There is thus an increase in material wealth in the form of usevalues, each of which represents a diminishing depository of value in exchange. That is, too much ‘capital’ has been accumulated as each capitalist tries to preserve capital personified by forcing the producers of surplus value towards greater productive effort, converting realized profits back into production to extract surplus value on an expanding scale in an effort at withstanding competitive pressures. Each individual capitalist seeks to prevent devaluation by extracting more surplus value, each trying to realize the products of labour as a value-valid expenditure of social labour, and attempts to do so in the face of diminishing rates of profitability as the extraction of surplus value becomes more costly with the increase in labour productivity.61 The importance of the fall in the rate of profit is that it decreases the rate of accumulation. That is, less surplus value is realized in exchange relative to the reproductive requirements of progressive accumulation, and capital has to accumulate in order to preserve existing values from competitive erosion. Capitalist society is a ‘living contradiction’.62 Although living labour disappears in the form of money as more money (M . . . M’), it ‘remains the presupposition’ of the whole system of capitalist wealth. In other words, the validity of capitalist wealth expresses itself in the form of money, and money is capital only as the manifestation of coined unpaid labour in the form of profit. Personified capital thus forces the workers beyond necessary labour to surplus labour. Only in this way does it realise itself, and create surplus value. But on the other, it posits necessary labour only to the extent and in so far as it is surplus labour and the latter realizable as surplus labour. It posits surplus labour, then, as the condition of the necessary, and surplus value as the limit of objectified labour, of value as such. As soon as it cannot posit value, it does not posit necessary labour; and, given its foundation, it cannot be otherwise. The attempt to ward off the threat of bankruptcy compels the capitalist, this personified existence of capital, ‘to make human labour (relatively) superfluous, so as to drive it, as human labour, towards infinity’.63 Capital, then, exists in

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 156

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

STATE, WORLD MARKET AND SOCIETY

157

antithesis to necessary labour and at the same time only in and through the imposition of necessary labour, which it has to posit for the sake of surplus labour. On the pain of ruin, it has to extract surplus value by diminishing the necessary labour of social reproduction, and yet it cannot accumulate surplus value without positing necessary labour. Capitalist reproduction entails crisis not just in the form of capital devaluation and liquidation of existing values, bankruptcy and liquidation. Most importantly, it manifests itself as a crisis of social reproduction, in which it appears as if the producers of surplus value are suddenly cut off from the means of subsistence. The rate of employment is regulated by the rate of capitalist accumulation, and its decline entails downward pressure on the general movement of wages and the intensification of labour for those in work, and enforced ‘idleness’ and collapse of wage income for others. Capitalism’s ‘development of human productive forces, i.e. of wealth . . . proceeds in a contradictory way’.64 It revolutionizes the forces of production in a crisis-ridden manner throwing workers out of work and depressing their access to the means of subsistence as money defaults and companies go bust. That is, it ‘restricts labour and the creation of value . . . and it does so on the same grounds as and to the same extent that it posits surplus labour and surplus value. By its nature, therefore, it posits a barrier to labour and valuecreation, in contradistinction to its tendency to expand them boundlessly.’65 The real barrier, then, to capital is capital itself: by forcing ‘the workers beyond necessary labour to surplus labour’ it tends to produce much more material wealth than can be realized with rates of profit adequate to the further valorization of value by means of progressive accumulation.66 Money has to beget more money to preserve the relations of abstract wealth, and crisis manifests the difficulty of bringing this about. There is then a crisis of the ‘valorisation of value’, as rates of accumulation dip, and rates of bankruptcy and unemployment increase, competition intensifies and the effort at increasing labour productivity strengthens – how quickly can things be done at less cost?67 Capitalist crises assert themselves in the form of unemployed workers and in the form of unemployed capital. Unemployed capital is one that has become divorced from direct productive engagement, and that has therefore spilled over into speculative channels seeking profitable returns by making money out of money, literally hedging its bets on how things might unfold, then and now.68 The so-called plethora of capital always applies essentially to a plethora of the capital for which the fall in the rate of profit is not compensated through the mass of profit – this is always true of newly developing fresh

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 157

2/19/2014 3:43:34 PM

158

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

offshoots of capital – or to a plethora which places capitals incapable of action on their own at the disposal of the managers of large enterprises in the form of credit.69 It is this plethora of capital that asserts itself in the form of financial capital, which for Susan Strange and others established the new capitalism of globalization.70 Financial capital is one that searches for near-instantaneous self-expansion, placing bets on a dazzling future that seems as certain as the promises of a Ponzi scheme. In the form of finance, money appears as the ‘mystification of capital in its most flagrant form’ in that it seems to posit an increase in wealth by investing into itself, eliminating the relation to labour.71 However, the so-called predominance of finance capital represents an accumulation of capital that could not be converted directly into direct productive activity. Hence ‘unemployed capital at one pole and unemployed workers at the other’ – essentially redundant human material.72 The sustaining of over-accumulation through credit-expansion and an accumulation of debt entails a potentially disastrous speculative deferral of economic crisis. This is because money capital accumulates in the form of a potentially worthless claim on future surplus value. The solidity and very existence of money capital is endangered insofar as capital, in its elementary form of money, becomes potentially ‘meaningless’ inasmuch as it appears as an irredeemable accumulation of claims on the future extraction of surplus value.73 That is, the divorce of monetary accumulation from productive accumulation entails a mortgage, and thus a gamble, on the future exploitation of labour. It indicates that the strength of the tie between capital and labour is loosening: the less credit-expansion is supported by the generation of surplus value in the present, the more the ‘superstructure of credit’ is at risk of losing its grip on the very source upon which its promise of wealth depends.74 There is, then, no doubt that capital can divorce itself from labour, positing itself as ‘a saleable thing for profit’.75 In the form of financial capital, wealth appears in the form M . . . M’ – ‘the meaningless form of capital, the perversion and objectification of production relations in their highest degree, the interest-bearing form, the simple form of capital, in which it antecedes its own process of reproduction.’ It appears, then, as if the ‘social relation is consummated in the relation of a thing, of money, to itself’. Although we see, in interest-bearing capital, ‘only form without content’, it is ‘only a portion of the profit, i.e. of the surplus-value, which the functioning capitalist squeezes out of the labourer’. Therefore, in finance capital, the relationship of capital to labour is only seemingly eliminated inasmuch as the expansion of monetary accumulation asserts itself as a ‘claim of ownership upon labour’, that is, as a claim on a portion of future surplus value. What Susan Strange dupped

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 158

2/19/2014 3:43:35 PM

STATE, WORLD MARKET AND SOCIETY

159

‘casino capitalism amounts therefore to a capitalism that accumulates wealth by mortgaging the future extraction of surplus value.76 Without the valorizing of living labour, the accumulation of money amounts to an accumulation of fictitious wealth. Financial panic and economic recession are two sides of the same coin of the crisis of valorizing living labour, which is the premise of money as more money.

Conclusion The ‘national’ and the ‘global’ are not externally related things. Of course, the national and the global are not identical but neither are they related to each other as merely external entities that happen to collide with one another from time to time. The global and the national are different-in-unity: they are moments of the social relations of production, which constitute their distinct forms of existence, suffuse their interrelation and contradict their differentiation. The global dimension of the capital relation, its aspatial character, is thus not without ‘space’. The aspatial exists contradictorily through nationally divided spaces of political sovereignty.77 The relation of the national state to the world market of capitalist society appears as a relation of a nationally fixed state to a globally mobile capital. However, and as Clarke puts it, ‘although the state is constituted politically on a national basis, its class character is not defined in national terms, the capitalist law of property and contract transcending national legal systems, and world money transcending national currencies’. Nation states are not only in competition with each other, as each tries to divert the flow of capital into its particular territory, they exist also as particular nodes within the global flow of capital. The nation state exists through the world-market society of capital and is confined ‘within limits imposed by the contradictory form of the accumulation of capital on a world scale’.78 In this context, the notion of the national economy is misleading. First, it is premised on the idea that capitalist utility of labour within a nationally defined space is, as implied by the use of the metaphor of the one national boat, based on some sort of ‘national harmony’ of interest: the ‘national interest’. Second, it is premised on the idea that the ‘limits’ to ‘national harmony’, to ‘national wealth’, do not hold sway in the conceptuality of capitalist wealth. Rather, ‘national wealth’ is seen constrained by external forces, which are said to disrupt the integrity of ‘national economies’ and ‘national’ labour markets. Thus, ‘disharmony’ seems to be ‘imported’ from the outside, as if it derived from some intangible world-market forces, from the sudden collapse of world market prices to global recession and crisis. In his critique of Carey’s

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 159

2/19/2014 3:43:35 PM

160

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

economic nationalist ideas, Marx argues forcefully that ‘these world-market disharmonies are merely the ultimate adequate expressions of the disharmonies which have become fixed as abstract relations within the economic categories, or which have a local existence on the smallest scale’.79 In other words, global ‘disharmony’ exists in and through the ‘domestic relations’ and vice versa. In this context, Marx argued that the state is the ‘harmonies’ last refuge’ – the harmonies of the law of value posit the state as political force of value.80 As the following chapter argues, it concentrates the political force of bourgeois society and establishes a law-governed social order to secure the fundamental sociability of the unsocial interests of competitive society, and to keep the social antagonism in check on the basis of the rule of law and by means of the force of law-making violence. The economy of free labour entails the state as the political form of that freedom.81 In conclusion, the capitalist social relations do not exist in terms of two sets of relations, that is, as relations of national harmony and, distinct from these, as relations of world-market disharmony. The ‘national’ relations subsist through the world-market society of capital, and the world market is the condition of capitalist wealth. Cox’s view that the state is ‘accountable to a nebuleuse personified as the global economy’ needs to be demystified.82 The view that capital is an intangible global ‘thing’ and that the state is accountable to this ‘thing’ is uncritical. The state is not accountable to capital. It is the political form of the capitalist social relations. Cox’s notion, then, of the global economy as an abstract intangible force, a nebuleuse, reinforces the fetishism of capital. Yet, it goes a long way towards what this chapter has argued.

Notes 1 This term is Elmar Altvater’s, Sachzwang Weltmarkt (Hamburg 1987). 2 See Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto (London 1997), p. 17. 3 William I. Robinson, A Theory of Global Capitalism: Production, Class and State in a Transnational World (Baltimore, MD 2004), p. 2. Leo Panitch and Sam Gindin, The Making of Global Capitalism (London 2012), argue that globalization is an outcome of US imperialism. 4 Stephen Gill, Power and Resistance in the New World Order (London 2003), p. xii. 5 Gill, Power and Resistance, p. 105. 6 Bob Jessop, State Power: A Strategic-Relational Approach (Cambridge 2008), p. 270. See Chapter II for a critique of the theoretical premises of this point of view.

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 160

2/19/2014 3:43:35 PM

161

STATE, WORLD MARKET AND SOCIETY

7 See, for example, Elmar Altvater, Die Rückkehr des Staates? Nach der Finanzkrise (Hamburg 2010). Bob Jessop, ‘The Return of the National State in the Current Crisis of the World Market’, Capital & Class, vol. 34, no. 1 (2010), pp. 38–43. 8 Alex Callinicos, ‘Contradictions of Austerity’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, vol. 36, no. 1 (2012), pp. 65–77. 9 Cox’s work has been pivotal for the development of critical International Political Economy (IPE). His ‘Global Perestroika’, The Social Register 1992 (London 1992), offers a succinct analytical statement of his approach, and that of critical IPE in general. On Cox’s work, see Adrian Budd, Class, States and International Relations (London 2013). Peter Burnham, ‘Open Marxism and Vulgar International Political Economy’, Review of International Political Economy, vol. 1, no. 2 (1994), pp. 121–32, offered an early, incisive critique. 10 Cox, ‘Global Perestroika’, p. 27. 11 Karl Marx, Grundrisse (London 1973), p. 108. 12 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. III (London 1966), p. 333, also p. 110. 13 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 163. 14 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. II (London 1978), p. 456. 15 Karl Marx, ‘Die revolutionäre Bewegung’, MEW 6 (Berlin 1968), p. 149. 16 Claudia von Braunmühl, ‘On the Analysis of the Bourgeois Nation State within the World Market Context’, in ed. John Holloway and Sol Picciotto, State and Capital (London 1978), made this insightful point in the context of the German state derivation debate. On this debate see Chapter 8, Introduction. 17 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 929. See also Karl Marx, ‘Brief an P. W. Annenkow vom 28.12.1846’, MEW 4 (Berlin 1977), p. 550. 18 David Ricardo, Principles of the Political Economy of Taxation (Cambridge 1995). 19 On the state as the concentrated force of competitive adjustment to worldmarket conditions, see Chapter 8. 20 Simon Clarke, ‘Class Struggle and the Gobal Overaccumulation of Capital’, in ed. Robert Albritton, Makato Itoh, Richard Westra and Alan Zeuge, Phases of Capitalist Development. Booms, Crisis and Globalizations (London 2001), p. 90. 21 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 255. 22 Clarke, ‘Class Struggle’, pp. 90–1. See also John Holloway, ‘Zapata in Wall Street’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, The Politics of Change (London 2000). 23 See Karl Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (London 1971), pp. 152–3. 24 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 146. 25 Marx, A Contribution, p. 98.

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 161

2/19/2014 3:43:35 PM

162

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

26 Adam Smith, Lectures on Jurisprudence (Oxford 1978), p. 6. For Smith, the cheapness of provision entails the state as the political force of wealth; see Chapter 8. 27 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 159. 28 Robert Reich, The Work of Nations (New York 1991). Joachim Hirsch, ‘Globalisation of Capital, Nation-States and Democracy’, Studies in Political Economy, 54 (1997), p. 46. 29 See Marx, A Contribution, p. 152. Marx’s point is succinct in its summary of Smith’s remark that ‘the proprietor of stock is properly a citizen of the world’. Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Indianapolis 1981), p. 848. 30 Marx and Engels, The Communist Manifesto, p. 16. 31 See, for example, Friedrich List, The National System of Political Economy (New York 1904). 32 Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London 1976), p. 73. 33 Colin Barker, ‘A Note on the Theory of the Capitalist State’, in ed. Simon Clarke, The State Debate (London 1991), p. 205. 34 Clarke, The State Debate, p. 179. 35 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 108. 36 Claudia von Braunmühl, ‘On the Analysis’, pp. 163, 168. 37 On this, see Clarke, ‘Class Struggle’; John Holloway, ‘Global Capital and the National State’ and Peter Burnham, ‘Capital, Crisis and the International State System’ both in ed. Werner Bonefeld and John Holloway, Global Capital, National Sate and the Politics of Money (London 1995). 38 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 161. 39 Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 160, 161, 162, 163–4. 40 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 161. 41 Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 164, 541, 162. 42 Man is not abstract Man. Man is the social individual in her social relations. 43 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 330. 44 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 823. 45 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 165. 46 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 330. 47 Marx, Capital, vol. III, pp. 814, 822. 48 Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 144, 528, 330, and Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 352. 49 Marx, From the Preparatory Materials, in Marx Engels Collected Works, vol. 29 (London 1987), p. 497. 50 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 920. Or as Jeremy Bentham, the father of utilitarianism, put it when recommending that children be put to work at four rather than 14 years of age: ‘ten precious years in which nothing is

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 162

2/19/2014 3:43:35 PM

STATE, WORLD MARKET AND SOCIETY

163

done! Nothing for industry! Nothing for improvement, moral or intellectual!’ Bentham, quoted in Michael Perelman, The Invention of Capitalism (Durham, NC 2000), p. 22. Ten lost years for progress, for civilization, for profit! 51 Marx, Capital, vol. I, pp. 167, 240–1. 52 Marx, Capital, vol. II, p. 185. 53 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 672. 54 Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 227–8. 55 Marx, Theories, p. 253. 56 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 426. 57 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 336. 58 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 739. 59 For Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination. A Reinterpretation of Marx ’s Critical Theory (Cambridge 1996) this contradiction between greater material wealth and a diminishing, socially necessary labour time per unit of use-value is the fundamental condition of capitalist crisis. 60 Simon Clarke, ‘M. Itoh’s “Basic Understanding of Capitalism”’, Capital & Class, vol. 13, no. 1 (1989), p. 142. 61 On this, see Simon Clarke, Marx ’s Theory of Crisis (London 1994). 62 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 421. 63 Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 399, 421. 64 Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 540, 541. 65 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 421. 66 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 421. 67 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 739. 68 See Paul Mattick Jr., Business as Usual (London 2011) and Sergio Bologna, ‘Money and Crisis’, Common Sense, no. 14 (1993), pp. 63–89, also available at: http://commonsensejournal.org.uk/issue-14/ 69 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 251. 70 Strange provided the paradigmatic term for the analysis of financial globalization, ‘casino capitalism’. Susanne Strange, Casino Capitalism (Manchester 1997). See also John Bellamy Foster and Robert W. McChesney, The Endless Crisis (New York 2012). 71 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 392. 72 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 251. 73 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 393. In the German original, Marx uses the term begriffslose form. In the English edition begriffslos is translated as ‘meaningless’. This translation is misleading. I use the term in the sense of ‘losing its grip’ on labour – a loss that renders money as a form of value fictitious. On this see Werner Bonefeld, ‘Money, Equality and Exploitation: An Interpretation of Marx’s Treatment of Money’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and John Holloway, Global Capital, National State and the Politics of Money (London 1995).

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 163

2/19/2014 3:43:35 PM

164

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

74 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 439. 75 Marx, Capital, vol. III, p. 393. 76 Marx, Capital, vol. III, pp. 393, 476. 77 For a critical theory of space as a social form, see Greig Charnock, ‘Challenging New State Spatialities: The Open Marxism of Henri Lefebvre’, Antipode, vol. 42, no. 5 (2010), pp. 1279–303, and ‘Lost in Space? Lefebvre, Harvey and the Spatiality of Negation’, forthcoming in South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 113, no. 2. 78 Simon Clarke, ‘The Global Accumulation of Capital and the Periodisation of the Capitalist State’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. I (London 1992), p. 136. Holloway, ‘Global Capital and the National State’. 79 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 887. 80 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 886. 81 On the meaning of ‘economy of free labour’, see Chapter 4. 82 Cox, ‘Global Perestroika’, p. 27.

9781441161390_Ch07_Final_txt_print.indd 164

2/19/2014 3:43:35 PM

8 On the state of political economy: Political form and the force of law Introduction Within traditional Marxist scholarship the state is usually seen as either an economically determined entity or a power that governs in the interests of the dominant social forces that assert themselves through the state as the public authority of their interests. In the latter perspective, the state appears as a strategic arena for the advancement of hegemonic projects.1 In the former, the state appears as an economically determined superstructure.2 Neither develops the state as the political form of bourgeois society. Following Braunstein, Adorno’s critical theory contains few if any argument about the conceptuality of the state.3 The new reading of Marx overlapped with the so-called German state derivation debate of the 1970s but Reichelt apart, the one discussed the conceptuality of value, the other sought to derive the role and function of the state from the movement of the capitalist economic categories.4 The term ‘derivation’ summarizes the dominant account of this debate succinctly. Instead of establishing the conceptuality of the state as the political form of society, it derived the state as the political complement of the capitalist accumulation process.5 None of these accounts develops the state from the actual, given relations of life, and none therefore offers a critique of the state as the apotheosized form of definite social relations.6 Marx’s critique of state, which exists only in fragments, suggests that apart from his argument about economic base and political superstructure he also conceives of the state as the political form of the capitalist social relations. Indeed, and as I argue below, the notion that the state is a political superstructure that arises from the economic base of society derives from

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 165

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

166

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

classical political economy.7 In the context of his critique of political economy, this is a paradoxical idea. His work is intended as a critique of the relations of economic objectivity, which, if taken seriously, cuts down on the very economic base from which the state is said to arise. There is only one social reality and this is the reality of the capitalistically organized social relations of production. ‘There is no other world than the one in which we live.’8 Instead, then, of deriving the state as an extra-economic force from some presupposed socio-economic categories, be it from a plurality of competing hegemonic strategies, an irresistible economic logic or as a functional requirement of the capitalist processes of accumulation, this chapter argues that the state is best conceptualized as the political form of capitalist society. The approach that this chapter takes represents a gear change. Rather than working through the fragments of Marx’s own writing about the state and the established elements of a critique of the state in the Marxist literature, it develops its argument by exploring Hegel’s political philosophy, Smith’s political economy and finally the neoliberal theory of the state, particularly of German neoliberal thought, which establishes a coherent account of capitalist economy as a practice of government. The final section discusses neoliberalism as the political theology of the state, which provides for a theoretical exposition of modern Bonapartism.9 I reckon that this change in approach establishes the contention of this chapter in a straightforward manner, that is, the political world is the social world in political form. I return to Marx’s account in the conclusion to demonstrate the critical force of his conception of the state as ‘the concentration of bourgeois society in the form of the state’.10 In this view, society doubles itself up into society and state, that is, the state is the political form of society ‘viewed in relation to itself’.11 I therefore hold that the institutional separation of state and society does not confer on the state an independent political logic of constitution and development. Rather, the political state is the premise of the non-coerced, depoliticized exchange relations between the buyers of labour power and the producer of surplus value who in spite of their manifest inequality pursue their interests in liberty as equal legal subjects, based on the rule of law. This pursuit expresses a history of class struggle. The chapter thus argues that the state is not some extra-economic force. Rather it is the ‘concentrated and organized force of society’.12

On the political form of society Hegel conceived of bourgeois society as antagonistic in character.13 It was because of its antagonistic character that it required a political form. He

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 166

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

167

develops the necessity of the state from the innate character of bourgeois society. In his Philosophy of Right, he first introduces the notion of general dependency: the particular person is essentially related to other particular persons, each finds satisfaction by means of the others, and their reciprocal relationship means that the satisfaction of needs comprises a universal system of mutual dependency. There is thus a division of labour and satisfaction of needs by means of exchange. Concerning the state, its purpose here is the ‘protection of property through the administration of justice ’. However, and importantly, ‘the infinitely complex, criss-cross, movement of reciprocal production and exchange, and the equally infinite multiplicity of means therein employed’ goes beyond the division of society into individualized individuals, or in today’s language, the so-called market individuals. He then argues that the division of labour crystallizes ‘into systems, to one or another of which individuals are assigned – in other words, into class divisions’. These divisions are antagonistic in character as the development of bourgeois society leads to its polarization into antagonistic class relations. According to Hegel, the polarization of society into two opposing classes is an innate necessity of bourgeois society. It belongs to its constituted dynamic. As he sees it, bourgeois society ‘results in the dependence and distress of the class tied to [work]’. Dependence and distress are also entailed in the ‘inability to feel and enjoy the broader freedoms and especially the intellectual benefits of civil society’.14 Moreover, the expanded reproduction of bourgeois society results ‘in the creation of a rabble of paupers’ and the ‘concentration of disproportionate wealth in a few hands’. What to do ‘when the masses begin to decline into poverty’ and start to rebel? He rejects redistribution of wealth as this ‘would violate the principle of civil society’. He also rejects what today is called a policy of full-employment as contrary to its logic. Rather than solving the problem, it would intensify it. Thus, ‘despite an excess in wealth, civil society is not rich enough, i.e. its own resources are insufficient to check excessive poverty and the creation of a penurious rabble’. There is no economic answer to the polarization of society. Economy does not provide order, nor does it curb the ‘rabble’. In fact, ‘the inner dialectic of civil society . . . drives it . . . to push beyond its own limits’. How to keep the class antagonism within the limits of its bourgeois form? For Hegel, there is only a political answer. He saw the state as the political force of bourgeois society and charged it with containing the class antagonism.15 Hegel conceives of bourgeois society as entirely uncivilized in its social nature. He portrays it as selfish, competitive and antagonistic in character. It allows for the accumulation of great wealth by the few at the expense of

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 167

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

168

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

the many, condemning the masses to poverty. Hegel describes bourgeois society in the following way: [the individual] is subject to the complete confusion and hazard of the whole. A mass of the population is condemned to the stupefying, unhealthy, and insecure labour of factories, manufactures, mines, and so on. Whole branches of industry, which support a large bulk of the population, suddenly fold up because the mode changes or because the values of their products fall on account of new inventions in other countries, or for other reasons. Whole masses are thus abandoned to helpless poverty. The conflict between vast wealth and vast poverty steps forth, a poverty unable to improve its conditions. Wealth . . . becomes a predominant power [, fostering resentment and hatred].16 He thus characterizes bourgeois society as a ‘moving life of the dead. This system moves hither and yon in a blind and elementary way, and like a wild animal calls for strong permanent control and curbing’.17 It requires, in short, the authority of the state to render its conduct ‘civil’ by containing the class tied to work within the boundaries of bourgeois society. Indeed, maintaining the cohesion of society might well be advanced by ‘successful wars’ that ‘have checked domestic unrest and consolidated the power of the state at home’.18 Without the political state, bourgeois society will implode under its own weight. The security of its existence, its social order and civil conduct, is a matter of state.

The state of political economy: On police, justice and moral sentiments Marx introduces his base/superstructure metaphor arguing that his investigation led him to the conclusion that the relations of production ‘constitutes the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness.’19 Leaving aside Marx’s own understanding of his work as a critique of economic categories, and therewith of the very economic objectivity from which the superstructure is supposed to arise, his metaphor says that the political form of bourgeois society, the state, belongs to the society from which it springs.20 Crudely put, the purpose of capital is to accumulate extracted surplus value, and the state is the political form of that purpose. The origin of the base/superstructure metaphor lies in classical

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 168

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

169

political economy. William Robertson summarized the classical position well: ‘in every inquiry concerning the operation of men when united together in society, the first object of attention should be their mode of subsistence. Accordingly as that varies their laws and policy must be different.’21 Adam Smith provided the classical exposition. His theory of history is remarkable for the emphasis it gives to economic forces that work their way through history towards ‘commercial society’. He argues that in each historical stage, the political form of society, be it conceived in terms of authority or jurisdiction, necessarily flows from the forms of property. For Smith, private property is the consequence of the development in the division of labour, which, he argues, ‘is not the effect of human wisdom but the slow and gradual consequence of the propensity to truck and barter’.22 By force of its innate dynamic, the propensity to exchange leads to an ever greater division of labour, the extension of which increases the social surplus and gives rise to the growing social differentiation of society into distinct social classes, leading to the establishment of private property and the separation of society into civil society and political state in commercial society. For Adam Smith political economy is not an economic science. Rather, it is ‘a branch of the science of the statesman or legislator’. 23 He, too, conceived of what he called ‘commercial society’ as class ridden, and held the state indispensable for maintaining the system of perfect liberty. It maintains this system by means not only of law but also by ‘ordering’ the conduct of society, restraining the passions of competition within the framework of the moral sentiments and law, and containing the class antagonism. The invisible hand is incapable of integrating and maintaining society. It does not remove the social impediments to its operation, nor does it create the moral sentiments upon which the conduct between the private interests depends, and nor does it resolve the clashes of interest between the classes. That is, the invisible hand has no independent reality. Fundamentally, it is a practice of government. Economy is political economy. According to Smith, production and distribution are regulated through competitive exchanges, mediated by money. This regulation is achieved where there is ‘perfect liberty’. The price mechanism that allows prices to rise and fall above and below the ‘natural prices’ is governed by the invisible hand, which informs individuals where to invest and what to sell. The invisible hand is a depoliticized devise of economic adjustment. Individuals follow price signals in a manner of their own choosing and in pursuit of their own interests. Government or persons do not tell anybody what to do, when and where. Nevertheless, its magic requires government. Impediments to its operation have to be removed by means of state, and economic freedom requires the order of freedom to sustain its sociability, preventing disorder.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 169

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

170

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

The Smithean state is therefore not a weak state. It is a strong state. It does not yield to the social interests. It governs over them, and as I argue below, also through them to secure the perfect liberty of the system as a whole. That is, for Smith the state does not compete with the invisible hand as if it were some alternative source of economic regulation. Rather, it is to facilitate its unimpeded operation, and it therefore governs for the sake of the system of perfect liberty. Its purpose is to protect, maintain and facilitate the law of private property to secure the further development of commercial society. Smith specifies a number of indispensable state functions. Apart from defending the country against external threats, it has to provide for an exact administration of justice in order to resolve clashes of interest between property owners. The state is indispensable also for the provision of public goods that are essential for the operation of the market, but which cannot be provided for by the market itself for lack of profitability.24 This responsibility for commercial society also entails that the state make efforts to help achieve the ‘cheapness of provision’, facilitating the progressive development of the wealth of nations on the basis of increased labour productivity.25 The state, then, is responsible for facilitating the law of private property, or as Marx called it, the law of value, by removing various institutional and legal impediments, and by confronting those private interests that impede the perfect liberty of the market by advancing their egoistic interests or indeed class interests. For Smith, ‘justice . . . is the main pillar that holds up the whole edifice’ of commercial society.26 Justice is a matter not only of law and the rule of law, which is the regulative force of the freedom of contract between ostensibly equal exchange subjects,27 fundamentally, justice is a matter of the wellordered ‘common wealth’. Order is the precondition of law. The rule of law does not apply to social ‘disorder and bloodshed’, and law does not enforce order. Police is responsible for the establishment of order and police is therefore the premise of the rule of law. Police enforces order and in this manner renders the rule of law effective. Further, the system of justice is dependent upon a moral code that commits individuals to the rules of justice, and therewith to the laws of private property. The removal of impediments to market freedom thus also entails the provision of morally committed participants in market freedom. That is, the system of perfect liberty amounts to a constant effort of restraining the passions of competition and profit-making by the rules of justice. It amounts also to a constant effort of facilitating ‘the will’ for competition and enterprise on the part of the class divided social individuals. There is thus need to facilitate the moral sentiments of the system of perfect liberty in ‘the will’ of the individuals, contain the passions of ‘self-love’, curb the rebellious character of the poor and facilitate the further improvements in the productive power of labour to sustain the progress of the common wealth.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 170

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

171

According to Smith, the moral sentiments of commercial society are based on the sense of the ‘propriety’ of the beauty of a well-ordered whole. This whole gives purpose and benefit to the private individuals who are both interested only in themselves and obliged to each other. The moral sentiments therefore express a moral sociability, which for Smith is based on ‘sympathy’. Sympathy is the ability of individuals to adopt the position of the ‘impartial and well-informed spectator’. However, sympathy is not a sufficient condition for containing the fundamental character of commercial society, that is, ‘self-love’. A society based on the pursuit of self-interest requires a moral foundation, a moral social fabric and an ethical framework, to sustain it. On the part of the self-interested individuals, the moral sentiments express, first, the charitable side of commercial society, or as Marx put it in the Holy Family, its sentimentality.28 Inasmuch as the concept of ‘free labour contains the pauper’, the character trait of private property combines free competition and robust enforcement of labour discipline on the factory floor, stealing atoms of additional labour time, with an impulse to charity for the poor and downtrodden.29 Second, for Smith, the moral sentiments manifest the mentality of the system of liberty. Their provision belongs therefore to the state, which renders the moral sentiments as the well-informed power of commercial society. That is, for Smith the political state is not really an impartial and well-informed spectator. Rather, it is charged with making the system of perfect liberty valid in the mentality of society.30 In short, the Smithean state is charged with rendering the system of perfect liberty effective. For Smith, the state governs in the true interests of the common wealth, appealing to and connecting with the sociable core of self-interested individuals, restraining their immediate individual interests and class interests within a moral framework that both legitimizes the system of justice and embeds the morality of private property, sympathy and competitiveness into the inner recess of the acting individuals, securing the physiognomy of bourgeois society. For the sake of liberty it is thus necessary to employ ‘the power of the commonwealth’, that is, the state, ‘to enforce the practice of justice. Without this precaution, commercial society will descend into bloodshed and disorder, every man revenging himself at his own hand whenever he fancied he is injured.’ Punishment is the condition of justice. ‘All men delight’ to see injustice ‘punished’, and injustice needs to ‘be punished . . . on account of the order of society’.31 Only those who do not violate the laws of justice are ‘left perfectly free to pursue [their] own interests [their] own way, and to bring both [their] industry and capital into competition with any other man, or order of man’.32 He thus suggests that the state is responsible for securing the proper use of freedom – by means of police: it punishes the misuse of freedom and thus

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 171

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

172

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

enforces the order of freedom, securing the law of private property. That is, the ‘affluence of the rich excites the indignation of the poor, who are often both driven by want, and promoted by envy to invade his possessions’. The freedom of private property therefore ‘necessarily requires the establishment of civil government’ to contain the ‘indignance of the many’. That is, ‘civil government, so far as it is instituted for the security of property, is in reality instituted for the defence of the rich against the poor, or of those who have some property against those who have none at all’. 33 However, for Smith the defence of private property against the poor is ostensibly undertaken in the interest of the poor as it is only by means of the system of perfect liberty that the poor will benefit from the law of private property as wealth will eventually trickle down. Smith introduces the class struggle between capital and labour arguing that ‘wages depend upon contract between two parties whose interests are not the same’. That is, the ‘workmen desire to get a lot, the master to give as little as possible. The former are disposed to combine to raise, the latter to lower the wages of labour.’ In this struggle, the masters have the upper hand because they ‘are fewer in number, and combine much more easily; they can live for longer without getting their profits, the workers are starved’. That workers rebel is understandable given their ‘desperate conditions’. Yet, their action is foolish because ‘the masters react with purpose and force the worker back and that is, the workmen very seldom derive any advantage from the violence of those tumultuous combinations’. 34 The only way to raise wages and improve conditions is by sustained accumulation, which increases the demand for labour and thus improves the market position of the worker. Resolution of the workers’ desperate conditions and quarrelsome nature does not lie in the admittedly unequal exchange relation between capital and labour. Resolution lies in the dynamic increase in wages that depend on the most rapid growth possible in the demand for labour, which results from the growth of the market, increase in trade and commerce, which is based on the division of labour, which in turn is fed by greater labour productivity. Therefore, ‘workers do well not to struggle, because with the increase of surplus, stock accumulates, increasing the number of workers, and the increase of revenue and stock is the increase of national wealth. The demand for those who live by wages . . . increases with the increase in national wealth.’ This, then, is the famous trickle-down effect – accumulation, he argues, increases national wealth and ‘occasions a rise in the wage of labour’. Smith calls this the ‘liberal reward for labour’, and one consequence of his argument is, of course, that if there are poor, then this is an indication that ‘things are at a stand’, requiring state action to facilitate ‘the cheapness of goods of all sorts’ by means of increased labour productivity as the foundation of the

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 172

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

173

profitability of stock, ensuring the price competitiveness of the products of labour in a world governed by the harsh reality of the invisible hand.35 The owners of stock in some countries might achieve higher rates of return on their investment than owners in some other countries, ‘which no doubt demonstrate[s] the redundancy of their stock’. For their stock to be maintained, competitive adjustment is required. Adjustment is neither automatic nor assured. It requires facilitation, which belongs to the state. The state is responsible for the progress of the common wealth. Indeed, police is needed to secure the system of perfect liberty in the face of ignorant and quarrelsome workers and the profit-seeking owners of stock. For Smith, while ‘national wealth’ and ‘workers’ benefit from progressive accumulation, the owners of stock might not because ‘the increase in stock, which raises wage, tends to lower profit’.36 Capitalists, he suggests, pursue their own narrow class interests and might therefore seek to maintain the rate of profit artificially, impeding the natural liberty of the market, for example, by means of monopoly, price fixing or protectionism. In this context, too, the state acts to enforce the system of perfect liberty. That is, ‘whatever regulations are made with respect to the trade, commerce, agriculture, manufactures of the country are considered as belonging to the police’.37 Effective policing entails a strong state, a state where it belongs: over and above the egoistic interests and class struggles, ostensibly not governing in the interest of either but in the interest of the beauty of the well-ordered whole of the system of liberty, securing its propriety. The state thus governs in the interests of the bonum comune of commercial society. It intervenes in the behaviour of individuals to restrain their passions that are governed by ‘self-love’ and short-term class interests to secure its further development. Concerning the poor, police is needed to make the worker accept that ‘if he is frugal and industrious, [he] may enjoy a greater share of the necessaries and conveniences of life than it is possible for any savage to acquire’. There is thus need, also, for ‘the instruction of the people’ chiefly by means of education and public diversions.38 For Smith, then, government should take pains to offset the socially and morally destructive effects of accumulation, by assuming responsibility for cultural activities to render society, in its moral sentiments, economic behaviour and social relations. The administration of justice, which secures the law of private property and gives ‘the inhabitants of a country liberty and security’, describes, in Smith’s words, an order of good government that enforces the system of perfect liberty upon the owners of stock to contain their passion within the framework of law, order, morality and sociability. For the benefit of everybody in society, including the poor who depend for the improvement of their circumstances on the increase in wealth, the political state enforces the discipline of a

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 173

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

174

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

rules-based competitive system to secure the further division of labour based on improved labour productivity. The purpose of the state is thus to secure for the invisible hand that perfect order upon which the progress of commercial society depends. For the sake of progress, the dynamic of commercial society needs to be sustained, and in this context, the ‘inequality in the fortunes of mankind’ is in fact ‘useful’.39 In conclusion, the state maintains ‘the rich in the possession of their wealth against the violence and rapacity of the poor’ and it does so in the interest of the poor themselves.40 Wealth will eventually trickle down to allow for that improvement of conditions which only economic growth can furnish. He thus conceives of the state unashamedly as a class state that, ostensibly, operates in the true interest of workers – for economic growth, security of employment and wage income and conditions. For Smith, the workers do well not to resist the progressive accumulation of capital inasmuch as their very existence depends on it. The base superstructure metaphor that Marx derived from classical political economy focuses the state as the political force of the law of value.41 As a tax state, it depends entirely on the progressive accumulation of the wealth of the nation, and thus on the international competitiveness of ‘stock’. However, the class character of the state is not defined in national terms. It subsists through world-market relations. As Smith put it, the proprietor of stock is properly a citizen of the world, and is not necessarily attached to any particular country. He would be apt to abandon the country in which he was exposed to a vexatious inquisition, in order to be assessed to a burdensome tax, and would remove his stock to some other country where he could either carry on his business, or enjoy his fortune more at his ease.42 In the well-ordered common wealth, the law of private property manifests itself in the form of the heavy artillery of the price mechanism, which feeds on the ‘cheapness of provision’ and which thus entails constant pressure to achieve greater labour productivity, the facilitation of which ‘produces what we call police’.43

Neoliberalism and the theory of the state: On free economy and market police The conventional view that neoliberalism has to do with the weakening of the state has little, if anything, to do with the neoliberal conception of the

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 174

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

175

free economy. For the neoliberals, too, the state is the indispensable political force of the society of free labour.44 Laissez-faire is no ‘answer to riots’.45 For the neoliberals the issue is not whether the state should or should not intervene. Rather, the issue is the purpose and method, the objective and aim of state intervention. Regulation by the invisible hand is indispensable – in the economic sphere. Left to its own devices, market freedom will ‘degenerate into a vulgar brawl’ (Röpke) between the ‘greedy self-seekers’ and implode in the face of the destructive forces of the proletariat (Rüstow).46 It ‘does not breed social integration’ nor does it create the moral sentiment and entrepreneurial commitments that sustain bourgeois society.47 The free economy is a practice of government. In the words of Hayek, the state is indispensable as the ‘economic planner for competition’.48 It facilitates (free) economy as a politically ordered freedom, which extends beyond the system of justice and the rule of law. Fundamentally economic freedom depends on ‘the will’ (Böhm) for economic freedom, which requires the ‘incorporation [of competition] into a total life-style’ relieving, says MüllerArmack, workers from the fear of capitalist freedom and making them accept self-responsibility for that freedom.49 The state is thus required to secure the ‘psycho-moral forces’ at the disposal of a capitalist society, transforming rebellious proletarians into self-responsible entrepreneurs of labour power.50 Neoliberalism recognizes that free economy is not some automatic process, which unfolds or asserts itself objectively over the acting individuals. Capitalist economy does not comprise ‘unconditionally valid economic laws’ nor is capitalism governed by the theological quirks of the invisible hand, nor do the dependent masses accept their existence as propertyless producers of surplus value without a fight.51 The circumstance that the labourers are ‘governed’ by the dull compulsion of economic need does neither come about just like that, nor does it maintain itself just like that. Its reality is neither given nor assured. It is made. That is, the magic of the invisible hand depends on uninhibited market forces, which in turn depend on the successful removal of impediments to free economy by the order-making and preserving state. Laissez-faire describes the wished-for economic conditions. It does not extend to the political sphere. In fact, Hayek argues that laissez-faire is ‘a highly ambiguous and misleading description of the principles on which a liberal policy is based’.52 Prevention of the ‘coercion and violence’ by private powers, principally by organized labour and selforganization of quarrelsome proletarians, is a political task.53 It aims at the ‘complete eradication of all orderlessness from markets and the elimination of private power from the economy’,54 securing the social individuals as rational actors of economic value, mere human material for the valorization

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 175

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

176

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

of value. The institutional separation of the state from the economy is not just a condition of economic liberty and social freedom, of the depoliticized exchange relations between the commodity owners. Rather, economic liberty is a practice of government. The depoliticization of the social relations is not a product of economic liberty. In its entirety it amounts to a practice of government. Free economy presupposes the absence of direct coercion; the buyers of labour power and producers of surplus value make contracts as free and equal citizens. Thus the free economy entails depoliticized relations based on a contract between self-responsible economic agents. Direct coercion and violence is replaced by economic preferences, that is, in reality, the silent force of economic compulsion. This organization of the exchange relations requires the power of the state as the force of socio-economic depoliticization. The trade relations in labour power and its effective utility as a means of greater wealth amounts to a political practice of depoliticized socio-economic relations. That is, free economy ‘is an eminently political decision ’, which needs to be made time and time again to contain the illiberal use of freedom and prevent the politicization of the social labour relations.55 The Smithean notion that the political state is innate to the concept of the invisible hand is fundamental to neoliberal thought. It sees the state as the public authority of the invisible hand, which is the regulative means of the depoliticized relations of factor competiveness and labour utility. Concentrated and organized coercive force is thus the precondition of free economy. The laws of equivalent exchange are premised on order, and the establishment of order is a political matter. That is, the invisible hand is neither an answer ‘to the hungry hordes of vested interests’, nor is it an answer to the rapacity of the poor, as Smith put it.56 The invisible hand is premised on the state as ‘market police’.57 Market police amounts to a constant effort at securing the social and moral preconditions for free economy. That is, in its entirety economic regulation by the invisible hand is a political practice. Liberalism therefore does not demand ‘weakness from the state, but only freedom for economic development under state protection’.58 In this sense, the state of the free economy does not really govern over society. Rather, it governs through the individuals. There is no freedom without the order of freedom, and order is not only a matter of law. It is also a matter of morality. The order of freedom entails surveillance as a means of freedom. The premise of government is that economic ‘security is only to be had at a price of constant watchfulness and adaptability and the preparedness of each individual to live courageously and put up with life’s insecurities’.59 There really is only one freedom, and that is the freedom of the self-responsible economic agents

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 176

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

177

who adjust to the price signals with the will of and for enterprise, the one buying labour power with the expectation of making a profit, the other selling labour power as the dispossessed producer of surplus value, seeking to make ends meet. That is, poverty is neither unfreedom nor is it primarily material in character.60 Rather, poverty expresses a moral form of deprivation that is characterized by a poverty of aspiration, requiring state action to transform the sellers of labour power from quarrelsome proletarians into citizens of private property. As such a citizen the worker personifies labour power, which she takes to the market to trade for a wage. She appears thus as an entrepreneur of labour power, always ready to compete for a contract of employment. She thus perceives poverty as an incentive to do better, sees unemployment as an opportunity for employment, prices herself into jobs willingly and on her own initiative and takes her life into her own hands, gets on with things, lives courageously and puts up with life’s insecurities and risks. For the neoliberals, unemployed workers are fundamentally entrepreneurs of labour power in transit, ‘floating’ from one form of employment to another. However, the sociological condition of the worker is based on ‘the transformation of labour power into a commodity, which results from the separation of the worker from the means of production’.61 There is thus a ‘natural tendency towards proletarianisation’, and government is therefore required to counteract this tendency, time and time again, to secure the order of freedom.62 Government over society is government in and through society to ensure ‘the will’ for enterprise and labour market competition, integrating the free labourer into the capitalist relations of ‘coined freedom’ as a willing employer of labour power.63 In sum, the neoliberal conception of political economy develops Smith’s insight that the veracity of economic categories is a political one. That is, the ‘players in the game’ need to accept free economy, especially those who ‘might systematically do poorly’64 and who therefore struggle against a conceptuality of freedom that for them entails a double freedom: they are free from the means of subsistence and therefore free to produce surplus value in exchange for a wage to meet their subsistence needs. For the neoliberals, there is an innate connection between the law of private property and the order-making and order-preserving force of the state. Indeed, the organizational centre of political economy is the state, it is ‘the guardian of enterprise’,65 setting and enforcing the rules of the free and equal exchange relations between the sellers and buyers of commodities, comprising on the one side the owner of the means of production as the buyer of labour power, and on the other the producer of surplus value as the seller of labour power. Economy has no independent reality. It is a political economy.66

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 177

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

178

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Political theology: Freedom and dictatorship According to Carl Friedrich, the purpose of ‘military government is to protect the welfare of the governed’ – it is ‘inspired by humanitarian consideration’.67 However cynical, his take on the humanitarian character of military government expresses the obvious truth that, as the political form of bourgeois society, the state is responsible for maintaining the existing social relations. Friedrich recognizes that the institutional independence of the state from society is crucial to this task. It allows the state to function as a ‘strong and neutral guardian of the public interest’ asserting ‘its authority vis-à-vis the interest groups that press upon the government and clamour for recognition of their particular needs and wants’.68 His argument illustrates well Marx’s critique of the state as the executive committee of bourgeois society. In our time, Milton Friedman has provided its cogent definition: [T]he organisation of economic activity through voluntary exchange presumes that we have provided, through government, for the maintenance of law and order to prevent coercion of one individual by another, the enforcement of contracts voluntarily entered into, the definition of the meaning of property rights, the interpretation and enforcement of such rights, and the provision of a monetary framework. The state has to ‘promote competition’ and do for the market what the market ‘cannot do for itself’. The state, then, is ‘essential both as a forum for determining the “rules of the game” and as an umpire to interpret and enforce the rules decided upon’ and enforcement is necessary ‘on the part of those few who would otherwise not play the game’. The state, he says, is the means through which ‘we’ set and modify the rules.69 However, what happens when ‘they’ fail to adjust to the demands of the market and instead start to rebel? Rebellions cannot be suppressed by ‘juridical injunction’.70 Suppression requires the employment of concentrated force that ‘in the name of freedom’ is said to protect the welfare of the governed. At a time of liberal emergency, the occasion might thus arise when ‘the law needs to be broken in order to preserve it’.71 The law does not suspend itself. Suspension is an eminently political decision. In Carl Schmitt’s definition of the political as the relationship between enemy and foe the state is properly a state on the condition that it recognizes the class enemy and formulates and conducts its policies on the basis of this recognition. He sees the state as the ‘monopolist of the ultimate decision’ as to whether the containment of the enemy on the basis of the rule of law is effective or whether

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 178

2/19/2014 3:45:28 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

179

its temporary suspension is required so that order can be restored for the sake of sound economy under the rule of law.72 He argued that ‘there is no legal norm that can be applied to chaos. Order has to be established for the legal norms to be effective’.73 Whether there is order or disorder, whether the rule of law applies or whether the force of law (making violence) is needed to reassert the rule of law is a question of judgement – not of law but of a sovereign decision. The decision is valid because it has been made. For the decision to be valid there is thus need to eliminate any doubt in the veracity of the action. All law, as Schmitt put it, is ‘situational’ – not as an expression of a shifting balance of the social forces that in the view of Jessop act through the state, defining its character and purpose.74 Here the rule of law reflects the ‘situation’ of the balance of class forces. For Schmitt, the rule of law is situational in character because its veracity is a matter of authoritative judgement about the conditions of social order. Society is either governed by the rule of law or it is not, in which case government by the force of law-making violence becomes necessary to restore the liberal veracity of the rule of law. The rule of law is thus situational because it depends on the sovereign decision as to whether it applies or not. Schmitt thus denounces the tradition of political pluralism and legal positivism as doctrines based on the idea of relative truth. Normative values, he argues, are either absolute or they posit nothing at all. Thus, ‘relative truth never gives one the courage to use force and to spill blood’.75 Whether the rule of law applies or whether it needs to be suspended is thus a question, not of law, but of sovereign decision and judgement in the face of the (class) enemy. Necessity knows no law. The law of necessity is the law of violence. ‘Sovereign is who decides on the state of emergency.’76 Long before Schmitt, Rosa Luxemburg’s critique of the state saw clearly what Schmitt affirms. In the context of the debate between the revolutionary and reformist wings of German social democracy, she declared that the state ‘is itself the representative of capitalist society. It is a class state’.77 It recognizes bourgeois class interests as universal-human interests, and governs accordingly. In this society, the representative institutions, democratic in form, are in content the instrument of the interests of the ruling class. This manifests itself in a tangible fashion in the fact that as soon as democracy shows the tendency to negate its class character and become transformed into an instrument of the real interests of the population, the democratic forms are sacrificed by the bourgeoisie and by its state representatives.78 Schumpeter thus argued that at its best liberal democracy is a most effective form of government because it allows for the peaceful circulation of elites

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 179

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

180

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

by means of competitive elections.79 The great danger for the democratic state is the democratization of society.80 By recognizing and organizing its own powers directly as social powers, the democratization of the society challenges the distinction between society and state by politicizing the social relations, leading to conditions of ungovernability, if unchecked. For the sake of liberty, the state needs thus to be rolled back from society, reinforcing the distinction between state and society and thus securing the political state as the presupposition of a depoliticized society, one that as a consequence of the political effort of socio-economic depoliticization, is solely governed by the liberal rule of law and the moral sentiments of enterprise and competition. Reasserting the distinction between state and society is an eminently political decision with potentially far-reaching consequences.81 Rossiter therefore argues that for the sake of liberal democracy ‘no sacrifice is too great for our democracy, least of all the temporary sacrifice of democracy itself’.82 Rossiter’s point focuses the raison d’être of Bonapartism succinctly. Bonapartism is the theology of political reaction. It asks what is necessary to secure bourgeois interests as the universal interests of society at a time of manifest political crisis. Its political force comes to the fore when the ‘constitutional government must be temporarily altered to whatever degree is necessary to overcome the peril and restore normal conditions’.83 That is, the democratization of society creates, as Friedrich put it, ‘the states of emergency which call for the establishment of constitutional dictatorship’.84 Necessity knows no law. It demands the use of force to restore the order of the common wealth. For Schmitt, therefore, an effective democracy depends on the fundamental homogeneity between rulers and ruled. It is, as it were, possible only on the condition that it is a democracy of ‘friends’.85 Schmitt’s programme of ‘sound economy and the strong state’ is the demand of neoliberalism.86 For the sake of an economy of free labour, liberalism has to put itself at the ‘forefront of the fight for the state’ because it is only the state that can guarantee the ‘common wealth’, and liberalism should not involve itself with defending particular interests. It should always focus on the ‘whole’, and this whole ‘is the state’.87 The purpose of ‘dictatorship within the bounds of democracy’ is innately social and moral as social disorder can only be resolved by a strong state that suppresses the class struggle.88 Röpke defines this ‘dictatorship within the bounds of democracy’ correctly as a commissarial dictatorship.89 It temporarily suspends the rule of law to restore legitimate authority in the face of an ‘extreme emergency’, for which he holds responsible those who lack the ‘moral stamina’ to absorb economic shocks.90 The neoliberal demand for the strong state is a demand for the limited state, one that limits itself to the task of making the economy of free labour effective. In the face of

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 180

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

181

disorder and politicized labour relations, the state has to act and when it has to act ‘the most fundamental principles of a free society . . . may have to be temporarily sacrificed . . . [to preserve] liberty in the long run’.91 According to Hayek, ‘dictatorship may impose limits on itself, and a dictatorship that imposes such limits may be more liberal in its policies than a democratic assembly that knows of no such limits’.92 Unsurprisingly, Hayek accepts Schmitt’s conception of sovereignty – ‘sovereign is the one who decides on the exception’.93 A dictatorship that imposes limits on itself, and that thereby governs for the sake of the free economy, is a dictatorship that ‘should be no cause for alarm’ because it is ‘constitutional’.94 That is to say, a constitutional dictatorship is not ‘a contradiction in terms’ but rather ‘the litmus test of constitutionalism’. In the face of liberal emergency, it preserves the rule of law by means of the force of law.95 Rossiter puts this point succinctly when he argues that ‘law is made for the state, not the state for the law’. In case circumstances ‘are such that a choice must be made between the two, it is the law which needs be sacrificed to the state’.96 The use of ‘organised force’, which according to Friedrich is employed for the welfare of the governed, does not entail less liberty. On the contrary, it is the condition of liberty. It preserves and sustains the prospects of liberty by means of ‘executive action’. The ‘extraordinary means for maintaining the state’97 – from martial law to a state of emergency, from restraint of civil liberties to a full-blown constitutional or commissarial dictatorship – entail not just a temporary strengthening of the state where ‘government will have more power, the people fewer rights ’.98 Fundamentally, it is a means of ‘freedom’.99 Nevertheless, there is the danger that dictatorship becomes ‘totalitarian’, or in the words of Schmitt, instead of the desired commissarial dictatorship, it assumes the character of a sovereign dictatorship. What to do? As Friedrich put it, ‘how are we to get effective, vigorous governmental action and yet limit the power of governmental bodies so as to forestall the rise of a despotic concentration of power?’100 For Friedrich this is a ‘logical paradox’ that can only be resolved in practice, that is, ‘whatever forbidden fields of freedom the necessities of crisis may force the leaders of a constitutional government to go, go they must’.101 In sum, the point of political theology is not to provide a political theory of the state, let alone a critique of the state as the political form of capitalist social relations. The point of political theology is to ask what is necessary to sustain the existent social relations. It moves, as it were, from the lectern to the barracks, seeking to maintain the economy of free labour in the face of a manifest social crisis, class conflict and political strife. It is premised on the understanding that economic liberty amounts to a political practice of ‘market police’.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 181

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

182

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Conclusion: On the critique of political economy The tradition of political economy establishes the state as the political form of free economy. It conceives of the state as the political force of the invisible hand. Without government, society descends into ‘disorder and bloodshed’. Government is the condition and premise of bourgeois society, civilizing its antagonistic character. It maintains the unity of the disunited social relations, and contains class antagonism on the basis of law and morality, and by means of force. The political state is the forceful premise of the relations of liberty, equality and utility. The difference between the neoliberals and Smith is that unlike Smith, they do not provide a social theory of capitalist social relations. They demand strong state action as the means of preserving and sustaining free economy. Economic regulation by the free price mechanism manifests a constant political effort of facilitating economic freedom in the social structure and moral fabric of society. A free labour economy presupposes the state as the political authority of that freedom. In its role as market police, the state is fundamentally a security state, ever vigilant in its surveillance of society to secure the proper use of freedom, ‘policing’ not only compliance with the rule of law but also the will for enterprise. Whether there is disorder or order is a matter, not of law but political decision. Their political stance expresses the ‘Bonapartist’ theology of state power, according to which the veracity of the strong state is not relative. It is absolute in its pursuit of a free economy of labour. Smith, in contrast, does not even utter the word ‘liberalism’. There was no such system to defend. Smith wrote his work as a critique of mercantilism. By the beginning of the nineteenth century, liberalism had become the ideological orthodoxy of a liberalizing state.102 It was in this context that Marx writes (with Engels) in the Communist Manifesto about the cosmopolitan character of the bourgeoisie, and defines the national state as the executive committee of the bourgeoisie. The idea that the economy comprises an independent reality expresses a theological conviction. The capitalist state is neither independent from the economy nor does it derive from it, nor does the economy comprise a structured system of independent economic laws. Capitalist economy is a socially constituted system of human reproduction that is antagonistic from the outset. Its cohesion, organization, integration and reproduction are matters of state. It provides for the ‘organisation of economy activity’.103 The tradition of political economy does not therefore define the state by its relationship to the market, nor does it define the economic in relationship to the state, a view which implies a conception of market and state as two distinct modes

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 182

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

183

of social organization, and the perennial question about such a conception is whether the market has autonomy vis-à-vis the state or conversely whether the state has autonomy vis-à-vis the maket, characterizing its retreat or resurgence as a power vis-à-vis the economic. For political economy the relationship between the economy and state is an innate one, and within their ‘inner connection’, the state is fundamental. It manifests the free economy of labour as a practice of government. There can thus be no economic crisis. Economic crises are crises of political economy. In Röpke’s view one should therefore ‘not speak of a “crisis of capitalism” but of a “crisis of interventionism”’.104 That is, the state is ‘the mistress of the economy in its totality as in its parts . . . and the state must master the whole of economic development both intellectually and materially’; it must plan for liberty and competition.105 Economic crises therefore manifest a failure of government, which turned a blind eye to the problems of economy, society and morality. The state failed either in removing impediments to market freedom or in restraining the passions of competition or greed, or in securing the cheapness of provision, or in facilitating the requisite psychomoral forces of enterprise, or in embedding the spirit of enterprise into society at large, or compounded the poverty of aspirations by a permissive welfare state, or turned a blind eye to the rapacity of the poor, which could have been curbed by means of welfare concessions, employment programmes, etc. The ‘failure’ of the state is the failure of the executive committee of bourgeois society. Marx’s conception of the state as the concentrated and organized force of society – ‘of society viewed in relationship to itself’ – focuses political economy as a political practice. As the organized force of the system of wealth based on free labour the state facilitates the order of economic freedom, sustains the capitalist relations of production and exchange, and seeks the further progress of the system of free labour by facilitating the ‘cheapness of provision’.106 Marx’s stance elucidates the liberal paradox that the state always governs too much and too little, commits too much welfare support or too little, regulates too much or too little. The market liberal idea that uninhibited market forces are the only remedy to resolving economic crisis is deceitful. Uninhibited markets describe a political practice of eliminating impediments to free economy. Similarly, the idea that market failure is a consequence of too little or too much regulation is deceitful in that it identifies the cause of crises in the adopted means of economic regulation, as if crisis resolution is a matter of technical fine-tuning. Nevertheless, in either case, the state is endorsed as the indispensable force of capitalist social reproduction. For the sake of the capitalist form of wealth, of value in process, money in process, and as such capital, the state cannot have enough power – the law of value presupposes

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 183

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

184

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

the ‘political state’ (Marx) as the concentrated force of the relations of bourgeois freedom. In the German Ideology, Marx sketches the character of the bourgeois relations of reproduction as follows: everyone is dependent on everyone else, and each person can only reproduce himself inasmuch as all others become means for him. Furthermore, each individual can only pursue and realize his own particular interests when his conditions of reproduction, which are identical to those of everyone else, are accepted, respected and recognized by everyone else. The particular will of the individual obtains thus through a will in which all individuals are united, which is common to all, that is, is universal as the bonum commune of their sociability as personifications of value. The ‘attitude of the bourgeois to the conditions of his existence acquires one of its universal forms in bourgeois morality’ and these forms ‘must assume the form of the state’ and must gain ‘expression as the will of the state, as law’. That is to say, it is ‘precisely because individuals who are independent of one another assert themselves and their own will, and because on this basis their attitude to one another is bound to be egotistical, that self-denial is made necessary in law and right’ and assumes the form of the state.107 The rule of law treats the owners of the means of production and the free labourer as identical subjects, as citizens endowed with the same legal rights and obligations. The law is blind to privileges. It is a law of equality. Contractual relations represent the form in which, according to law, freedom obtains in the form of a legally bound recognition of private individuals in their relationship to one another. The labour contract is the juridical form of the bourgeois freedom of labour – it combines the freedom of exchange on the labour market with the acquired right to compel the worker beyond the necessary labour time and appropriate her unpaid labour time in the form of profit. This then characterizes the form of the state as an ‘illusory community’.108 In this community of equals ‘each pays heed to himself only, and no one worries about the rest. And precisely for that reason, either in accordance with the pre-established harmony of things, or under the auspices of an omniscient providence, they all work together to their mutual advantage, for the common weal and in the common interest.’109 Marx’s ironic take on the magic of the invisible hand as the regulative principle of bourgeois freedom, entails the understanding that in this society the individuals are indeed governed by real economic abstractions. However, these abstractions have no independent reality, they are socially constituted abstractions. Similarly the state is not an independent power. Rather it is ‘society’s [independent] power’.110 The state, then, does not ‘possesses its own intellectual, ethical and libertarian bases’.111 Rather, society doubles itself up into society and state. Instead of despotism, the state of capitalist society imposes law on the basis of order; it is the concentrated force of social order. It makes order by means of the force of law-making violence.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 184

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

185

It depoliticizes the socio-economic relations and so guarantees contractual relations of social interaction, secures the free and equal market relations and maintains the social relations founded on equality, freedom and utility. The depoliticization of society entails the ‘concentrating of the political character’ of society in the form of the state, this independent institutional form that is the concentrated force of society. The political form does not derive from bourgeois society. Rather it is immanent to its concept. For the sake of liberty, it forbids the dependent sellers of labour power and the owners of the means of subsistence equally to steal bread. The political state is the state of bourgeois society.

Notes 1 See, for example, Bob Jessop, State Power: A Strategic-Relational Approach (Cambridge 2008). The seminal work is Nicos Poulantzas, Political Power and Social Classes (London 1973). For a succinct critique of Poulantzas’s account, see Simon Clarke, ‘Marxism, Sociology and Poulantzas’ Theory of the State’, Capital & Class, vol. 1, no. 2 (1977), pp. 1–31. 2 Ernest Mandel, The Formation of the Economic Thought of Karl Marx (London 1971). 3 Dirk Braunstein, Adornos Kritik der politischen Ökonomie (Bielefeld 2011). Horkheimer and Marcuse did write about the authoritarian transformation of the Weimar state, but these efforts, too, remained rudimentary. Max Horkheimer, ‘Authoritarian State’, Telos, no. 15 (Spring 1973), pp. 3–20. Herbert Marcuse, ‘The Struggle Against Liberalism in the Totalitarian View of the State’, in Negations (London 1988). Franz Neumann, Behemoth (New York 2009) and Alfred Sohn Rethel, Economy and Class Structrure of German Fascism (London 1978) published insightful analyses about the Nazi state but did not develop a critical theory of the state as the political form of society. 4 The German state derivation debate of the 1970s sought to ‘derive’ the category ‘state’ from the economic categories of Marx’s Capital. The main contributions to this debate, including Reichelt’s, have been collected by John Holloway and Sol Picciotto in State and Capital (London 1978 ). The derivation debate was the German trajectory of the more general trend in the 1970s at breaking the economic determinism of Marxist state theory, from Italian Autonomism, see Steve Wright, Storming Heaven (London 2002), to the state debate within the Conference of Socialist Economists in Britain, see Simon Clarke (ed.), The State Debate (London 1991) and also Poulantzas’s early state theory, which set out to complement Marxian economic theory with a Marxist political theory. His final work on the state, State, Power, Socialism

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 185

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

186

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

(London 1978) was closer to the German state debate in its attempt at deriving the state from the capitalist social relations. 5 Elmar Altvater, ‘Some Problems of State Intervention’, and Joachim Hirsch ‘The State Apparatus and Social Reproduction’, both in John Holloway and Sol Picciotto, State and Capital. A Marxist Debate (London 1978). Hirsch’s contribution overlaps with Poulantzas’s account. 6 See, however, Bernhard Blanke, Ulrich Jürgens and Hans Kastendiek, ‘On the Current Marxist Discussion on the Analysis of Form and Function of the Bourgeoise State’, in John Holloway and Sol Picciotto, State and Capital. A Marxist Debate (London 1978), for an attempt at deriving the necessity of the state from the exchange relations between sellers and buyers of labour power. See also Robert Fine, Democracy and the Rule of Law (Caldwell, NJ 2002). Evgeny Pashukanis’s Law and Marxism (London 1987) work was instrumental for this line of argument. In distinction, Johannes Agnoli, Der Staat des Kapitals (Freiburg 1995) and Faschismus ohne Revision (1997), rather the deriving the ‘political’ form from the socio-economic forms, recognized the political character of political economy, which he developed in the context of his analysis of fascism and post-war developments. See also Johannes Agnoli, ‘The Market, the State, and the End of History’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, The Politics of Change (London 2000). Simon Clarke, Keynesianism, Monetarism and the Crisis of the State (Cheltenham 1988). John Holloway, ‘The State and Everyday Struggle’, in ed. Simon Clarke, The State Debate (London 1991), conceived of the state as the form assumed by the capitalist class relations and class struggle. See also John Holloway and Sol Picciotto, ‘Introduction’, in State and Capital: A Marxist Debate (London 1978). 7 Marx’s claim that his study let him to the discovery of this notion is misleading. See Werner Bonefeld, ‘Free economy and strong state’, Capital & Class, vol. 34, no. 1 (2010), pp. 15–24. 8 Theodor Adorno, Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge 2008a), p. 47. 9 The term Bonapartism refers to Marx’s account of Napoleon Bonaparte’s coup d’état that established a populist military dictatorship to safeguard the existing social relations in the face of mass revolt and revolution. Essentially, it amounts to a military counterrevolution, which uses selective reforms to co-opt the radicalism of the depended masses. In the modern era the term refers to Fascist and other authoritarian regimes that replace the liberal rule of law by the force of law-making violence, ostensibly safeguarding the rule of law by suspending it at a time of liberal emergency. Karl Marx, The Eigtheenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon (New York 1963). 10 Marx, Grundrisse (London 1973), p. 108. 11 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 108. 12 Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 915.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 186

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

187

13 Some might object to the use of bourgeois society in this context and insist on the use of civil society. But recall Hegel’s dictum: ‘In this society, the individuals are not citoyens, they are bourgeois’. Georg W. F. Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts 1817/18 (Stuttgart 1983), art. 89. The German for ‘civil society’ is Zivilgesellschaft or zivile Gesellschaft, not bürgerliche Gesellschaft, which translates as ‘bourgeois society’. 14 Georg W. F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford 1967), pp. 126. 130–1, 150, 149–50. 15 Hegel, Philosophy of Right, pp. 150, 151. 16 Georg W. F. Hegel, Jenenser Realphilosophie (Leipzig 1932), p. 232. 17 Hegel, Jenenser Realphilosophie, p. 240. 18 Hegel, Philosophy of Right, p. 210. 19 Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (London 1971), p. 20. The German original says ‘Basis’. The English edition says ‘foundation’. 20 The metaphor says that ‘the superstructure is the expression of the substructure’. Walter Benjamin, Das Passagen Werk (Frankfurt 1983), pp. 495–6. See also Werner Bonefeld, ‘Adam Smith and Ordoliberalism: On the Political Form of Market Freedom’, Review of International Studies, vol. 39, no. 2 (2013), pp. 233–50. 21 William Robertson, A General History of North and South America (London 1834), p. 79. 22 Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Indianapolis 1981), p. 25. 23 Smith, Inquiry, p. 428. 24 See Smith, Inquiry, p. 723. 25 Adam Smith, Lectures on Jurisprudence (Indianapolis 1978), p. 6. 26 Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (Oxford 1976), p. 86. 27 On this see Pashukanis, Law and Marxism. 28 Karl Marx, The Holy Family, Collected Works, vol. 4 (London 1975). 29 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 604. 30 Michel Foucault, ‘Governmentality’, in ed. Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller, The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality (Chicago 1991), captures this inhabitation of the moral sentiments well. Governmentality focuses on the internalization of the function of government into the mentality of the acting subjects. 31 Smith, Moral Sentiments, pp. 340, 89, 91. 32 Smith, Inquiry, p. 687. 33 Smith, Inquiry, pp. 710, 715. 34 Smith, Inquiry, pp. 83, 84, 85. 35 Smith, Inquiry, pp. 86–7, 87, 91, 333. 36 Smith, Inquiry, pp. 109, 105.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 187

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

188

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

37 Smith, Lectures, p. 5. 38 Smith, Inquiry, pp. 10, 723. 39 Smith, Lectures, p. 338. 40 Smith, Lectures, p. 338. 41 In distinction to Backhaus, ‘Between Philosophy and Science’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, Open Marxism, vol. I (London 1992), Marx’s metaphor does not surpass classical political economy. Werner Bonefeld, ‘The Capitalist State: Illusion and Critique’, in Revolutionary Writing (New York 2003). 42 Smith, Inquiry, pp. 848–9. 43 Smith, Lectures, p. 5. 44 The term neoliberalism was coined by Alexander Rüstow at the Walter Lippmann Colloquium in 1938. For the market liberals, it summarized the political experiences of the late 1920s and early 1930s. They asked what needs to be done to make capitalism work, and how to define or redefine capitalist economic rationality. They identified neoliberalism with a strong state – a state that governs for the free economy. The term was coined in critical distinction to laissez-faire liberalism, which at that time was the cause célèbre of the Austrian school of economics, von Mises in particular. The distinction between laissez-faire liberalism and neoliberalism though analytically sharp, is of less importance in the context of Realpolitik. For example, von Mises asserts that uninhibited market forces are the only remedy to resolving economic crisis, and then argues that ‘fascism and similar movements have . . . saved European civilization’. Ludwig von Mises, The Free and Prosperous Commonwealth (Irvington, NY 2000), p. 51. I owe the reference to Rüstow’s elucidation of neoliberalism as a rejection of (Austrian) laissez-faire to Ralf Ptak, ‘Neoliberalism in Germany’, in ed. Philip Mirowski and Dieter Plehwe, The Road from Mont Pelerin (Cambridge, MA 2009). For Michel Foucault, Biopolitics (London 2008), German neoliberalism is the foundation of neoliberal thought. For an introduction to the main tenants of German neoliberalism see, Werner Bonefeld, ‘Freedom and the Strong State’, New Political Economy, vol. 17, no. 5 (2012), pp. 633–56. 45 Hans Willgerodt and Alan Peacock, ‘German Liberalism and Economic Revival’, in ed. Alan Peacock and Hans Willgerodt, German Neo-Liberals and the Social Market Economy (London 1989), p. 6. 46 Wilhelm Röpke, ‘The Guiding Principles of the Liberal Programme’, in ed. Friedrich Wünsche, Standard Texts on the Social Market Economy (Stuttgart 1982), p. 188. Alexander Rüstow, ‘Die Staatspolitischen Vorraussetzngen des wirtschaftspolitischen Liberalismus’, in Rede und Antwort (Ludwigsburg 1963), p. 255. 47 Werner Eucken, Grundsätze der Wirtschaftspolitik (Tübingen 2004), p. 360. 48 Friedrich Hayek, The Road to Serfdom (London 1944), p. 31. 49 Franz Böhm, Ordnung der Wirtschaft (Berlin 1937), p. 52. Alfred MüllerArmack, ‘The Social Market Economy as an Economic and Social Order’,

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 188

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

189

Review of Social Economy, vol. 36, no. 3 (1978), p. 328. Alfred Müller Armack, Genealogie der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft (Stuttgart 1981), p. 92. 50 Wilhelm Röpke, International Economic Disintegration (London 1942), p. 68. 51 Alexander Rüstow, ‘General Social Laws of the Economic Disintegration and Possibilities of Reconstruction’, Afterword to Wilhelm Röpke, International Economic Disintegration (London 1942), pp. 272–3, 270. 52 Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, p. 84. 53 Friedrich Hayek, A Tiger by the Tail (London 1972), pp. 66, 87. 54 Böhm, Ordnung der Wirtschaft, p. 150. 55 Franz Böhm, ‘Die Kampfansage an Ordnungstheorie und Ordnungspolitik’, Ordo, no. 2 (1973), p. 39. 56 Wilhelm Röpke, The Social Crisis of Our Time (New Brunswick, NJ 2009), p. 181. 57 Rüstow, ‘General Social Laws’, p. 289. 58 Hayek, A Tiger by the Tail, p. 66. 59 Wilhelm Röpke, The Moral Foundation of Civil Society (New Brunswick, NJ 2002), p. 198. 60 See, Sir Keith Joseph and Jonathan Sumption, Equality (London 1979). 61 Alexander Rüstow, Freiheit und Herrschaft (Münster 2005), p. 365. Rüstow develops the purposes of the liberal state based on a clear understanding of the doubly free labourer as the condition of free economy. See chapter 4 for an exposition. 62 Röpke, The Social Crisis, p. 128. 63 Wilhelm Röpke, Maß und Mitte (Zürich 1950), p. 252. 64 Victor Vanberg, ‘“Ordnungstheorie” as Constitutional Economics. The German Conception of a “Social Market Economy”’, Ordo, vol. 39 (1988), p. 26. 65 Victor Vanberg, The Constitution of Markets (London 2001), p. 50. 66 Michel Foucault disagrees with this point. He develops his argument on the basis of two distinct, though interdependent logics, the logic of the market and the logic against the market. He identifies the logic for the market as a competitive market economy that is ruled by the laws of perfect liberty – free competition, pursuit of economic value and regulation of entrepreneurial preferences and innovation by the free-price mechanism. He conceives of the logic against the market as comprising the principle of a biopolitical social policy, which for Foucault somewhat compensates for the heartless logic of economic value. Foucault, Biopolitics, p. 242. In distinction, political economy focuses the state as market-facilitating and market-embedding, which includes the relentless attempt at sustaining and maintaining the moral sentiments and sociological preconditions of economic liberty to secure the free economy of labour. On this see also Keith Tribe, ‘The Political Economy of Modernity: Foucault’s Collége de

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 189

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

190

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

France Lectures of 1978 and 1979’, Economy and Society, vol. 38, no. 4 (2009), pp. 679–98. 67 Carl Friedrich, Constitutional Government and Democracy; Theory and Practice in Europe and America (London 1968), p. 547. 68 Carl Friedrich, ‘The Political Thought of Neo-Liberalism’, The American Political Science Review, vol. 49, no. 2 (1955), p. 512. 69 Milton Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom (Chicago 1962), pp. 27, 34, 15, 25, 23. 70 Clinton L. Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship. Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies (Princeton, NJ 1948), p. 303. 71 Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship, pp. 7, 12. 72 On this see, Carl Schmitt, ‘Sound Economy – Strong State’, Appendix to Renato Cristi, Carl Schmitt and Authoritarian Liberalism (Cardiff 1998). 73 Carl Schmitt, Politische Theologie (Berlin 1990), p. 20. 74 Jessop, State Power. 75 Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy (Cambridge, MA 1988), p. 64. 76 Schmitt, Politische Theologie, p. 11. 77 Rosa Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution (London 1989), p. 41. Some commentators have rejected the New Left’s critique of the state, Johannes Agnoli, Die Transformation der Demokratie (Freiburg 1990), in particular, as adopting a left Schmittean perspective because of its anti-parliamentarian political stance. See, for example, Die Zeit ’s commentary on the occasion of Schmitt’s ninety-fifth birthday in 1983, in http://www.zeit.de/1983/28/ carl-schmitt-und-die-linke/seite-3 (accessed 1 February 2013). If there is a Schmittean left, it is the one that affirms the state as an instrument of violence, which needs to be seized and wielded on behalf of the identified class friend. The Schmittean left is the Leninist left. For a critique of Leninism, see the contributions to Werner Bonefeld and Sergio Tischler, What Needs to be Done? (Aldershot 2002). 78 Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution, p. 47. 79 See Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism & Democracy (London 1992), p. 246. 80 See, for example, Wilhelm Hennis, Die missverstandene Demokratie (Freiburg 1973), for an argument that the democratic self-determination of society is the biggest threat to democratic government. 81 In our time, the Pinochet dictatorship in Chile is the most emblematic. For Milton Friedman and Friedrich Hayek, it was a force of and for liberty. See Renato Cristi, Carl Schmitt and Authoritarian Liberalism (Cardiff 1998). 82 Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship, p. 314. 83 Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship, p. 5. 84 Friedrich, Constitutional Government, p. 580.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 190

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

191

ON THE STATE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

85 In the late 1920 and early 1930s, Schmitt and the German neoliberals fed on each other’s analyses; their vocabulary and concepts were interchangeable. After the Second World War, there was great ambiguity towards Schmitt, and efforts of cutting the connection are legion. Hayek, for example, rejected Schmitt in toto, denouncing him, rigthly, as the ‘leading Nazi theoretician of totalitarianism’ only to acknowledge that Schmitt ‘probably understood the character of the developing form of government better than most people’. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, p. 187; and Friedrich Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty (London 1979), p. 194. Hayek also accepted Schmitt’s distinction between democracy and liberalism and argued that Schmitt’s analysis was ‘most learned and perceptive’. Friedrich Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (London 1960), p. 485. On the connection between Schmitt and Hayek, see Cristi, Carl Schmitt and William E. Scheuermann, Carl Schmitt. The End of Law (Boulder, CO 1999). 86 Schmitt, ‘Sound Economy’. Rüstow, ‘Die Staatspolitischen Vorraussetzungen’. Rüstow’s paper was originally published in 1932. The legal philosopher Herman Heller, ‘Autoritärer Liberalismus?’ Die Neue Rundschau, vol. 44, no. 1 (1933), pp. 289–98, characterized this demand for strong state authority as an ‘authoritarian liberalism’, which he saw manifested in the political programme of the conservative von Papen government (1 June 1932 to 17 November 1932). On this, see Dieter Haselbach, Autoritärer Liberalismus und Soziale Marktwirtschaft (BadenBaden 1991). 87 Wilhelm Röpke, International Order and Economic Integration (Dodrecht 1959), pp. 44, 45. 88 Alexander Rüstow, ‘Diktatur innerhalb der Grenzen der Demokratie’, Vierteljahreshefte für Zeitgeschichte, vol. 7 (1959), pp. 110–11. Rüstow’s article first appeared in 1932. 89 Röpke, International Economic Disintegration, pp. 246, 247. 90 Röpke, The Social Crisis, p. 52. 91 Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty, p. 217. 92 Friedrich Hayek, cited in Cristi, Carl Schmitt, p. 168. Hayek’s musing about the liberalizing character of dictatorship came about in the context of the coup d’état in Chile in 1973. 93 Friedrich Hayek, Wissenschaft und Sozialismus (Tübingen 1978), p. 125. 94 Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship, p. 4. 95 Friedrich, Constitutional Government, pp. 580, see also p. 581. 96 Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship, p. 11. 97 Friedrich, Constitutional Government, pp. 563, 560. 98 Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship, p. 5. 99 Friedrich, Constitutional Government, p. 581. 100 Friedrich, Constitutional Government, p. 581.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 191

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

192

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

101 Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship, p. 290. 102 See Clarke, Keynesianism, chap. 1. 103 Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom, p. 15. 104 Wilhelm Röpke, Crisis and Cycles (London 1936), p. 160. 105 Böhm, Ordnung , p. 10. Hayek, The Road, p. 31. 106 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 108. ‘Cheapness of provision’ is Smith’s term. Smith, Lectures on Jurisprudence, p. 6. 107 Karl Marx and Friederich Engels, The German Ideology, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London 1976), pp. 180, 329. 108 Marx and Engels, The German Ideology, p. 78. 109 Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 280. 110 Marx, From the Preparatory Materials, in Marx Engels Collected Works, vol. 29 (London 1987), p. 439. 111 Karl Marx, ‘Critique of the Gotha Programme’, in Marx Engels Selected Works, vol. 3 (Moscow 1970), p. 28.

9781441161390_Ch08_Final_txt_print.indd 192

2/19/2014 3:45:29 PM

9 Anti-capitalism and the elements of antisemitism: On theology and real abstractions On the critique of the personifications of capital This book started with the argument that the sensuous social practice subsists in and through the movement of supersensible economic things. The supersensible world is the world of sensuous human practice in inverted form. According to Marx the point of critique can therefore not be to ‘make the individual responsible for relations whose creature he socially remains, however much he may subjectively raise himself above them’.1 It is not sufficient to criticize capitalists for their seemingly excessive addiction to profit, nor is it sufficient to criticize bankers for pursuing money for the sake of more money. On the pain of ruin, these behaviours manifest the ‘objective necessity’ of the capitalistically constituted social relations. Neither the capitalist nor the banker, nor indeed the worker can extricate themselves from the reality in which they live and which asserts itself not only over them but also through them, and by means of them. In this context, the question ‘what is criticized?’ becomes an important one. As I put it in the Introduction, how does one oppose the fateful movement of coins? Clearly, the critique of the banker, or any other socioeconomic operative of a system that asserts itself as an independent force over and through the social individuals, misses the object of critique. As a critical theory, the critique of political economy is therefore not a critique of the personifications of economic categories. It does not argue that the economy of labour is corrupted by the private interests of the capitalist and

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 195

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

196

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

his political friends, from which derives the demand for political action to set things right, ostensibly in the interest of humanity and for the sake of a rationalized labour economy. Instead, it is a critique of the capitalistically organized social relations of human reproduction that assume the form of a movement of economic things, which objectify themselves in the person. Nevertheless, while every individual is ‘ruled by abstractions’, the owners of great wealth experience this rule as a source of much enrichment and power. In this context Horkheimer and Adorno have argued that the ‘rulers’ are safe for as long as the ‘ruled’ struggle under the spell of the inverted world, in which, say, the cause of financial crisis, economic downturn and conditions of austerity are attributed to the greedy behaviour of identifiable individuals.2 A spellbound critique of capitalism demands more of this and less of that. It apportions blame and proclaims to know ‘how to set things right’. Rather than the capitalistically organized relations of social reproduction, it is, say, the profit-making consciousness of the capitalist and the greed of the speculator that is criticized, rejected and condemned. That is, the critique of the capitalist manifests itself as a demand for a better capitalism, one that works in the interests of the ‘workers’. Marx’s critique of Proudhon focused on this simple point.3 Proudhon substituted the critique of capitalism for a critique of the capitalist, seeking to free capital from the capitalist so as to utilize its economic force for the benefit of a well-ordered society, investing in society. The critique of the capitalist leaves the category of capital not only entirely untouched, it also elevates ‘capital’ as a thing beyond critique. Instead of a critique of the capitalist social relations, it identifies the guilty party, condemns it and demands state action to sort things out. It thus attributes capitalist conditions to the conscious activity of some identifiable individuals, who no longer appear as the personification of economic categories but, rather, as the personalized subject of misery. This personalization of the economic categories entails a number of differentiations, most importantly between the productive or indeed creative capitalist as a ‘producer’ of ‘real’ wealth employing a hardworking and creative people, and the financial or indeed parasitic capitalist who makes his fortune by speculating in money to the detriment of industry and workers. Here the distinction between use-value and concrete labour, on the one hand, and exchange value and abstract labour, including the manifestation of value in the form of money, on the other, appears in the form of distinct personalities – pitting the creative industrialist against the parasitic banker-cum-speculator. There emerges, then, the idea of a capitalism that is corrupted by the financial interests. Finance turns capitalism into a casino that spins the fortune wheel of the world at the expense of national industry, national wealth, national workers and national harmony.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 196

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

197

In this view the capital fetish, which manifests itself in the form of money as the ‘most senseless, incomprehensible form’ of wealth, expresses the conscious activity and the will of bankers, financiers and speculators.4 That is, a definite form of social relations manifests itself in the form of a movement of coins and then, under the spell of this coined movement, rebels against the personifications of a world governed by coins. The personalized critique of capital identifies the ‘wrongdoer’ of the wronged society and calls him a merchant of greed. For the sake of employment and industry, something needs to be. Something can be done! The personalized critique of capitalist social relations is open to abuse from the outset. It thinks akin to a register of blame, and condemns the identified party as a power that hides behind the economic phenomena, sucking the living life out of the national community of hard-working people. This identification of the subject of misery leads to the condemnation of the world-market society of capital as a network of money and power that imposes itself with destructive force on a national people who appear thus as victims of the cosmopolitan peddlers. The contemporary idea that so-called neoliberal capitalism resulted from a Washington-based agreement between money and power, the so-called Washington consensus, purports the idea, at least by implications, of a conspiratorial construction of a finance-driven world economy that, buttressed by the political and military might of the United States, exploits the nations of the world.5 The critique of financial imperialism entails the idea of anti-imperialism as a progressive, liberating force. The reverse of anti-imperialism is national liberation, by which the dominated national communities defend their identity in opposition to the disintegrating forces of financial globalization and imperial power. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri thus claim that ‘the anti-modern thrust that defines fundamentalism might be better understood not as a pre modern but as a post modern project’. What they endorse as a ‘progressive’ form of nationalism is entirely regressive.6 It is pure ideology to distinguish healthy national sentiment from pathological nationalism . . . The dynamic that leads from the supposedly healthy national sentiment into its overvalued excess is unstoppable, because its untruth is rooted in the person’s act of identifying himself with the irrational nexus of nature and society in which he by chance finds himself.7 The idea of the nation as a subject of liberation is as irrational as the belief in a national destiny and a national homogeneity of purposes, from the national industry via the national interest to the national history. The idea of the nation as the foundation of being and becoming recognizes the term ‘cosmopolitanism’ as a term of abuse. In its stead, it puts its faith in the imagined nation as some

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 197

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

198

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

naturally rooted and active thing, which it idolizes as the ‘spirit of the people’. If indeed it is permissible at all to speak about the national spirit of the people, it is a national spirit not by nature, but by history. By reducing history to nature or by reading nature into history, the struggle for national liberation becomes delusional inasmuch as a people are forced to act as if they really are natural forces that have a national history and destiny. The imagined nature of a people depends on the existence of some indefinable Other as the abstract focal point of the pseudo concreteness of the wronged nation.8 The identification of the ‘guilty parties’, speculator, banker and US imperialism personalizes the world of economic objectivity, and points an accusing finger at the identified foe of the national harmony of interests. According to Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, this personalization of the movement of real economic abstractions entails the elements of antisemitism.9 The personalized critique of capitalism is not a critique of capitalism, it identifies the hated forms of capitalism in the guilty party. It thus denounces identifiable wrongdoers under the spell of identification, which once radicalized into blind resentment becomes demagogic in its demand for salvation. What is the name of the speculator, what is the character of the banker and where does the wrongdoer live, how to make her visible? The wrongdoer can be named and identified, and yet appears intangible. She is everywhere, rumoured to stand behind the phenomena of a world that imposes itself upon the relations of national harmony with devastating force. The Nazi ideologue Alfred Rosenberg formulated the essence of modern antisemitism succinctly when he portrayed it as an attack on Communism, Bolshevism and ‘Jewish capitalism’, that is, a capitalism not of productive labour and industry, but of parasites – money and finance, speculators and bankers.10 Antisemitism articulates a senseless and barbaric discontent with conditions, which by leaving capitalism entirely untouched, is totalitarian in its manifestation. It is totalitarian ‘in that it seeks to make the rebellion of suppressed nature against domination directly useful to domination’ to the point of utter destruction.11 Auschwitz is the name of this destruction.12 For Adorno, Auschwitz not only manifested the violence that resides in the bourgeois relations of abstract equality and abstract identity but also confirmed the bourgeois relations of pure identity as death.13 That is, everyone can be numbered and become a number, and what is numbered is added up with mathematical precision to allow for the best possible calculation of given quantities of human material. The image of a Man is a metaphysical distraction. There are no subjects. Every number is a resource. Those deemed valueless human material are gassed without delay. Time is of the essence. There is no time to waste. This chapter argues that modern antisemitism is the ‘rumour about the Jews’ as incarnation of hated forms of capitalism.14 This rumour implies that

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 198

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

199

antisemitism expresses resistance to capitalism. The chapter expounds this deadly notion. The next section, introduces the elements of antisemitism, presents their contemporary context in anti-imperialism and argues that the anti-imperialist idea that the enemy of my enemy is my friend is entirely regressive. The final two sections explore Adorno and Horkheimer’s conception of Nazi antisemitism.15 The conclusion argues that antisemitism expresses the theology of anti-capitalism.

On the elements of antisemitism: On parasites and national liberation Racism and antisemitism are different-in-unity. All forms of racism project some Other as a disintegrating force of some assumed national homogeneity of purposes. Racism projects the Other as inferior or ‘sub-human’. This Other can be exploited economically and used as a political scapegoat. In contrast to antisemitism, this racialized Other is perceived as a rooted power – she has her own national roots and traditions. She belongs to a different national community. Racism demands that this Other should accept her position of inferiority without question. Its objective is not to ‘exclude people’ but to ‘keep them within the system as inferiors (Untermenschen)’.16 For the racist this Other is a potential slave, who needs to be kept in check for the sake of a society that demands to be served. This Other is regulated through institutional racism, threat of expulsion, segregation, racial profiling, slander, arson, murder and forced removal to indicate the precarious nature of her immigrant status. Racism transposes feudal relations of social hierarchy, position and privilege on to bourgeois society modernizing, as it were, the relations between master and slave as relations of an ‘organic’ society where everybody knows their place in the social hierarchy, and where the Other provides the excuse for a damaged life and becomes the object of hatred and ridicule, and is accepted, however precariously, for as long as she does her work quietly, without being seen. Antisemitism, in contrast, projects the Other as rootless and all-powerful. For the antisemite, the Jew comes from nowhere and, as a rootless cosmopolitan, is depicted as eternally wandering restlessly from place to place, peddling in money and misery. As a revenge the ‘wandering Jew’ is therefore not allowed, even in death, to rest. Desecration of Jewish cemeteries is the epitome of antisemitic behaviour.17 For the antisemite the Jews have no concrete roots, and the attempt to find roots, even in death, is a provocation and an incitement for action. That is, the ‘Jews’ are deemed ‘rootless’ and thus ‘unnatural’: they have their roots in a book, in reason,

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 199

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

200

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

cunning, argument, ideas, abstract thought and they personify abstract wealth – money and finance. Reason is a powerfully destructive force that belongs to the dissenter, heretic and subversive thinker. The antisemite attributes this power of reason to the cunning ‘Jew’.18 The ‘Jew’ is possessed by a rootless intelligence that is destructive of organic social matter. Their power however cannot be defined concretely; it is an abstract, intangible, invisible power. Antisemitism has nothing to do with concrete people. It ‘is the rumour about Jews’,19 all of them without exception – since nobody in particular can be named as the responsible agent of evil, everybody is guilty. Everybody can therefore be a Jew. The Jew is seen as the one who stands behind phenomena. Racism’s treatment of the Other as a real or potential slave contrasts with antisemitism’s projection of the ‘rootless and invisible’ power of the destructive Jew, this projected incarnation of evil. Evil cannot be enslaved for were it possible to enslave evil, it would no longer be evil. Evil needs to be eliminated. The rumoured Jew personifies an invisible power, and this power needs to be made visible through dehumanization; once reduced to a cipher it can be treated as if it really were invisible – the projected foe of the relations of national harmony is disappeared without trace. 20 Modern antisemitism summons the idea of finance and speculators as merchants of greed and, counterpoised to this, espouses the idea of a national community based on some assumed linearity of ancestral traditions and associated costumes of imagined forms of national morality and integrity. The national character is deemed to derive from the supposedly natural bonds of the nation that, as an organic community of equals, is based on blood and the ancestral possession of soil. The nation ‘is “subject to blood”, it arises from the “soil”, it furnishes the homeland with indestructible force and permanence, it is united by characteristics of “race”, the preservation of whose purity is the condition of the [nation’s] “health”’.21 Antisemitism asserts the idea of the ancestral nation as the imaged counterpoint to a world governed by fateful abstractions, especially money and finance, which are the forms of capitalist wealth par excellence. Money for the sake of more money includes the freedom to wealth and ruin, it entails wealth as an independent force that makes itself manifest behind the backs of the producers, as if directed by invisible forces. Antisemitism translates the discontent with the conditions of wealth into the collective approval of anger and resentment about the ‘Jewish capitalism’ of money. The depiction of the Jew as the ‘external enemy within’, who speculates for the sake of more money on the nation’s industry, is premised on the existence of the national state as the gatekeeper of the one-national ‘boat’, defined by the virtues of national solidarity, national struggle, national homogeneity of purpose and national industry and economy.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 200

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

201

This national definition of solidarity and economic effort attributes the production of material wealth to the concrete labour of the nation, in distinction to the abstract conceptuality of capitalist wealth as a world-market condition, which, in the form of money and finance, accumulates in a few hands. Whereas the nation produces the material wealth with sweat and tears, the wealth of money and finance seems effortless. It results from the dealing and wheeling with money, speculating on the national wealth of a hardworking people with fateful consequences. Instead of the capitalist social relations of production, there are the hard-working nations, and instead of the class division of society, there is a division between subordinate nations and imperial nations, and then there is the Jew – this personalized embodiment of abstract wealth that asserts its intangible but no less destructive power over the nations of the world in cohort with the system of imperialism and monopoly capitalism. Wallerstein has argued convincingly that orthodox Marxism was originally hostile to the concept of national liberation and ‘quite suspicious of all talk about the rights of peoples, which they associated with middle-class nationalist movements’. It was only at the Baku congress in 1920 that the emphasis on class struggle ‘was quietly shelved in favour of the tactical priority of anti-imperialism, a theme around which the 3rd International hoped to build a political alliance between largely European Communist parties and at least those of the national liberation movement . . . that were more radical’.22 After Baku, anti-imperialist struggles were ‘given the label of “revolutionary” activity’.23 The seminal text that informed this shift from the class struggle for general human emancipation to the anti-imperialist struggle for national liberation is Stalin’s Marxism and the National Question, written in 1913. Defining a nation as a ‘historically evolved, stable community of language, territory, economic life, and psychological make-up manifested in a community of culture’, he declared that ‘it is sufficient for a single one of these characteristics to be absent and the nation ceases to be a nation’.24 The Great Purges, as Leon Trotsky commented as early as 1937, espoused antisemitic demagogy to such an extent against the Marxists of internationalist persuasion that it almost amounted to a science. In the Soviet understanding of class struggle as anti-imperialist national liberation, the Jew appeared in many disguises – liberal, freemason, Social-Democrat, Trotskyist, fascist or Zionist – but regardless of its projected image, he embodied everything that was defined as capitalist, imperialist, Western and above all non-Russian.25 The critique of imperialism entails the demand for national self-determination as a liberating revolutionary practice. The abandonment of class as the critical category of revolutionary thought and its replacement by the category of the dominated nation remains particularly strong in relationship with Israel.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 201

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

202

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

According to Perry Anderson who is one of the more critical and distinctive thinkers of the anti-imperialist left, ‘entrenched in business, government and media, American Zionism has since the sixties acquired a firm grip on the levers of public opinion and official policy towards Israel, that has weakened only on the rarest of occasions’.26 For Anderson, Israel is a Jewish state, its nationalist triumphs are Jewish triumphs and its economy is a Jewish economy, making Israel a ‘rentier state’ that is kept by the United States as its imperialist bridgehead in the Middle East. The Jews, then, have not only conquered Palestine but they have also taken control of America, or as James Petras sees it, the current effort of ‘US empire building’ is shaped by ‘Zionist empire builders’.27 For Petras, Zionism is the ideology and the far-reaching organizational system and political practice of modern US imperialism that safeguards capitalist profits and wealth, its power and parasitic prosperity.28 Under the banner of anti-imperialist solidarity alliances with most unsavoury political forces can be reached in the pursuit of seemingly progressive ends, which on closer inspection are entirely regressive. According to Alex Callinicos anti-capitalism has to ‘meet the requirements of (at least) justice, efficiency, democracy, and sustainability’.29 In order to radicalize the anticapitalist movement, he demands that moral support is given to anti-imperial ‘resistance’ groups that are openly hostile to the anti-capitalist ends that he advocates.30 He urges the left to work in alliance with the ‘respectable Islamic clergy’ in order to ‘radicalise the anti-capitalist movement by giving it an antiimperialist edge’.31 That is, ‘[w]e have to work with the Muslim Brotherhood over specific issues [Palestine or Iraq]’.32 Judith Butler argues with a similar abandonment of thought that anti-imperialist resistance is a good thing in itself. When asked by ‘Online Magazin für Frauen’ to clarify her statement that Hamas and the Hezbollah are progressive social movements she remarks that ‘groups like Hamas and Hezbollah should be described as left movements . . . They are “left” in the sense that they oppose colonialism and imperialism.’33 Since she does not condone the use of violence she rejects their tactics, but accepts them nevertheless as members of the global left because they reject imperialism and demand national liberation. Her definition of the ‘left’ is indifferent to social ends and purposes, and includes most unsavoury bedfellows, historical as well as contemporary. Besides the imagined and romanticized qualities of the national being, what really does it mean to say that the nation is liberated? Slavoj Žižek provides a more circumspect argument. He says that in the face of antisemitism one should not ‘preach liberal tolerance’ but try to ‘express the underlying anti-capitalist motive in a direct, non-displaced way’.34 However, anti-capitalism does not necessarily entail the struggle for the classless society of human purposes. Žižek’s observation about the

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 202

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

203

underlying anti-capitalist motives seems to subscribe to a teleological view of history that believes in capitalism as a stage of transition to communism, as if by necessity. What if it does not? What other forms of anti-capitalism are possible, and what would it mean to express them in a direct, nondisplaced way? The support of anti-capitalism for the sake of anti-capitalism is entirely misconceived. Alex Callinicos’s robust defence of Al Qaeda against its description as fascist is a case in point. He rejects this description as ‘an extraordinary assertion’, and then goes on to say that the ‘Muslim concept of the ummah – the community of the faithful – is precisely a transnational one, something that the Al Qaeda network has strictly observed (whatever respects in which its interpretations of Muslim doctrine may differ from those of others), incorporating as it does activists from many different national backgrounds’.35 For Callinicos, Al Qaeda is transnational by virtue of its ‘strict observance of the ummah’, and therefore it cannot be described as ‘fascist’.36 Whether the fascist label is appropriate or not is beside the point. What is concerning is the ticket mentality that attaches labels to social things without further thought as to what these things might be. Anti-capitalism is not a singular form of opposition to the prevailing mode of social labour, and between that ‘non-displaced’ anti-capitalism and this anti-capitalism there is a world of difference.37 At best, solidarity with false friends self-affirms a posture of radicalism in conformist rebellion; at worst, maddened by resentment and blinded by its desire for action, it starts to ‘kick with the pricks instead of against them’.38 The anti-imperialist view that the enemy of my enemy is my friend is devoid of redeeming social contents. It buys into the ‘regressive egality’ of some imagined national or transnational we.39 In this context, the demand that nobody should be stoned to death becomes a relative one because anti-imperialism requires solidarity with supposedly anti-imperialist clerics who really believe that a woman who wants to be free from the traditional fetters of patriarchy should be stoned to death. ‘If “differance” has become the hallmark of theoretical anti-reason, “the Other” has become the hallmark of practical anti-reason.’40 Žižek is therefore right to argue that there should be no attempt to ‘“understand” Arab antiSemitism . . . as a “natural” reaction to the sad plight of the Palestinians’. It has to be resisted ‘unconditionally’. To ‘understand’ Islamic antisemitism as a ‘justified’ expression of anger against imperialism is to claim, by implication, that antisemitism articulates a worthwhile resistance to capitalism. Similarly, there should be no attempt to ‘understand’ the measures of the state of Israel ‘as a “natural” reaction against the background of the Holocaust’.41 Such ‘understanding’ accepts the utilization of Nazi barbarism as a legitimation for militarized state action. Every state is an entrepreneur of memory to legitimize itself and justify its policies in the name of the nation and the national interest.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 203

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

204

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

Such utilization of the past does not redeem the dead. Following Benjamin, redemption entails the recovery of the past in contemporary struggles for human emancipation, which is both singular and universal, indivisible and priceless.42 It is associated with refuseniks, heretics, dissenters and dissidents, not the good offices of the state. If therefore the critique of Israel wants to be more than just a deceitful publicity about nationalized abstractions, it has to summon the courage of the refusenik and dissenter and think against the grain of the national mist. It thus has to recognize the social distinctions that disappear in the political form of a homogenized national people. The abject violence used by the state of Israel in its dealings with the Palestinians has nothing to with Jewishness. State violence is not Jewish in character. Violence holds sway in the conceptuality of the capitalist social relations and it characterizes the state as the concentrated force of that society. What does the attribute ‘Jewish’ refer to? What is a Jewish state? The great theorist of the autonomy of the state, Thomas Hobbes, conceived of it as the result of a social contract that allowed the warring social interests to flourish on the basis of mutual protection. His state appeared akin to a mortal God. Adam Smith defined the state as a market enabling power – it polices the law-abiding conduct between the private interests to secure the relations of perfect liberty. For the economy to be free, the state needs to be strong, as market police. Karl Marx conceived of the state as the concentrated force of bourgeois society, and saw it as the political form of capitalist social relations. Max Weber argued that the state cannot be defined by its functions, let alone imagined national characteristics, but solely by its means: the legitimate use of violence. He conceived of the modern state as a machine. Lenin depicted the state as the instrument of class rule, and demanded the dictatorship of the proletariat. None of these accounts defines the state in terms of the supposed or imagined national characteristics of a homogenized people. Such forging of national identity is a political task, and Perry Anderson is therefore absolutely right when he argues that the potential of violence against the Other is intrinsic to nationalism, whichever.43 The attribute ‘Jewish’ does not refer to concrete human beings in their social relations, not does it refer to concrete individuals, be it Ariel Sharon or Karl Marx, Albert Einstein or Emma Goldman, Rosa Luxemburg or Leon Trotsky, Michael Neumann or Esther Rosenberg. It disregards human distinctions and rejects the notion that capitalist society comprises antagonistically constituted social relations for an argument about the Jewish character of capitalism. Its denunciation is total in that it treats everybody as an agent of the same invariant type, whether they are anarchists, communists, refuseniks, capitalists or workers, conservatives, religious fanatics, war mongers, peacelovers, beggars or just plain and boring average Joes.44 Instead of recognizing

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 204

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

205

contradictions, distinctions, antagonisms, struggles and conflicts, it projects those abstract, reason-defying, imagined ‘qualities’ upon which antisemitism rests onto a nationalized people, substituting the critique of the form of the state as the concentrated force of the existing social relations for totalitarian conceptions of the national friend and the national foe. Within this relationship, reason is suspended and thought is led to the further, equally irrational belief that the enemy of my enemy is my friend – from Hamas and the Hezbollah to the Muslim Brotherhood. That however also means that the only way to confront resurgent antisemitism is not to preach liberal tolerance which, say, accepts that nobody, neither woman nor man, should be stoned to death but represses this principle in relation to the anti-imperialist Other because its civilized humanity is in fact inhuman towards a people it secretly regards as uncivilized. Anti-capitalist tolerance of death by stoning because it was the anti-imperialist friends who did it has no values to defend and no principles to call upon. Antisemitism does not articulate anti-capitalism in a displaced manner. It criticizes capitalism as a system of Jewish power. Ulrike Meinhof, the late co-founder of the German Red Army Faction, succinctly articulated this rationalization of antisemitism as a hatred of capitalism when she said, Auschwitz meant that six million Jews were killed, and thrown on the waste-heap of Europe, for what they were: money Jews. Finance capital and the banks, the hard core of the system of imperialism and capitalism, had turned the hatred of men against money and exploitation, and against the Jews . . . Anti-Semitism is really a hatred of capitalism.45 What is Jewish about capitalism? What do antisemites attack when they attack capitalism? What is the measure of success? The following sections explore this topic with reference to Nazi antisemitism.

On the time of abstraction Antisemitism does not ‘need’ Jews. The ‘Jew’ has powers attributed to it that cannot be defined concretely. It is an abstraction that excludes nobody. Anyone can be considered a Jew. The concept ‘Jew’ knows no individuality, cannot be a man or a woman and cannot be seen as a worker or beggar; the word ‘Jew’ relates to a non-person, an abstraction. ‘The Jew is one whom other men consider a Jew.’46 In their Dialectic of the Enlightenment, Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno emphasize that Enlightenment’s ‘reason’

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 205

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

206

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

obtains fundamentally as ‘instrumental rationality’. ‘Instrumental rationality’ is reason’s false friend. Reason demands to know what the human purpose of something is; while instrumental rationality is interested in essentially two things: ‘how long did it take?’ and ‘how much did it cost?’ It thus focuses on the functionality of things, whatever they might be, and seeks to dispose of them as efficiently, effectively and economically as possible. In a world governed by real abstractions and measured by abstract social time, the mere existence of difference, this fleeting glimpse of a life beyond economic compulsion, is an intolerable provocation. It fosters the blind resentment and anger which antisemitism focuses and exploits but does not itself produce. ‘The thought of happiness without power is unbearable because it would then be true happiness.’47 Antisemitism differentiates between ‘society’ and ‘national community’. ‘Society’ is identified as ‘Jewish’, whereas community is modelled as a counter-world to society. Community is seen as natural and its natural character is seen to be at risk because of some ‘evil’ abstract social forces. The attributes given by the antisemite to the Jew include mobility, intangibility, rootlessness and conspiracy against the – mythical and mythologized – values of the imagined community of an honest and hard-working people. Reason stands rejected because of its infectious desire to go to the root of things, and the root of things can only be Man in her social relations. Reason is the weapon of critique. It challenges conditions where Man is degraded to a mere economic resource. For antisemitism independence of thought and the ability to think freely without fear is abhorrent. It detests the idea that ‘Man is the highest being for Man ’.48 Instead, it seeks deliverance through the furious affirmation of its own maddening reality, one that is governed by real economic abstractions. It asserts its own subjectivity under the spell of perverted economic forms. ‘Madness is the substitute for the dream that humanity could organize its world humanely, a dream that a man-made world is stubbornly rejecting.’49 For the apologists of the economy of free labour, the reference to the invisible hand operates like an explanatory refuge.50 It explains everything with reference to the Invisible. ‘Starvation is God’s way of punishing those who have too little faith in capitalism.’51 For the antisemites, however, the power of the invisible can be explained – the imagined Jew is its personalized existence. The Jew is the branded social parasite that is said to oppress, undermine and pervert the ‘natural community’ of a rooted homogenous people. The category ‘Jew’ is said to be the irresistible, abstract and intangible force of – bourgeois – civilization, from the invisible hand of the market to the relations of abstract equality before money and law. It personifies abstract thought, abstract equality and abstract wealth.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 206

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

207

Against this, the antisemite elevates the ‘regressive equality’ of some assumed ancestral community of Volksgenossen, which derives not only from some mythical ‘property’ of the land but also from some imagined bond of blood. In distinction to the parasitic wealth of money and finance, they claim to be creative producers of concrete things. The myth of the Jew as the incarnation of abstract equality is confronted with the myth of the original possession of soil and productive endeavour. The Volksgenosse sees himself as a son of nature and thus as a natural being. He sees his natural destiny in the liberation of the national community from the allegedly rootless, abstract values of capitalist civilization, demanding their naturalization so that everything is returned to ‘nature’. In short, the Volksgenosse portrays himself as rooted in blood and ancestral tradition to defend his own faith in the collective approval of anger. This anger is directed towards civilization’s supposed victory over nature, a victory that is seen as condemning the Volksgenossen to sweat, toil and physical effort, whereas the Other is seen to live a life as banker and speculator, living in splendour and with ease. The Volksgenosse aspires that life for himself. The Volksgenosse thus speculates in death and banks the extracted gold teeth. For the Volksgenossen, the Jews ‘are the scapegoats not only for individual manoeuvres and machinations but in a broader sense, inasmuch as the economic injustice of the whole class is attributed to them’.52 Pogroms are not only conceived as a liberating action but also as a moral obligation: Antisemitism calls for a ‘just’ revenge on the part of the ‘victimized’ national community against the powers of ‘rootless’ society. ‘Community’ is seen to be both victimized and ‘strong’. Strength is derived from the mythical-natural conception of the national being. This naturalization of community finds legitimation for murder in the naturalization of the ‘action’: nature is conceived as a destiny. Antisemitism’s stigmatization of reason and money as evil not only mythologizes reason and money as forces that come, like their projected personification, the Jew, from nowhere, it also produces the legend that those with a ‘home’, ‘tradition’, ‘roots’ and ‘soil’ are the victims of some abstract, intangible economic forces. The insight that ‘the constitution of the world occurs behind the backs of the individuals, yet it is their work’ is turned against itself: antisemites agree that the world makes itself manifest behind the backs of what they consider as the folk.53 Yet, they deny that it is their work. Instead, it is a world of evil global forces conspiring to undermine the relations of national harmony, based on ancestry, tradition and blood, and industry. The evil force is personified in the category ‘Jew’. In the struggle between ‘good’ and ‘evil’ reconciliation appears neither possible nor desirable. Evil needs to be eradicated in order for the ‘good’ to be set free, and in this effort of national

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 207

2/19/2014 3:46:14 PM

208

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

liberation from the global disharmonies of finance and money, and perceived imperial dictate, the fury of resentment unfetters all irrational powers – ‘a movement that ends with the total functionalization of the mind.’54 Kant’s notion that reason was to lead mankind to maturity formulated reason’s claim to think beyond itself in order to find deliverance in significance and meaning, in humanity. This is reason’s revolutionary imperative. Reason entails critical thought and judgement, intelligence and cunning, reflection and subversion. Reason has no price and cannot be priced. It is therefore rightly viewed with suspicion. It asks about the social purposes of a world governed by the movement of economic quantities and the microeconomic organization of living labour as an economic resource without discernible qualities, that is, a standardized and yet flexible human factor of production that is entirely employable whatever the ‘product’. Under the spell of a time made abstract, difference manifests a difference in quantity only and it is because of this measure of success that reason appears as the unreason [Unwesen] of a world that is ‘hostile to the subject’.55 All social labour-time is identical in the form of money for as long as it is performed within the time of profit, and if it is not, then it has no value, and the labour put into it is invalid. The time of profit is the time of economic success, measured by the rate of return. Effort counts as quantifiable effort only. Everything is assessed for use, what remains is burned. The efficient organization and the cold, dispassionate execution of the deed – the cruelty of silence in the house of the hangman – is mirrored by its disregard for individuality: corpses all look the same when counting the results and they have become truly equal to each other; and nothing distinguishes a number from a number except the difference in quantity – the measure of success. How long did it take? What did it cost? ‘The morbid aspect of anti-Semitism is not projective behaviour as such, but the absence from it of reflection.’56 In a world governed by the movement of economic quantities, quantitative expansion is the measure of success. In terms of quality, one quantity is the same as any other quantity, except that one is greater than the other. In this context, Adorno has argued that ‘Auschwitz confirmed the philosopheme of pure identity as death’.57 What remained was burned. Auschwitz, then, confirms the ‘stubbornness’ of the principle of ‘abstraction’ not only through extermination for extermination’s sake but also, and because of it, through ‘abstractification’. The naturalization of the abstract as ‘Jew’ denied not only humanity, as the ‘Jew’ stands expelled from the imagined national community. The abstract is also made abstract: all that can be used is used like teeth, hair, skin; labour-power and, finally, the abstract is made abstract and thus invisible. The invisible hand of the market, identified as the personalized power of the ‘Jew’, is transformed into smoke-filled air.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 208

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

209

On antisemitism, finance and industry Nazi antisemitism is different from the antisemitism of the old Christian world. This does not mean that it did not exploit Christian antisemitism, which accused the ‘Jew’ as the assassin of Jesus and as a trafficker in money. Modern antisemitism uses and exploits these historical constructions and transforms them: The Jew stands accused and is persecuted for following unproductive activities. His image is that of an intellectual and banker. ‘Bankers and intellectuals, money and mind, the exponents of circulation, form the impossible ideal of those who have been maimed by domination, an image used by domination to perpetuate itself.’58 The terms ‘abstract, rationalist, intellectual . . . take a pejorative sense; it could not be otherwise, since the anti-Semite lays claim to a concrete and irrational possession of the values of the nation.’59 The abstract values themselves are naturalized and identified as ‘Jew’. Both, thus, the ‘concrete’ and the ‘abstract’ are naturalized: one through the possession of land (the concrete as rooted in nature, blood and tradition) and the other through the possession of ‘poison’ (the abstract as the rootless and thus uprooting power of intelligence and money). The myth of the national unity of a frugal and industrious people is counterpoised to the myth of a Jewish capitalism of money making. The elements of antisemitism comprise, on the one hand, the condemnation of financial capitalism as a world-market reality of effortless wealth. Here speculators reign supreme in reckless pursuit of more money; and money chases money in a manner akin to incest: money invests into itself seeking to make more money out of money whatever the cost to national industry and national employment. In the borderless world of price and profit, the national economy is under the compulsion of the ruthless forces of money and finance. On the other hand, the elements of antisemitism comprise the endorsement of productive capital as a material force and foundation of national wealth, which characterizes the creative and industrious traditions of a national people. Capitalism is thus rejected as a ‘Jewish’ rentier capitalism that akin to a parasite, lives by coining the productive effort of a hard-working people, on the pain of national ruin. The elements of modern antisemitism distinguish between a natural form of capitalism, in which labour produces material wealth, and an abstract form of capitalism, in which money instantiates its own expansion ostensibly by betting on the creative power of national industry and national wealth, seemingly gambling it away. Nothing stands to reason. The ‘muck of ages’ is turned into resentment, and is thus affirmed as the national destiny that is ready for action.60 In response to the merciless ‘Jew’, it shows no mercy, and seeks deliverance. Tradition, soil and blood is counterpoised to reasoning, intelligence, self-reflection; and

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 209

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

210

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

in the nationalist view, national economy and the industrious labour of a hard– working, creative people are counterpoised to the abstract forces of international finance and imperialism. The Volksgenossen are thus equal in blindness. ‘AntiSemitic behaviour is generated in situations where blinded men robbed of their subjectivity are set loose as subjects.’61 While reason subsists in and through the critique of social relations, the Volksgenosse has faith only in the efficiently unleashed terror that robs the identified subject of the hated forms of capitalism of everything they have – cloth, shoes, teeth, hair, skin, life. The collection of gold teeth from those murdered, the collection of hair from those to be killed and the overseeing of the slave labour of those allowed to walk on their knees for no more than another day, only requires effective organization. Time is of the essence and there is thus no time to waste. Antisemitism articulates a senseless, barbaric rejection of capitalism that makes anti-capitalism useful for capitalism. It holds the Jew responsible for the fateful movements of economic things, and attacks the identified culprit. The antisemitic fury against (Jewish) capitalism leaves the established economy of labour entirely untouched. In fact, it demands its efficient and effective employment so as to liberate the world from the perceived wrongdoers who hide behind the abstract phenomena of money, finance and thought. Nazi antisemitism demands a well-organized rebellion of suppressed nature. It maims and kills with a cool head and stubborn effort. Its denunciation of capitalism as ‘Jewish capitalism’ allowed, indeed demands, the relentless development of capitalist enterprise as a national good while seemingly rejecting capitalism as a system of finance, money-grabbing speculation and accumulation of parasitic wealth. The critique of capitalism as ‘Jewish capitalism’ views capitalism as in fact nothing more than an unproductive money-making system – a rentier economy that lives off and thereby undermines the presumed national harmony of a community of natural people. The rebellion against capitalism asserts itself thus as a rebellion for a greater productive effort in the name of national economy and national wealth. Marx’s critique of commodity fetishism is robust in its critique of this dualist conception of labour and money. Labour produces value and value becomes visible in the money form; and labour is either productive of exchange value or it is not; and if it is not, the consequences are devastating. The seeming dualism between labour and money is the objective delusion of the commodity form.62 On the one hand, there is the fetish-like endorsement of concrete labour, creative enterprise and industry, producing the material wealth that satisfies human needs. On the other hand, there is the abstract sphere of reified economic things that seemingly move on their own volition, according to some innate economic logic that asserts itself beyond human control. Between the concrete labour of industry and the movement of abstract economic forces, the global power of finance calls the shots. The

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 210

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

211

celebration of the concrete goes hand-in-hand with the rejection of the mobility, universality and intangibility of finance capital, of the parasitic wealth of speculators. The vampire-like figure of capital sucking labour in the quest for more surplus value, portrayed by Marx in Capital, is thus displaced: capitalist production is deemed intrinsically good as a creative industrial endeavour of the concrete labour of the nation, and it is the power of money alone, in and of itself, that corrupts and degrades this labour for the sake of money-making. Money threatens the viability of this labour and money is thus conceived as the root of all evil and the cause of all perversion. That is, the dualist conception of money and labour fetishizes enterprise and industry as the embodiment of a concrete national community, which is threatened with destruction by the rootless power of money. In sum, modern antisemitism is the barbaric ideology of what Marx described in his analysis of the role of credit as the ‘abolition of the capitalist mode of production within the capitalist mode of production itself’.63 National Socialism focused the resolution of this perverted abolition on the national state as the ‘harmonies’ last refuge’ that restored the imagined natural order of society by terrorist means.64 For the antisemites, then, the world appears to be divided between hated forms of capitalism, especially finance and money capital, and concrete nature. The concrete is conceived as immediate, direct, matter for use and rooted in industry and productive activity. Money, on the other hand, is not only conceived as the root of all evil, it is also judged as rootless and of existing not only independently of industrial capital but also over and against it: all enterprise is seen to be perverted in the name of money’s destructive quest for self-expansion. In this way, money and financial capital are identified with capitalism while industry and productive labour are perceived as constituting the concrete and creative enterprise of a national community. Thus, industry and enterprise are ‘made’ capitalist by (Jewish) money: money penetrates all expressions of industry and thus perverts and disintegrates the community of the people in the name of finance capital’s abstract values. The force and power of money is seen to undermine the individual as entrepreneur; the creative in terms of national industry; the rooted in terms of the imagined traditions of blood and soil; the community in terms of a paternalist direction of use-value production. For the antisemites, then, it is possible not only to embrace capitalism but also to declare that labour creates freedom. ‘They declared that work was not degrading, so as to control the others more rationally. They claimed to be creative workers, but in reality they were still the grasping overlords of former times.’65 By separating what fundamentally belongs together, that is production and money, the differentiation between money, on the one hand, and industry and enterprise, on the other, amounts to a fetish critique of capital that, by attacking the projected personifications of capital, seeks its unfettered expansion by any means.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 211

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

212

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

The approval of the Volksgenosse as the personification of concrete nature, blood, soil and industry, goes hand in hand with the denunciation of the Jew as the personalized power of economic abstractions. In this way, the ideology of blood and soil, on the one hand, and machinery and unfettered industrial expansion, on the other, are projected as images of a healthy nation that stands ready to purge itself from the perceived enemies of the national economy, that is, the abstract, universal, rootless, mobile, intangible, international ‘vampire’ of ‘Jewish capitalism’. Extermination is itself an effort of concrete nature, and thus industrialized. Extermination manifests ‘the stubbornness of the life to which one has to conform, and to resign oneself’.66 As Volksgenossen they have all committed the same deed and have thus become truly equal to each other: their efficiently discharged occupation only confirmed what they already knew, they had lost their individuality and had instead been set loose as a hard working subject of extermination. Everything is thus changed into pure nature. The abstract was not only personified, it was also ‘abstractified’. At the gate of Auschwitz, the Volksgenossen made clear that money does not liberate anybody from concrete nature. Labour is liberating. It makes you free – Arbeit macht frei. That is, Auschwitz was a factory to destroy the personification of the abstract. Its organization was that of a fiendish industrial process, the aim of which was to ‘liberate’ the concrete from the abstract. The first step was to dehumanize, that is, to strip away the ‘mask’ of humanity, of qualitative specificity, and reveal the Jews for what ‘they really are’ – shadows, ciphers, numbered abstraction. Then followed the process to ‘eradicate that abstractness, to transform it into smoke, trying in the process to wrest away the last remnants of the concrete material “use-values”: clothes, gold, hair, soap’.67

Conclusion: Society in critical and theological perspectives Adam Smith was certain in his own mind that capitalism creates the wealth of nations and noted that the proprietor of stock is properly a citizen of the world, and is not necessarily attached to any particular country. He would be apt to abandon the country in which he was exposed to a vexatious inquisition, in order to

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 212

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

213

be assessed to a burdensome tax, and would remove his stock to some other country where he could either carry on his business, or enjoy his fortune more at his ease.68 David Ricardo concurred, adding that ‘if a capital is not allowed to get the greatest net revenue that the use of machinery will afford here, it will be carried abroad’ leading to ‘serious discouragement to the demand for labour’.69 He thus also formulated the necessity of capitalist social relations to produce ‘redundant population’. According to Hegel, the accumulation of wealth renders those who depend on the sale of their labour power for their social reproduction, insecure in deteriorating conditions. He concluded that despite the accumulation of wealth, bourgeois society will find it most difficult to keep the dependent masses pacified, and he saw the form of the state as the means of containing social antagonism, curbing the rebelliousness of the dependent masses.70 For Karl Marx, the critique of the capitalist amounted to a critique of an economic character mask. He therefore demanded the critique of the real thing, that is, capital as the constituted form of the relations of socio-economic objectivity. Against the existing concept of formal equality, he argued that communism rests on the equality of individual human needs. John Holloway thus conceives of the class struggle in entirely negative terms as a struggle against a society that is founded on the existence of a class tied to work.71 Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer argued that antisemitism articulates a senseless, barbaric rejection of capitalism that makes anti-capitalism useful for capitalism. ‘The rulers are only safe as long as the people they rule turn their longed-for goals into hated forms of evil.’72 Antisemitism channels discontent with conditions into blind resentment against the projected external enemy within. That is, no matter what the Jews as such may be like, their image, as that of the defeated people, has the features to which totalitarian domination must be completely hostile: happiness without power, wages without work, a home without frontiers, religion without myth. These characteristics are hated by the rulers because the ruled secretly long to possess them.73 That is, the spellbound critique of capitalism is ‘functional’ for the perpetuation of the system of abstract wealth – it encourages a resentful anti-capitalism, one that identifies, condemns and attacks the rumoured wrongdoer, and one that therefore condemns itself to mere fodder in a system of wealth that depends on the ready availability of its human material.74 Antisemitism holds the Jew responsible for the manoeuvres of the invisible hand, and as

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 213

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

214

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

the projected personalization of capitalism, the Jew is condemned as the veritable agent of misery. The Jew is evil personified, and evil needs to be eliminated so that the world is free of evil, and thus cured of the idea of a life beyond free labour.75 Antisemitism is the rumour about Jews. The rumour picks up on the fateful and at times devastating movement of economic forces. It says, blame the Jew. Antisemitism is the resentful theology of anti-capitalism. It personalizes hated forms of capitalism, provides an outlet for discontent, and offers an enemy. Antisemitism is all-embracing – because it comprehends nothing.

Notes 1 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 92. Michael Heinrich, An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital (New York 2012), argues with similar purpose in Chapter 10, Section 2. 2 Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectics of Enlightenment (London 1979), p. 179. 3 Karl Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy, Marx Engels Collected Works, vol. 6 (London 1976), and Grundrisse (London 1973), pp. 239–89. 4 Marx, From the Preparatory Materials, in Marx Engels Collected Works, vol. 29 (London 1987), p. 487. 5 Peter Gowan’s Global Gamble (London 1999) is the most emblematic account of this view. 6 Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (Cambridge, MA 2000), pp. 149, 105. 7 Theodor Adorno, Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords (New York 1998), p. 118. 8 This part draws on Adorno, Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge 2008a), pp. 100–2. 9 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics. 10 Alfred Rosenberg, Der staastsfeindliche Zionismus (Munich 1938). 11 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 185. 12 There is of course a difference between the antisemitism that culminated in Auschwitz and the antisemitism of the post-1945 world. However, whether antisemitism persists because or despite of Auschwitz is, ultimately, an idle question. The terms ‘despite’ and ‘because’ give credence to the notion that Auschwitz, this factory of death, was in fact successful in destroying antisemitism, too. This view purports that antisemitism has not so much to do with society but that it has rather something to do with Jews. On the history of this idea, and its imprint on modern sociology, see Detlev Claussen, ‘The Dialectic of Social Science and Worldview. On Antisemitism

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 214

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

215

in Sociology’, in ed. Marcel Stoetzler, Antisemitism and the Invention of Sociology (Lincoln, NB 2014). Auschwitz is not an event in the historicity of bourgeois society. As I argued in Chapter 4, the past does not reveal the present. Rather, it is the present that reveals the past. 13 I return to this point below in Section 2. 14 Theodor Adorno, Minima Moralia (London 1974), p. 141. 15 See their ‘Elements of Antisemitism’, in Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectics of Enlightenment (London 1979). 16 Immanuel Wallerstein, After Liberalism (New York 1995), p. 78. 17 This point derives from Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 183. 18 As Pat Buchanan sees it, the crisis of American values is a consequence of the nefarious effects of ‘critical theory’ for which he holds ‘those trouble making Communist Jews’ responsible. Pat Buchanan The Death of the West (New York 2002). Buchanan is former senior advisor to American Presidents Nixon, Ford and Reagan. He is a distinguished conservative thinker. 19 Adorno, Minima Moralia, p. 141. 20 Or as Jean-Paul Sartre argues in his Anti-Semite and Jew (New York 1976), once the mob is assembled, Jews can be kicked without fear. 21 Herbert Marcuse, Negations (London 1988), p. 23. 22 Wallerstein, After Liberalism, p. 156, 23 Wallerstein, After Liberalism, p. 211. 24 Josef Stalin, Marxism and the National Question (New York n.d.), p. 8. 25 See Leon Poliakov, Vom Antizionismus zum Anti-Semitismus (Freiburg 1992), p. 47. 26 Perry Anderson, ‘Scurrying Towards Bethlehem’, New Left Review, 2nd series, no. 10 (2001), pp. 5–30, 15. 27 James Petras, ‘Empire Building and Rule: U.S. and Latin America’, in ed. Pratyush Chandra, Anuradha Ghosh and Ravi Kumar, The Politics of Imperialism and Counterstrategies (Delhi 2004), p. 210. 28 James Petras, The Power of Israel in the United States (Atlanta, GA 2006). 29 Alex Callinicos, An Anti-Capitalist Manifesto (Cambridge 2003), p. 107. 30 Alex Callinicos and Chris Nineham, ‘At an impasse? Anti-Capitalism and the Social Forums Today’, International Socialism (online) no. 115 (2007); http://www.isj.org.uk/index.php4?id=337&issue=115 (accessed 31 May 2013). See also Chris Harman, ‘Hizbollah and the War Israel Lost’, International Socialism (online), no. 112 (2006); http://www.isj.org.uk/index. php4?id=243&issue=112 (accessed 31 May 2013). 31 Alex Calllincos, ‘The Grand Strategy of the American Empire’, International Socialism Journal (online), no. 97 (2002); pubs.socialistreviewindex.org.uk/ isj97/callinicos (accessed 29 July 2010). 32 International Socialism, ‘Egypt: The Pressure Builds Up’, International Socialism (online), no. 106 (2005), p. 31; http://www.isj.org.uk/index. php4?id=90&issue=106 (accessed 29 July 2010).

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 215

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

216

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

33 See http://radicalarchives.org/2010/03/28/jbutler-on-hamas-hezbollah-israellobby/ and for her quoted remark see http://www.aviva-berlin.de/aviva/ Found.php?id=1427323 (both sources accessed 8 April 2013). 34 Slavoj Žižek, Welcome to the Desert of the Real (London 2002), p. 130. 35 Alex Callinicos, ‘The Anti-Capitalist Movement after Genoa and New York’, in ed. Stanley Aronowitz and Heather Gautney, Implicating Empire (New York 2003), p. 140. 36 For further discussion of this point, Werner Bonefeld, ‘Antisemitism and the Power of Abstraction: From Political Economy to Critical Theory’, in ed. Marcel Stoetzler, Antisemitism and the Invention of Sociology (Lincoln, NB 2014). 37 See Marcel Stoetzler, ‘On the Possibility That the Revolution That Will End Capitalism might Fail to Usher in Communism’, Journal of Classical Sociology, vol. 12, no. 2 (2012), pp. 191–204. 38 See Adorno, Minima Moralia, pp. 73–4. 39 Adorno, Minima Moralia, p. 56. 40 Gillian Rose, Judaism & Modernity (Oxford 1993), p. 5. 41 Žižek, Welcome to the Desert, p. 129. 42 Walter Benjamin, ‘Theses on the Philosophy of History’, in Illuminations (London 1999). 43 Anderson, ‘Scurrying Towards Bethlehem’. 44 Indeed, the thoughtless support for the patriotic anti-imperialist resistance does not recognize the feminists, socialists, communists and anarchists either. It recognizes the anti-imperialist resistance of, say, The Hezbollah, and what is not recognized can be removed from the face of the earth. 45 Ulrike Meinhof, quoted in Georg Watson, ‘Race and the Socialists’, Encounter (November 1976), p. 23. On Auschwitz and the (West-)German left see Detlev Claussen, ‘In the House of the Hangman’, in ed. Anson Rabinbach and Jack Zipes, Germans and Jews Since the Holocaust (New York 1986). 46 Sartre, Anti-Semite and Jew, p. 69. 47 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 172. On capitalist wealth as the vanishing moment of a time made abstract, see Chapter 6. 48 Marx, ‘Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right – Introduction’, Collected Works, vol. 3 (London 1975)’, p. 182. 49 Theodor Adorno, ‘What Does Coming to Terms with the Past Mean?’ in ed. Geoffrey H. Hartman, Bitburg in Moral and Political Perspective (Bloomington 1986), p. 124. 50 On the meaning of ‘economy of free labour’, see Chapter 4. 51 John D. Rockefeller Sr., quoted in Manning Marable, Race, Reform and Rebellion (Jackson, MS 1991), p. 149. 52 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 174.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 216

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

217

ON THEOLOGY AND REAL ABSTRACTIONS

53 Marcuse, Negations, p. 151. 54 Marcuse, Negations, p. 23. 55 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 167. 56 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 189. 57 Adorno, ‘What Does Coming to Terms with the Past Mean?’, p. 363. 58 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 172. 59 Sartre, Anti-Semite and Jew, p. 109. 60 ‘Only in a revolution’ can the social individual ‘succeed in ridding itself of all the muck of ages and become fitted to found society anew’. Karl Marx and Friederich Engels, The German Ideology, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London 1976), p. 53. For critical interpretation, see Michael Lebowitz, ‘Beyond the Muck of Ages’, in Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism (Aldershot 2005). 61 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 171. 62 The part draws on Moishe Postone, ‘Anti-Semitism and National Socialism’, in ed. Anson Rabinbach and Jack Zipes, Germans and Jews since the Holocaust (New York 1986). 63 Marx, Capital, vol. III (London 1966), p. 438, and see Chapter 7, Section 3. 64 Marx, Grundrisse, p. 886. 65 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 173. 66 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 171. 67 Postone, ‘Anti-Semitism’, pp. 313–14. 68 Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Indianapolis 1981), pp. 848–9. 69 David Ricardo, Principles of the Political Economy of Taxation (Cambridge 1995), p. 39. 70 See Georg W. F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford 1967), pp. 122–9. 71 John Holloway, Change the World without Taking Power (London 2002). 72 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, p. 199. 73 Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectics, pp. 185, 199. On the notion of a spellbound critique of society, see Chapter 3, 74 For an account of the functionality of social conflict, see Lewis A. Coser, The Functions of Conflict (London 1956). 75 On free labour, see Chapters 4 and 5.

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 217

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

9781441161390_Ch09_Final_txt_print.indd 218

2/19/2014 3:46:15 PM

10 Conclusion: On the elements of subversion and negative reason Notes from tomorrow The difficulty in conceiving of the society of the free and equal has to do with its very idea. In distinction to the pursuit of abstract wealth, of value in process, money in process and as such capital, and in distinction to seizure of the state, pursuit and preservation of political power, economic value and factor efficiency, and in distinction to the idea of labour as the natural necessity of social wealth and conception of the economic as an economy of labour, it follows a completely different entelechy of human development – it seeks the society of human purposes, universal human emancipation. The wealth of the communist individuals and the wealth of capitalist society belong to two different realities. For the society of the free and equal social wealth is free time. The time ‘for enjoyment’ (Marx), freely disposable time (Adorno), comprises the communist measure and form of wealth.1 For communism time is not money, equality is not an abstract equality before the law and the labourer is not a time’s carcass. Its metabolism with nature is not a means towards the accumulation of abstract wealth. Rather, this society of communist individuals is characterized by the equality of individual human needs, and the satisfaction of human beings. It recognizes humanity as a purpose, not as a means. The time of value and the time of human purposes belong to different worlds. The time of human purposes is the time of the democratic organization of the means of human existence by the community of the communist individuals themselves.2

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 219

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

220

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

The society of human purposes stands in opposition to all hitherto history. Its achievement entails that the progress of this history comes to a standstill so that society can be found anew.3

On the critique of the present Louis Althusser was right to argue that Man as such does not exist. Man as such does not do anything and Man as such is therefore incapable of alienating herself as a personification of perverted economic forms. In distinction to Althusser, Man is always objectified Man, and ‘it is objectivity which constitutes the subjective mode of conduct’.4 In the topsy-turvy world of capital, Man is a non-conceptuality, that is, the social individuals are governed by their own social product, which manifests itself in the form of an uncontrollable movement of economic quantities that assert themselves with blind force over the acting subjects. Yet it is their own world that prevails not only over them but also prevails in and through them. Economic nature is a social nature. Its reality is immanent to its own social context. Society manifests itself in the inverted form of economic objectivity. Objectivity is ‘the generic term for all relations, institutions, and forces in which humans act’.5 Definite forms of social relations comprise thus an ‘objective conceptuality’.6 In distinction to the traditional hypothesis of society as a manifestation of some general economic laws that ostensibly determine social development in the last instance, the critique of political economy, conceived critically, amounts to an ad hominem critique of the entire system of economic objectivity as the finite reality of determinant social relations. Instead of deriving the actual social relations from some hypothesized economic laws of nature, it develops the economic structure of society from the actual social relations.7 The view that ‘we can do no other than nature does’ naturalizes capitalist society, and accommodates to its supposed nature.8 In distinction, the critical intension of the ad hominem critique is to think against the spell of identification, cracking the economic things from within. It therefore argues that the economic relations manifest the objective necessity of the ‘prevailing relations of production’.9 The social individual depends for her life on the independent movement of the economic forces over which she has no control; yet this movement is not the doing of economic nature. It is her own doing.10 The actual social relations manifest themselves in the inverted form of a movement of real economic abstractions. Man receives from society what she puts into society. That is, the person objectifies herself in the economic

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 220

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

CONCLUSION

221

thing, endowing it with a consciousness and a will, and the economic thing subjectifies itself in the person as the ‘agent of value’. In the inverted world of Monsieur le Capital and Madame la Terre, the ‘individual subjects’ are mere ‘character masks’ of economic forces. They live under ‘the compulsion of the universal’, that is, the ‘law of value, which capitalism realizes over the heads of men’.11 The supersensible world, which is the world of real economic abstractions, encompasses the sensuous world of human social practice in ‘the fantastic form of a relationship between things’.12 It ‘degrades the individuals to its function’, regardless as to how much they may try to raise themselves above their own forsaken world.13

Affirmation and negation As a critical theory of society, the critique of political economy is devoid of affirmative traits. Rather than ascribing to society a natural essence, according to which the economic forms can be traced back to some origin in nature, it rejects ‘the thesis that society is subject to natural laws [as] ideology’.14 Akin to a fake diamond, existing society radiates with the false promise that, if planned well, the further progress of economic development will liberate the propertyless producers of surplus value from the harsh reality of their socio-economic position. Critical theory is critical on the condition that it resists this falseness, refusing to be taken in by a philosophy of progress that in its entirety is tied to existing social relations. It therefore refuses to ‘sanction things as they are’.15 Its conception of society is entirely negative: ‘to negate a negation does not bring about its reversal’ and were such a reversal to occur, it would merely prove ‘that the negation was not negative enough’. In short, ‘what is negative is negative until it has passed’.16 It therefore does not sign up to the idea of a progressive future.17 Instead, its ‘objective goal is to break out of the context from within’.18 There is no vantage point from which to launch the society of human purposes. Its reality is entirely negative, that is, what is ‘negative’ in revolution/critique does not harbour in it the notion of a teleological or progressivist ‘positive resolution’.19 The society of human purposes is not the hidden secret of the capitalist social relations. Rather, its hidden secret is the force of the law-making violence of expropriation that divorced the mass of the population from the means of subsistence, cutting the producer of surplus value off from the direct access to the means of life. The force of law-making violence appears in the form of economic compulsion, which facilitates the selling and buying of

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 221

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

222

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

labour power between equal legal subjects who exchange with each other in freedom from direct coercion. The interests of the sellers and buyers of labour power are not the same. Their civilized conduct is a political matter. That is, the state is charged with depoliticizing the relationship between capital and labour by concentrating the political character of bourgeois society. The state is no independent being. It is the political form of the bourgeois relationships of coined freedom. Its purpose is not negotiable. The political state is the state of social depoliticization. It policies the bourgeois form of freedom in the form of contractual relations between the buyers of labour power and the producers of surplus value as equal subjects of law, and money. Marx thus argued that the bourgeois conception of equal rights manifests the right of private property as a right of inequality.20 He therefore argued that all who live from the sale of their labour power ‘find themselves directly opposed to the form in which, hitherto, the individuals, of which society consist, have given themselves collective expression, that is, the state; in order therefore to assert themselves as individuals, they must overthrow the state.’21 The society of the free and equal organizes its ‘“forces propres” as social forces’, and therefore does not separate social power from itself in the ‘shape of political power’.22 Critical theory demands a praxis that fights barbarism and argues that in hell everything is hellish. Like Marx,23 it rejects the idea of revolution as a revolution for the freedom of labour as regressive, denies that bourgeois society contains within itself the necessity of human emancipation, opposes the notion of historical progress for the benefit of the working class as a ‘conformist rebellion’, a rebellion that, say, instead of ending slavery, seeks a new deal for slaves. Class is an entirely negative concept. The critique of class society finds its positive resolution not in better-paid and fully employed producers of surplus value. It finds its positive resolution only in the classless society. The notion of revolution as a revolution for workers expresses a theological idea. According to Lukács, for example, the worker can resist reification because, as long as he rebels against it consciously, ‘his humanity and his soul are not changed into commodities’.24 Reification thus does not affect the soul of the worker, as if the soul is not of this world but of divine origin. Lukács derives the revolutionary subject, he calls it the totality of the proletarian subject represented by the Party, from something that is entirely invisible – history however does not unfold according to invisible principles. Critical theory is not a theoretical expression of the soul of the social forces. Rather, it aims at these forces themselves, seeking their dissolution. That is, at its best, historical materialism thinks against the progress of history and, as such, it really ‘brush[es] history against the grain’ (Benjamin) so that the

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 222

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

CONCLUSION

223

negative reason of human emancipation does not become ‘a piece of the politics it was supposed to lead out of’ (Adorno). 25 History does not unfold. It takes no side. In fact, ‘[h]istory does nothing, it “possesses no immense wealth”, it “wages no battles”. It is man, real, living man who does all that, who possesses and fights; “history” is not, as it were, a person apart, using man as a means to achieve its own aims; history is nothing but the activity of man pursuing his aims.’26 These aims are not theologically determined, naturally founded or purposefully active. The purpose of capitalism is the profitable accumulation of abstract wealth for its own sake. The commune of human purpose is not an existing human purpose. Its reality is entirely negative. History appears as a linear sequence of events, from one battle to another and from this division of labour to that division of labour, culminating in the present. This appearance is real but by itself, devoid of meaning. What does it really mean to say that history is a sequence of events? Events of what, and what was so eventful? History appears as a transcendent force of progress only when one abstracts from it, leading to its description as a sequence of events, for which the terms ‘historicity’ provides the name. Historicity comprises the idea of history without history.27 That is to say, in order to comprehend history, one needs to ‘crack’ the appearance of history as a sequence of events.28 One needs thus to think out of history, out of the battles for freedom, slave insurrections, peasant revolts, the struggles of Les Enragés, working class strikes, riots, insurrections and revolutions, to appreciate the traditions of the oppressed, recognize the smell of danger and the stench of death, gain a sense of the courage and cunning of struggle, grasp the spirit of sacrifice, comprehend however fleetingly the density of a time at which the progress of the muck of ages almost came to a standstill.29 History does not lead anywhere; it has no telos, no objectives, no purpose and it does not take sides. At its worst, it continuous on the path of victorious progress under darkened clouds and smoke-filled skies. At best, its progress will be stopped. Such history has not been made yet, though it has often been attempted. In our time, this attempt is called communism – this attempt at negation that seeks to rid the world of ‘all the muck of ages’. For Marx, the struggle against oppression is the struggle of the last oppressed class, time and time again. The oppressed class does not struggle for the progress of oppression – this really is the business of the ‘overlords’ of history.30 The proletariat is the name of the oppressed class of our time. Marx says that it is the last class. It might not be the last class, though, and if it is not, then the continuum of history will not have been broken.31 That is to say, there really is no secret reality that points beyond the existing social relations of production. The resolution to the dialectical context of immanence is that context itself. ‘The whole is false.’32 The whole has to go.

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 223

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

224

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

On the difficulty of saying NO Only a reified consciousness can declare that it is in possession of the requisite knowledge, political capacity and technical expertise not only for resolving capitalist crises but also to do so ‘for the workers’.33 Its grasp of reality is entirely abstract and its assertion to know what to do is groundless. As a practical theory for action, its condemnation that capitalism produces deplorable situations is tireless. Deplorable situations (Mißstände ) are not the same as deplorable conditions (Zustände ). The dispossessed producer of surplus value is a condition of capitalism. In distinction, deplorable situations describe entirely avoidable socio-economic circumstances, be they the result of a chance development, government incompetence or hard-nosed classpolitics. As such it can be rectified by well-meaning political interventions that regulate capitalist economy for the benefit of the poor and downtrodden. The critical insight that the capitalist form of wealth is premised on a class of dispossessed producers of surplus value disappears from view, and what appears in its stead is the view that the situation of the workers can be overcome by means of state. It is thus suggested that the fateful movement of an economy, in which ‘the needs of human beings, the satisfaction of human beings, is never more than a sideshow’, can be resolved and transformed for good by well-meaning government interventions. This notion is ‘in great measure no more than ideology’.34 In essence, then, its protest against a really existing misery that blights the life of a whole class of individuals, is in reality a party political advert; it transforms the refusal to sanction things as they are into ‘ticket thinking’.35 Ticket thinking is ‘one-dimensional’. It feels the pain of the world and offers its own political programme as the means of salvation, with a claim to power. Ticket thinking proclaims ‘falseness’.36 It promises a world beyond misery amid ‘a pile of debris’ that ‘grows skyward’.37 Ticket thinking feeds on what it condemns. It condemns this miserable situation and that shortcoming with righteous indignation and an eye for power. It sniffs out the miserable world, from the outside as it were, and at best transforms the protest against capitalism into a political advertisement for itself. At worst, it radicalizes its stance into a moral crusade against the identified wrongdoers, with potentially deafening consequences. Benjamin’s theses of history say that the poor and miserable will not be liberated unless they liberate themselves, by their own effort, courage and cunning. Herbert Marcuse focuses the conundrum of this argument most succinctly when he argued that slaves ‘have to be free for their liberation so that they are able to become free’.38 Marcuse’s argument is to the point: to bring the progress of capitalism to a standstill and found society anew

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 224

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

CONCLUSION

225

requires a non-capitalist identity, and the difficulty of its conception is a simple one: such an identity does not belong to the present, which is a capitalist present. What really does it mean to say ‘no’ to a capitalistically organized mode of human subsistence and social reproduction? To say ‘no’ to capitalism is simple. But to say what the ‘no’ is, is difficult. For one, the ‘no’ is not external to but operates within that same society that it opposes. Like Marx’s summons of class struggle as the motor of history, the ‘no’ drives the negative world forward. It is its dynamic force. Furthermore, to say what the ‘no’ is compromises the ‘no’ insofar as it becomes positive in its affirmative yes to something that has no valid content except the very society that it opposes. The ‘no’ is immanent to its own forsaken social context. It has no independent reality and contains no teleological direction. There is no reality beyond the existent social relations.

On the realism of negation There is thus need for a realistic conception of the struggle for the society of human purposes. Class struggle has to be rediscovered as the laboratory of human emancipation. This struggle does not follow some abstract idea. It is a struggle for access to ‘crude and material things without which no refined and spiritual things could exist’. 39 What then is the working class ‘in-itself’ struggling for? ‘In-itself’ it struggles for better wages and conditions, and defends wage levels and conditions. It struggles against capital’s ‘werewolf’s hunger for surplus labour’ and its destructive conquest for additional atoms of unpaid labour time, and thus against its reduction to a mere time’s carcass. It struggles against a life constituting solely of labour-time and thus against a reduction of human life to a mere economic resource. It struggles for respect, education and recognition of human significance, and above all it struggles for food, shelter, clothing, warmth, love, affection, knowledge, time for enjoyment and dignity. Its struggle as a class ‘in-itself’ really is a struggle ‘for-itself’: for life, human distinction, life-time and above all, satisfaction of basic human needs. It does all of this in conditions (Zustände ) in which the increase in material wealth that it has produced, pushes beyond the limits of its capitalist form. Every so-called trickle-down effect that capitalist accumulation might bring forth presupposes a prior and sustained trickle up in the capitalist accumulation of wealth. And then society ‘suddenly finds itself put back into a state of momentary barbarism; it appears as if famine, a universal war of devastation had cut off the supply of every means of subsistence’.40

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 225

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

226

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

The existence of the social individuals as personifications of seemingly self-moving economic forces does not entail the reduction of social consciousness to economic consciousness. It entails the concept of economy as an experienced concept, and economic consciousness as an experienced consciousness. At the very least, economic consciousness is an unhappy consciousness. This is the unhappy consciousness of the struggle for access to the means of subsistence. It is this struggle that makes the oppressed class the depository of historical knowledge. Class struggle ‘supplies a unique experience with the past’.41 Whether this experience ‘turns concrete in the changing forms of repression as resistance to repression’ or whether it turns concrete in forms of repression is a matter of experienced history. ‘There has been as much free will as there were men with the will to be free.’42 The society of human purposes can be defined in negation only. In the struggle against a negative world nothing is certain, except misery itself. Nevertheless, uncertainty is also an experienced concept. Historically, it has assumed the form of the Council, the Commune, the Räte, the Soviet, the Assemblies and now the squares – from Barcelona and Madrid to Istanbul, from Tunis to Cairo, from Athens to Rio, from Buenos Aires to New York, and Beijing, too – this democracy of the streets, which, despite appearance to the contrary, manifests no impasse at all. It is the laboratory of the society of the free and equal – its validity is its own uncertainty.43

Notes 1 Karl Marx, Theories of Surplus Value, vol. 3 (London 1972), p. 252. Theodor Adorno, Gesellschaftstheorie und Kulturkritik (Frankfurt 1975), p. 43. 2 On communism as the society of communist individuals, see Herbert Marcuse, Soviet Marxism (London 1958), p. 127. 3 This insight is core to Walter Benjamin’s ‘Theses on the Philosophy of History’, in Illuminations (London 1999). The understanding of communism as the ‘end of the muck of ages’ that ‘founds society anew’ is Marx’s – Karl Marx and Friederich Engels, The German Ideology, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London 1976), p. 53. 4 Theodor Adorno, ‘Einleitung zum Vortrag “Gesellschaft”’, Soziologische Schriften I, in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 8 (Frankfurt 1997), p. 570. 5 Theodor Adorno, ‘Soziologie und empirische Forschung’, in Theodor Adorno, Hans Albert, Ralf Darendorf, Jürgen Habermas, Harald Pilot and Karl Popper, Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen Soziologie (Munich 1993), p. 84. 6 Theodor Adorno, ‘Drei Studien zu Hegel’, in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 5 (Frankfurt 1971), p. 209.

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 226

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

227

CONCLUSION

7 This is, in a nutshell, the argument of Chapters 2 and 3. 8 David Harvey, ‘History versus Theory: A Commentary of Marx’s Method in Capital ’, Historical Materialism, vol. 20, no. 2 (2012), p. 13. 9 Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London 1990), p. 354; translation amended. 10 On ‘cracking’ and ‘doing’, see John Holloway, Change the World without Taking Power (London 2002) and Crack Capitalism (London 2010). 11 Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 311, 305, 311, 199. 12 Marx, Capital, vol. I (London 1990), p. 165. 13 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 311. This part draws on Marx, Capital, vol. I, p. 92. 14 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 355. 15 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. xix. 16 Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 159–60. 17 See Benjamin, ‘Theses’, and Theodor Adorno, Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge 2008a) and Theodor Adorno, ‘Fortschritt’, in Stichworte. Kritische Modelle 2 (Frankfurt 1969), for a critique of the philosophy of progress. Progress has already been made: from one set of rulers to another (Benjamin). Adorno agrees and disagrees with Benjamin’s notion of history as a universal history of the victors. For Adorno, history appears as such a universal history by hindsight only. It feeds on the circumstance that the many attempts to crack its continuum have failed, and what failed vanished from the record only to appear in the form of a triumphal succession of one set of rulers to the next. For history to be made, its progress has to be stopped. 18 Adorno, Lectures on History, p. 407. 19 I owe this point to Richard Gunn. 20 On this, see Karl Marx, ‘Critique of the Gotha Programme’, in Marx Engels Selected Works, vol. 3 (Moscow 1970). 21 Marx and Engels, German Ideology, p. 80. For an insightful account of Marx’s conception of the directly social democracy of the communist individuals as the antithesis to the state-form of bourgeois society, see Miguel Abensour, Democracy Against the State (London 2011). 22 Karl Marx, ‘On the Jewish Question’, Collected Works, vol. 3 (London 1975), p. 168. 23 Marx, Critique of the Gotha Programme. According to Benjamin, ‘Theses’, p. 250, Marx attacked the Gotha Programme of German Social Democracy because he was ‘smelling a rat’. 24 Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness (London 1971), p. 172. 25 Benjamin, ‘Theses’, p. 248; Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 143. 26 Karl Marx, The Holy Family, in Marx Engels Collected Works, vol. 4, p. 93. 27 In Benjamin’s (‘Theses’, p. 254) judgement, the transformation of history into a science without history characterizes the ‘bordello of historicity’.

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 227

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

228

CRITICAL THEORY AND THE CRITIQUE OF POLITICAL ECONOMY

28 I use this phrase in reference to Holloway, Crack Capitalism. 29 The notion of thinking out of history rather than about history, derives from Adorno’s negative dialectics which argues that for thought to comprehend society it needs to think out of society. For him, thinking about society, or about history, amounts to an argument based on hypothetical judgements that treat society as an ‘as if’, leading to dogmatic claims about its natural character. 30 On this, see Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment (London 1979). 31 On this, see Werner Bonefeld, ‘Critical Theory, History, and the Question of Revolution’, in ed. Shannon Briscant, Communism in the 21st Century, vol. 3 (Oxford 2014); ‘Notes on Fetishism, History and Uncertainty: Beyond the Critique of Austerity’, forthcoming Isegoria. Revista de Filosofia Moral y Politica, no. 50 (2014). 32 Theodor Adorno, Minima Moralia (London 1974), p. 50. 33 Adorno, Lectures on History, p. 25. 34 Adorno, History and Freedom, p. 51. 35 See Adorno and Horkheimer, Dialectic and Theodor Adorno, Ästhetische Theorie (Frankfurt 1970), p. 377. 36 Adorno, Lectures on History, p. 28. 37 Benjamin, ‘Theses’, p. 249. 38 Herbert Marcuse, Der eindimensionale Mensch (Darmstadt 1967), p. 61. See also Werner Bonefeld, ‘State, Revolution and Self-determination’, in ed. Werner Bonefeld and Sergio Tischler, What is to be Done? (Ashgate 2002), p. 133. 39 Benjamin, ‘Theses’, p. 246. 40 Karl Marx and Friederich Engels, The Communist Manifesto (London 1997), p. 18. 41 Benjamin, ‘Theses’, p. 254. 42 Adorno, Lectures on History, p. 265. 43 On this see Katarina Nasioka, ‘Communities in Crisis’, Massimo de Angelis, ‘Social Revolution and the Commons’ and Massimiliano Tomba, ‘Clash of Temporalities’, all forthcoming in South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 113, no. 2 (2014).

9781441161390_Ch10_Final_txt_print.indd 228

2/19/2014 3:46:47 PM

Selected bibliography Abensour, Miguel. Democracy Against the State (Cambridge: Polity, 2011). Adorno, Theodor. ‘Spengler Today’, Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung , no. 9, 305–24 (1941). —. Einleitung zur Musiksoziologie (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1962). —. Stichworte. Kritische Modelle 2 (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1969). —. Ästhetische Theorie (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970). —. ‘Drei Studien zu Hegel’, in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 5, edited by Rolf Tiedemann (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1971). —. Minima Moralia (London: Verso 1974). —. Gesellschaftstheorie und Kulturkritik (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1975). —. ‘Reconciliation under Duress’, in Aesthetics and Politics, Theodor Adorno, Walter Benjamin, Ernst Bloch and Georg Lukács, 151–76 (London: Verso, 1980). —. ‘What Does Coming to Terms with the Past Mean?’ in Bitburg in Moral and Political Perspective, edited by Geoffrey Hartman, 114–29 (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1986). —. ‘Society’, in Critical Theory and Society, edited by Stephen Eric Bronner and Douglas Mackay Kellner, 267–75 (London: Routledge, 1989). —. Negative Dialectics (London: Verso, 1990). —. ‘Soziologische Schriften I’, in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 8, edited by Rolf Tiedemann and Hermann Schweppenhäuser (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1997a). —. ‘Seminar Mitschrift of 1962’, in Appendix to Dialektik der Wertform, Hans-Georg Backhaus, 501–12 (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, 1997b). —. Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998). —. Lectures on History and Freedom (Cambridge: Polity, 2008a). —. Lectures on Negative Dialectics (Cambridge: Polity, 2008b). Adorno, Theodor and Horkheimer, Max. Dialectic of Enlightenment (London: Verso, 1979). —. Towards a New Manifesto (London: Verso, 2011). Adorno, Theodor, Albert, Hans, Darendorf, Ralf, Habermas, Jürgen, Pilot, Harald and Popper, Karl. Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen Soziologie (Munich: DTV Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1993). Agnoli, Johannes. Die Transformation der Demokratie (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, 1990). —. Der Staat des Kapitals (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, 1995).

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 229

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

230

SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

—. Subversive Theorie – Die Sache selbst und ihre Geschichte (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, 1996). —. Faschismus ohne Revision (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, 1997). —. Politik und Geschichte (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, 2001). —. ‘Destruction as the Determination of the Scholar in Miserable Times’, in Revolutionary Writing , edited by Werner Bonefeld, 25–37 (New York: Autonomedia, 2003). Althusser, Louis. Lenin and Philosophy (New York: Montly Review Press, 1971). —. Essays in Self-Criticism (New York: Schocken Books, 1976). —. For Marx (London: Verso, 1996). Althusser, Louis and Balibar, Étienne. Reading Capital (London: Verso, 1970). Altvater, Elmar. Sachzwang Weltmarkt (Hamburg: VSA, 1987). —. Die Rückkehr des Staates? Nach der Finanzkrise (Hamburg: VSA, 2010). Arthur, Chris. ‘Value, Labour, and Negativity’, Capital & Class (25), no. 1, 15–39 (2001). —. The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital (Leiden: Brill, 2004a). —. ‘Subject and Counter-Subject’, Historical Materialism (12), no. 3, 93–102 (2004b). —. ‘Arbeit, Zeit, und Negativität’, in Kapital & Kritik. Nach der neuen MarxLektüre, edited by Werner Bonefeld and Michael Heinrich, 281–305 (Hamburg: VSA, 2011). Backhaus, Hans-Georg. ‘Between Philosophy and Science: Marxian Social Economy as Critical Theory’, in Open Marxism, vol. I, edited by Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, 93–132 (London: Pluto Press, 1992). —. Die Dialektik der Wertform (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, 1997). —. ‘Über den Doppelsinn der Begriffe “politische Ökonomie” und “Kritik” bei Marx und in der Frankfurter Schule’, in Wolfgang Harich zum Gedächtnis, vol. II, edited by Stefan Dornuf and Reinhard Pitsch, 10–213 (München: Müller und Nerding, 2000). —. ‘Der widersprüchliche und monströse Kern der nationalökonomischen Begriffsbilding’, in Emanzipation und Versöhnung. Zu Adornos Kritik der ‘Warentausch’-Gesellschaft und Perpektiven der Transformation, edited by Iring Fetscher and Alfred Schmidt, 111–41 (Frankfurt: Neue Kritik Verlag, 2002). —. ‘Some Aspects of Marx’s Concept of Critique in the Context of His Economic-Philosophical Theory’, in Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism, edited by Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, 13–29 (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005). —. Marx, Adorno und die Kritik der Volkswirtschaftslehre (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, forthcoming). Bellofiore, Riccardo and Fineschi, Roberto (eds). Re-reading. New Perspectives after the Critical Edition (London: Palgrave, 2009). Benjamin, Walter. Das Passagen Werk (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1983). —. ‘Theses on the Philosophy of History’, in Illuminations, edited with an Introduction by Hannah Arendt, 245–55 (London: Pimlico, 1999). —. ‘Critique of Violence’, in Reflections, edited by Peter Demetz, 277–300 (New York: Random House, 2007).

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 230

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

231

Bensaid, Daniel. Marx For Our Time (London: Verso, 2002). Bidet, Jacques. Exploring Marx’s Capital: Philosophical, Economic and Political Dimensions (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2009). Bologna, Sergio. ‘Money and Crisis’, Common Sense, no. 14, 63–89 (1993). Available at: http://commonsensejournal.org.uk/issue-14/ Bonefeld, Werner. ‘Abstract Labour: Against its Nature and on its Time’, Capital & Class (34), no. 2, 257–76 (2010). —. ‘Debating Abstract Labour’, Capital & Class (35), no. 3, 475–9 (2011). Bonefeld, Werner (ed.). Revolutionary Writing (New York: Autonomedia, 2003). Bonefeld, Werner and Heinrich, Michael (eds). Kapital & Kritik. Nach der neuen Marx-Lektüre (Hamburg: VSA, 2011). Bonefeld, Werner and Holloway, John (eds). Global Capital, National State and the Politics of Money (London: Palgrave, 1995). Bonefeld, Werner and Psychopedis, Kosmas (eds). The Politics of Change. Globalization. Ideology and Critique (London: Palgrave, 2000). —. Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005). Bonefeld, Werner and Tischler, Sergio (eds). What Needs to be Done? Leninism, Anti-Leninist Marxism and the Question of Revolution (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2002). Bonefeld, Werner, Gunn, Richard, Holloway, John and Psychopedis, Kosmas (eds). Open Marxism, 3 vols (London: Pluto Press, 1992–5). Braunstein, Dirk. Adornos Kritik der politischen Ökonomie (Bielefeld, Transcript Verlag, 2011). Callinicos, Alex. ‘The Anti-Capitalist Movement after Genoa and New York’, in Implicating Empire, edited by Stanley Aronowitz and Heather Gautney, 133–50 (New York: Basic Books, 2003). —. ‘Against the New Dialectic’, Historical Materialism (13), no. 2, 41–59 (2005). —. ‘Is Leninism finished?’ Socialist Review, January 2013, at: http://www. socialistreview.org.uk/article.php?articlenumber=12210, accessed 28 March 2013. Carchedi, Guglielmo. ‘The Fallacies of “New Dialectics” and Value-Form Theory’, Historical Materialism (17), no. 1, 145–69 (2009). —. ‘A Comment on Bonefeld’s ‘Abstract Labour: Against its Nature and on its Time’, Capital & Class (35), no. 2, 207–309 (2010). Charnock, Greig. ‘Challenging New State Spatialities: The Open Marxism of Henri Lefebvre’, Antipode (42), no. 5, 1279–303 (2011). —. ‘Lost in Space? Lefebvre, Harvey and the Spatiality of Negation’, forthcoming South Atlantic Quarterly (113), no. 2 (2014). Clarke, Simon. ‘Marxism, Sociology and Poulantzas’ Theory of the State’, Capital & Class (1), no. 2, 1–31 (1977). —. ‘Capital, Fractions of Capital and the State’, Capital & Class (2), no. 2, 32–77 (1978). —. ‘Althusserian Marxism’, in One Dimensional Marxism. Althusser and the Politics of Culture, edited by Simon Clarke, Terry Lovell, Kevin McDonnell, Kevin Robins and Victor Seidler, 7–102 (London: Allison & Busby, 1980). —. Keynesianism, Monetarism and the Crisis of the State (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 1988).

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 231

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

232

SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

—. Marx, Marginalism and Modern Sociology (London: Palgrave, 1991). —. Marx’s Theory of Crisis (London: Palgrave, 1994). —. ‘Class Struggle and the Global Overaccumulation of Capital’, in Phases of Capitalist Development. Booms, Crisis and Globalizations, edited by Robert Albritton, Makato Itoh, Richard Westra and Alan Zeuge, 76–92 (London: Palgrave, 2001). Clarke, Simon (ed.). The State Debate (London: Palgrave, 1991). Claussen, Detlev. ‘The Dialectic of Social Science and Worldview. On Antisemitism in Sociology’, forthcoming in Antisemitism and the Invention of Sociology, edited by Marcel Stoetzler (Lincoln, NB: Nebraska University Press, 2014). Cohen, Gerald Allan. Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defense (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978). Cox, Robert. ‘Global Perestroika’, in The Social Register 1992, edited by Leo Panitch and Ralph Miliband, 26–43 (London: Merlin Press, 1992). Cristi, Renato. Carl Schmitt and Authoritarian Liberalism (Cardiff: University of Wales Press, 1998). Dalla Costa, Mariarosa. ‘Capitalism and Reproduction’, in Open Marxism, vol. III, edited by Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn, John Holloway and Kosmas Psychopedis, 7–16 (London: Pluto Press, 1995). —. ‘Development and Reproduction’, in Revolutionary Writing , edited by Werner Bonefeld, 135–59 (New York: Autonomedia, 2003). De Angelis, Massimo. ‘Marx and Primitive Accumulation’, in Subverting the Present. Imagining the Future, edited by Werner Bonefeld, 27–50 (New York: Autonomedia, 2008). Debord, Guy. Society of the Spectacle (New York: Zone Books, 1994). Eagleton, Terry. Why Marx was Right (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2011). Engels, Friederich. Anti-Dühring , MEW 20 (Berlin: Dietz, 1983). Federici, Silvia. Caliban and the Witch (New York: Autonomedia, 2004). Ferguson, Adam. Essays on the History of Civil Society (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1966). Fine, Robert. Democracy and the Rule of Law (Caldwell, NJ: The Blackburn Press, 2002). Foucault, Michel. ‘Governmentality’, in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller, 87–104 (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1991). —. Biopolitics (London: Palgrave, 2008). Fracchia, Joseph. ‘The Philosophical Lenin and Eastern “Western Marxism” of Georg Lukács’, Historial Materialism (21), no. 1, 69–93 (2013). Friedman, Milton. Capitalism and Freedom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962). Friedrich, Carl. Constitutional Government and Democracy; Theory and Practice in Europe and America (London: Blaisdell, 1968). Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Hegel’s Dialectics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982). Giddens, Anthony. The Consequences of Modernity (Cambridge: Polity, 1990). Gunn, Richard. ‘Notes on Class’, Common Sense, no. 2, 15–25 (1987). Available at: http://commonsensejournal.org.uk/issue-two/

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 232

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

233

—. ‘Against Historical Materialism’, in Open Marxism, vol. II, edited by Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, 1–45 (London: Pluto Press, 1992). Habermas, Jürgen. Philosophisch-politische Profile (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1987). Hardt, Michael and Negri, Antonio. Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000). Harvey, David. ‘History versus Theory: A Commentary of Marx’s Method in Capital ’, Historical Materialism (20), no. 2, 3–38 (2012). Haug, Wolfgang Fritz. Vorlesungen zur Einführung ins ‘Kapital’ (Hamburg: Argument Verlag, 2005). Hayek, Friedrich. The Road to Serfdom (London: Routledge, 1944). Hegel, Georg W. F. Jenenser Realphilosophie (Leipzip: Meiner, 1932). —. Philosophy of Right, translated by T. M. Knox (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967). —. Die Philosophie des Rechts: die Mitschriften Wannenmann (Heidelberg 1817/18) und Homeyer (Berlin 1818/19), edited and introduced by Karl-Heinz Ilting (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1983). Heinrich, Michael. ‘Reconstruction or Deconstruction’, in Re-reading Marx. New Perspectives after the Critical Edition, edited by Riccardo Bellofiore and Roberto Fineschi, 71–98 (London: Palgrave, 2009). —. ‘Enstehungs- und Auflösungsgeschichte des Marxschen “Kapital”’, in Kapital & Kritik, edited by Werner Bonefeld and Michael Heinrich, 155–93 (Hamburg: VSA, 2011). —. An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2012). Holloway, John. ‘The State and Everyday Struggle’, The State Debate, edited by Simon Clarke, 225–59 (London: Palgrave, 1991). —. ‘Global Capital and the National State’, in Global Capital, National Sate and the Politics of Money, edited by Werner Bonefeld and John Holloway, 116–40 (London: Palgrave, 1995a). —. ‘The Abyss Opens: The Rise and Fall of Keynesianism’, Global Capital, National State and the Politics of Money, edited by Werner Bonefeld and John Holloway, 7–34 (London: Palgrave, 1995b). —. Change the World without Taking Power (London: Pluto Press, 2002). —. Crack Capitalism (London: Pluto Press, 2010). Holloway, John and Picciotto, Sol (eds). State and Capital. A Marxist Debate (London: Edward Arnold, 1978). Horkheimer, Max. Zur Kritik der instrumentellen Vernunft (Frankfurt: Fischer Verlag, 1985). —. Kritische und Traditionelle Theorie (Frankfurt: Fischer Verlag, 1992). Jameson, Frederic. Presenting Capital (London: Verso, 2011). Jay, Martin. The Dialectical Imagination, A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923–1950 (London: Little Brown, 1973). Jessop, Bob. Nicos Poulantzas: Marxist Theory and Political Strategy (London: Palgrave, 1985). —. State Power: A Strategic-Relational Approach (Cambridge: Polity, 2008).

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 233

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

234

SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

Jevons, William Stanley. The Theory of Political Economy (London 1888). Available at: http://www.econlib.org/library/YPDBooks/Jevons/jvnPE.html, accessed 4 February 2013. Kay, Geoffrey. ‘Why Labour Is the Starting Point of Capital ’, in Value. The Representation of Labour in Capitalism, edited by Diane Elson, 46–66 (London: CSE Books, 1979). —. ‘Abstract Labour and Capital’, Historical Materialism (5), no. 1, 255–80 (1999). Kay, Geoffrey and Mott, James. ‘Concept and Method in Postone’s Time Labour and Social Domination ’, Historical Materialism (12), no. 3, 169–88 (2004). Kicillof, Axel and Startosta, Guido. ‘Value Form and Class Struggle’, Capital & Class (31), no. 2, 13–40 (2007a). —. ‘On Materiality and Social Form’, Historical Materialism (15), no. 3, 9–43 (2007b). —. ‘On Value and Abstract Labour. A Reply to Werner Bonefeld’, Capital & Class (35), no. 2, 295–305 (2010). Krahl, Hans Jürgen. Konstitution und Klassenkampf (Frankfurt: Verlag Neue Kritik, 1971). —. Vom Ende der abstrakten Arbeit (Frankfurt: Materialis Verlag, 1984). List, Friedrich. The National System of Political Economy (New York: Longmans, 1904). Lukács, Georg. History and Class Consciousness (London: Merlin, 1971). —. Marx’s Basic Ontological Principles (London: Merlin, 1978). —. Lenin: A Study in the Unity of His Thought (London: Verso, 1997). Luxemburg, Rosa. The Accumulation of Capital (London: Routledge, 1963). —. Reform or Revolution (London: Bookmarks, 1989). Mandel, Ernest. The Formation of the Economic Thought of Karl Marx (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971). Marcuse, Herbert. Soviet Marxism (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1958). —. Der eindimensionale Mensch (Darmstadt: Luchterhand, 1967). —. Negations (London: Free Association Books, 1988). —. Reason and Revolution (London: Routledge, 2000). Marcuse, Herbert and Schmidt, Alfred. Existenzialistische Marx-Interpretationen (Frankfurt: EVA, 1973). Marx, Karl. Marx Engels Werke (MEW) (Berlin: Dietz, 1956ff). —. The Eigtheenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon (New York: International Publishers, 1963). —. Capital, vol. III (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1966). —. ‘Critique of the Gotha Programme’, in Marx Engels Selected Works, vol. 3, 13–30 (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1970). —. A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1971). —. Theories of Surplus Value, vol. 3 (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1972). —. Grundrisse (London: Penguin, 1973). —. Marx Engels Collected Works (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1975ff.). —. Ökonomische Manuskripte 1857/58 , MEGA II.1.1 (Berlin: Dietz, 1976). —. Capital, vol. II (London: Penguin, 1978). —. Ergänzungen und Veränderungen, MEGA, II.6 (Berlin: Dietz, 1987).

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 234

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

235

—. Capital, vol. I (London: Penguin, 1990). Marx, Karl and Engels, Friederich. The German Ideology, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1976). —. The Communist Manifesto (London: Pluto Press, 1997). Menger, Carl. Problems of Economics and Sociology (Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 1963). Murray, Patrick. ‘Marx’s “Truly Social” Labour Theory of Value’, Historical Materialism (6), Summer, 27–65 (2000). Nasioka, Katarina. ‘Communities in Crisis’, forthcoming South Atlantic Quarterly (113), no. 2 (2014). Negt, Oskar and Alexander, Kluge. Public Sphere and Experience (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1993). Ollman, Bertell. Alienation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977). Pashukanis, Evgeny. Law and Marxism (London: Pluto Press, 1987). Perleman, Michael. The Invention of Capitalism (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2000). Pinkus, Theodor (ed.). Conversations with Lukács (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1975). Postone, Moishe. ‘Anti-Semitism and National Socialism’, in Germans and Jews since the Holocaust, edited by Anson Rabinbach and Jack Zipes, 302–14 (New York: Holmes & Meier, 1986). —. Time, Labour and Social Domination (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996). Poulantzas, Nicos. ‘Theorie und Geschichte: Kurze Bemerkung über den Gegenstand des “Kapitals”’, in Kritik der politischen Ökonomie, 100 Jahre Kapital, edited by Walter Euchner and Alfred Schmidt, 58–68 (Frankfurt: EVA, 1969). —. Political Power and Social Classes (London: New Left Books, 1973). —. Classes in Contemporary Capitalism (London: New Left Books, 1975). —. State, Power, Socialism (London: New Left Books, 1978). Proudhon, Pierre Joseph. What is Property? An Inquiry into the Principle of Right and of Government (Teddington: The Echo Library, 2008). Reichelt, Helmut. ‘Why did Marx Conceal His Dialectical Method?’ in Open Marxism: Emancipating Marx, edited by Bonefeld Werner, Gunn Richard, Holloway John and Kosmas Psychopedis, 40–83 (London: Pluto Press, 1995). —. ‘Jürgen Habermas’ Reconstruction of Historical Materialism’, in The Politics of Change, edited by Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, 105–45 (London: Palgrave, 2000). —. Zur logischen Struktur des Kapitalbegriffs bei Marx (Freiburg: Ç´a ira, 2001). —. ‘Die Marxsche Kritik ökonomischer Kategorien. Überlegungen zum Problem der Geltung in der dialektischen Darstellungsmethode im Kapital ’, in Emanzipation und Versöhnung. Zu Adornos Kritik der ‘Warentausch’Gesellschaft und Perpektiven der Transformation, edited by Iring Fetscher and Alfred Schmidt, 142–89 (Frankfurt: Verlag Neue Kritik, 2002). —. ‘Social Reality as Appearance: Some Notes on Marx’s Concept of Reality’, in Human Dignity. Social Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism, edited by Werner Bonefeld and Kosmas Psychopedis, 31–68 (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005).

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 235

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

236

SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

—. Neue Marx-Lektüre. Zur Kritik sozialwisschenschaftlicher Logik (Hamburg: VSA, 2008). —. ‘Zur Konstitution ökonomischer Gesellschaftlichkeit’, in Kapital & Kritik, edited by Werner Bonefeld and Michael Heinrich, 232–57 (Hamburg: VSA, 2011). Ricardo, David. Principles of the Political Economy of Taxation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995). Robertson, William. A General History of North and South America (London: Mayhew, Isaac and Co., 1834). Robinson, Joan. Economic Philosophy. An Essay on the Progress of Economic Thought (New York: Adlin Publishing, 1962). Röpke, Wilhelm. The Moral Foundation of Civil Society (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 2002). —. The Social Crisis of Our Time (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 2009). Rose, Gillian. The Melancholy Science: An Introduction to the Thought of Theodor W. Adorno (New York: Columbia University Press, 1979). —. Judaism & Modernity (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1993). Rossiter, Clinton L. Constitutional Dictatorship. Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1948). Rubin, Isaak. Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value (Detroit: Black and Red, 1972). Rüstow, Alexander. ‘General Social Laws of the Economic Disintegration and Possibilities of Reconstruction’, in Afterword to International Economic Disintegration, Wilhelm Röpke, 267–83 (London: William Hodge, 1942). Sartre, Jean-Paul. Anti-Semite and Jew (New York: Schocken Books, 1976). Say, Jean-Baptiste. A Treatis on Political Economy (New York: August M. Kelly Publishers, 1971). Schmidt, Alfred. ‘Zum Erkenntnisbegriff der Kritik der politischen Ökonomie’, in Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie heute. 100 Jahre ‘Kapital’ , edited by Walter Euchner and Alfred Schmidt, 30–43 (Frankfurt: EVA, 1968). —. ‘Der strukturalistische Angriff auf die Geschichte’, in Beiträge zur marxistischen Erkenntnistheorie, edited by Alfred Schmidt, 194–266 (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1969). —. The Concept of Nature in Marx (London: New Left Books, 1971). —. ‘Praxis’, in Gesellschaft: Beiträge zur Marxschen Theorie 2, edited by HansGeorg Backhaus, 264–306 (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1974). —. History and Structure (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983). Schmitt, Carl. The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988). —. Politische Theologie (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1990). —. ‘Sound Economy – Strong State’, in Appendix to Carl Schmitt and Authoritarian Liberalism, Renato Cristi, 212–32 (Cardiff: University of Wales Press, 1998). Schrader, Fred Edmund. Restauration und Revolution. Die Vorarbeiten zum ‘Kapital’ von Karl Marx in seinen Studienheften 1850–1858 (Hildesheim: Gerstenberg, 1980). Schumpeter, Joseph. Das Wesen und der Hauptinhalt der theoretischen Nationalökonomie (Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot, 1908).

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 236

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY

237

—. Theorie der wirtschaftlichen Entwicklung (Berlin: Duncker and Humblot 1964). —. Geschichte der ökonomischen Analyse (Göttingen: Vanderhoek & Rubrecht, 1965). —. Capitalism, Socialism & Democracy (London: Routledge, 1992). Smith, Adam. The Theory of Moral Sentiments (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1976). —. Lectures on Jurisprudence (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1978). —. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1981). Smith, Tony. The Logic of Marx’s Capital (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990). Sohn-Rethel, Alfred. Warenform und Denkform (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1978a). —. Economy and Class Structure of German Fascism (London: CSE Books, 1978b). Stoetzler, Marcel. ‘Postone’s Marx’, Historical Materialism (12), no. 2, 261–81 (2004). —. ‘On the Possibility that the Revolution that will End Capitalism might Fail to Usher in Communism’, Journal of Classical Sociology (12), no. 2, 191–204 (2012). Tomba, Max. ‘Historical Temporalities of Capital: An Anti-Historicist Perspective’, Historical Materialism (17), no. 4, 44–65 (2009). Vanberg, Victor. The Constitution of Markets (London: Routledge, 2001). Von Braunmühl, Claudia. ‘On the Analysis of the Bourgeois Nation State within the World Market Context’, in State and Capital. A Marxist Debate, edited by John Holloway and Sol Picciotto, 160–77 (London: Edward Arnold, 1978). Wallerstein, Immanuel. After Liberalism (New York: The New Press, 1995). Watson, Georg. ‘Race and the Socialists’, Encounter, November, 15–23 (1976). Wright, Erik Olin. Classes (London: Verso, 1985). —. Class Counts (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997). Wright, Steve. Storming Heaven (London: Pluto Press, 2002). Zarembka, Paul. ‘Primitive Accumulation in Marxism’, in Subverting the Present. Imagining the Future, edited by Werner Bonefeld, 67–75 (New York: Autonomedia, 2008). Žižek, Slavoj. Welcome to the Desert of the Real (London: Verso, 2002).

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 237

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

9781441161390_bib_Final_txt_print.indd 238

2/19/2014 3:35:46 PM

Index Abensour, Miguel 227n. 21 abstract labour 7, 10, 11, 42, 43, 91, 98n. 56, 121–4, 137, 139n. 23, 140nn. 29, 34, 36, 141–2nn. 61, 68, 147, 152, 154 in context of systematic dialectics 126 as form of class struggle 125–6 physiological determination of 124 social form of 123–8 as substance of value 124–5 trans-historical treatment of 137 and value form 128–36 and concrete labour 130–2 and double character of labour 128–30 and free labour 87–95, 160, 171, 175 and real-time abstraction 133–6 abstract negativity 35 ad hominem critique 38, 39, 54, 62, 69, 220 Adorno, Theodor 2, 3, 8, 10, 14n. 19, 23, 37–9, 43, 46n. 42, 48n. 71, 49nn. 84, 93, 50n. 116, 55–7, 62, 63, 65–6, 69, 72n. 44, 86, 96n. 22, 101, 114, 120n. 77, 127, 138n. 7, 141n. 41, 165, 196, 198, 208, 213, 222, 227n. 17, 228n. 29 Dialectic of the Enlightenment 1, 48n. 84, 96n. 22, 138n. 87, 205 Negative Dialectics 4–5, 73n. 63 Agnoli, Johannes 13n. 13, 72n. 36, 75n. 109, 186n. 6, 190n. 77 Alliez, Eric 141n. 51 Althusser, Louis 22, 28, 32, 35, 46n. 42, 49n. 90, 50n. 116, 61, 99n. 69, 117n. 21, 120n. 74, 220

9781441161390_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 239

Altvater, Elmar 160n. 1, 161n. 7, 186n. 5 American Zionism 202 Amin, Samir 80 Anderson, Perry 13n. 14, 50n. 116, 202, 204 anti-capitalism and antisemitism 199–210, 214n. 12 abstraction and 205–8 finance and industry and 209–12 on critique of capital personifications 195–9 and society in critical and theological perspectives 212–14 anti-humanism, theoretical 28–9, 35 anti-imperialism 197, 201, 216n. 44 antisemitism see under anticapitalism Arthur, Chris 13n. 14, 15n. 41, 16n. 57, 50n. 121, 56, 88, 89, 123, 125–7, 140n. 34, 141nn. 41–2, 143n. 109 Auschwitz 198, 205, 208, 212, 214nn. 12–13, 216n. 45 authoritarian liberalism 191n. 86 automaticity, of inverted society 71n. 10 autonomization, law of 8–9, 84, 91 Backhaus, Hans-Georg 3, 7–8, 13n. 16, 47n. 46, 50n. 113, 74n. 91, 89, 98n. 56, 140n. 36, 188n. 41 Balibar, Étienne 30 barbarism 2, 12, 66, 204, 222, 225 base/superstructure metaphor 168–9, 174, 187n. 20 Beck, Ulrich 117nn. 22–3

3/4/2014 11:53:08 AM

240

INDEX

Beck-Gernsheim, Elisabeth 117n. 23 Bell, Daniel 25 Bellofiore, Ricardo 13n. 14, 132 Benjamin, Walter 14n. 23, 37, 95n. 2, 97n. 22, 187n. 20, 204, 222, 224, 226n. 3, 227nn. 17, 27 Bensaid, Daniel 141n. 51 Bentham, Jeremy 162n. 50 Bidet, Jacques 48n. 63, 120n. 73 Blanke, Bernhard 186n. 6 Bonapartism 166, 180, 182, 186n. 9 Bonefeld, Werner 15n. 42, 16n. 57, 73n. 60, 74n. 72, 75n. 108, 96n. 3, 117n. 22, 139n. 18, 163n. 73, 186n. 7, 187n. 20, 188nn. 41, 44, 190n. 77, 216n. 36 bourgeois society 66–7, 73n. 59, 109, 114, 118n. 43, 150–1, 160, 166, 178, 185, 187n. 13, 213 as uncivilized 167–8 Bowmaker, Simon 46n. 30 Braunmühl, Claudia von 161n. 16 Braunstein, Dirk 4, 14n. 19, 46n. 42, 165, 185n. 3 Braverman, Harry 126, 138n. 7 Brittan, Sam 25 Buchanan, Pat 215n. 18 Budd, Adrian 161n. 9 Burnham, Peter 161n. 9, 162n. 37 Butler, Judith 202 Callinicos, Alex 16n. 54, 31, 118n. 25, 202, 203 capital 115, 152–4 as autonomic subject’ of bourgeois society 66 as barrier to capital 157 as bewitching force 62, 115 competitive logic of 148 law of 86 personified 156 plethora of 157–8 and primitive accumulation 81 self-valorization of 113 as social relationship 154 see also capitalism capitalism 24, 27, 31–3, 117n. 19, 122

9781441161390_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 240

and abstract labour 121, 123–4, 138n. 1 casino 159, 163n. 70, 196 conceptuality of 56 critique of 4, 6, 9–10, 38, 41, 196 and exchange relations 61 hatred of 205 historical presupposition of 87 and labour 29–30 ontologized time in 133 and primitive accumulation 80 purpose of 223 and social relations 47n. 42 structuralist analysis of 29 see also capital capitalist wealth 9–11, 40–3, 60, 66, 88, 90, 102, 106, 110–11, 119n. 53, 200–1 globalization and 147, 150, 155, 156, 159, 160 time of 122, 125, 129, 130 Carchedi, Guglielmo 139nn. 18, 23 Carey, Henry 159 Charnock, Greig 164n. 77 civil government, establishment of 172 Clarke, Simon 32, 34, 44nn. 2, 4, 9, 116n. 16, 119n. 53, 159, 162n. 37, 163n. 61, 185nn. 1, 4, 186n. 6 class 10, 33 antagonism 9, 70, 92, 93, 107, 167 and classification 102–6 and competition 106–9 and critique 114–15 and labour and surplus value 109–14 relationship 59, 64 social 115 struggle 64, 101–2, 118n. 43, 172, 225–6 see also individual entries classical view 3–7, 9–12, 13n. 16, 14nn. 23, 30, 21, 22, 32–4, 37, 41, 71n. 12, 104–5, 109, 115, 128, 130, 136–7, 166, 168–9, 174, 188n. 41 Claussen, Detlev 214n. 12 Cohen, Gerald 14n. 23, 119n. 45

3/4/2014 11:53:08 AM

INDEX

commercial society 22, 169, 170, 171, 173–4 moral sentiments of 171 transition towards 33 conceptualization, significance of 56–9 contractual freedom 59, 107, 170 Coser, Lewis A. 217n. 74 cosmopolitanism 197 Cox, Robert 148, 160, 161n. 9 Cristi, Renato 191n. 85 critical theory, of society see under political economy, critique of Dalla Costa, Mariarosa 16n. 56, 95n. 2, 160n. 83 de Angelis, Massimo 80, 96n. 10, 121, 123, 125–6, 136, 141n. 42, 228n. 43 debasement 1 Debord, Guy 63, 127 democratization of society, danger of 180 demystification 60, 62 demythologization 38 De Vroey, Michel 122, 142n. 82 dialectics 15n. 33, 54, 67–9, 90, 95, 98n. 50, 115 and critique of political economy 67–9 negative 4–5, 11, 120n. 77, 228n. 29 objective 37 systematic 15n. 41, 88–9, 126 tradition dialectics 5–6 dictatorship and freedom 178–81 distributive justice 119n. 45 disunity and unity 60, 64, 107, 108, 109, 115 Dobb, Maurice, 138n. 11 ‘double character of labour’ 122–3, 128–30, 132, 137 doubly free wage labourer 86, 88, 93, 94, 111, 189n. 61 ‘dynamic within stasis’ 86 Eagleton, Terry 14n. 23, 34, 105 economic compulsion 59, 84, 106–8, 114, 119n. 43, 176, 206, 221

9781441161390_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 241

241

economic consciousness 226 economic freedom 169, 175–6 economic objectivity 23, 36–40, 168 economic rationality 24–5, 59, 188n. 44 economic theory and economic nature 22–8 significance of 21 Engels, Friederich 5, 14n. 30, 36, 42, 182 equal exchange law, as fiction 93 equivalence exchange, and money 3 essence, appearance of 63–7 Eucken, Walter 188n. 47 exchange value 3, 9, 38, 42–3, 65, 91, 122, 128, 129, 131–2, 134–5, 196, 210 existentialism 73n. 60 Federici, Silvia 16n. 56, 95n. 2 Ferguson, Adam 33 fetishism 197 abstract labour 137 of commodities 2–3, 37, 40, 44n. 1, 54, 62, 90, 91, 93, 122, 210 critique of 8, 39, 63, 210 and world market 152–5 financial capital 158, 211 Fine, Robert 186n. 6 Fineschi, Roberto 13n. 14, 98n. 50 Foster, John Bellamy 163n. 70 Foucault, Michel 187n. 30, 188n. 44, 189n. 66 Franklin, Benjamin 127, 140n. 29 free economy and market police see neoliberalism freeman and slave, comparison of 83, 97n. 32 Friedman, Milton 190n. 81 Friedrich, Carl 178, 180–1 Gambino, Ferruccio 119n. 59 Giddens, Anthony 90, 117nn. 20, 22 Gill, Stephen 147 Gindin, Sam 160n. 3 Glassman, Jim 82, 83, 87, 88, 96n. 10 globalization see world market governmentality 187n. 30

3/4/2014 11:53:08 AM

242

INDEX

Grollios, Vasilis 71n. 16 Gunn, Richard 75n. 108, 107 Habermas, Jürgen 14n. 20, 61, 73n. 54 Hardt, Michael 197 Harvey, David 31, 46n. 31, 47n. 50, 79–80 The New Imperialism 79 Haselbach, Dieter 191n. 86 Haug, Wolfgang Fritz 29, 32, 47n. 47, 139n. 23 Hayek, Friedrich 25, 61, 175, 181, 190n. 81, 191nn. 85, 92 Hegel, Georg W. F. 64, 119n. 43, 166, 187n. 13, 213 Phenomenology 44n. 1 Philosophy of Right 167 Science of Logic 89 Heinrich, Michael 5, 10, 13n. 14, 142n. 79 Heller, Herman 191n. 86 Hennis, Wilhelm 190n. 80 Hill, Christopher 99n. 62 Hirsch, Joachim 151, 186n. 5 historical materialism 36, 56, 65, 70, 139n. 27, 222–3 critique of 48n. 71 Engels’ view of 36 structuralist idea of 31 traditional Marxist conception of 37 historicity 37–8, 215n. 12, 223, 227n. 27 history 96–7n. 22, 223, 227nn. 17, 27, 228n. 29 as chain of causality 98n. 54 Hobbes, Thomas 204 Holloway, John 44n. 9, 47n. 46, 95n. 2, 118n. 43, 137, 185n. 4, 186n. 6, 213, 228n. 28 Honneth, Axel 73n. 59 Horkheimer, Max 4, 5, 24, 48n. 62, 49n. 84, 96n. 22, 118n. 43, 138n. 7, 185n. 3, 196, 198, 213 Dialectic of the Enlightenment 1, 48n. 84, 96n. 22, 138n. 87, 205

9781441161390_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 242

human practice 60, 62 sensuous 61, 63, 66, 67, 70, 195, 221 ideology, significance of 38, 55 imperialism, critique of 201–2 instrumental rationality 206 inverted forms 6–10, 15n. 42, 23, 25, 27, 35, 38, 40, 47n. 42, 53, 54, 57, 58, 62–5, 69, 71n. 10, 88, 98n. 56, 112, 126, 195, 196, 220–1 Itoh, Makato 121, 124, 137 Jameson, Frederic 15n. 34 Jay, Martin 14n. 20 Jessop, Bob 30, 47–8nn. 56, 66, 71, 116n. 16, 179, 185n. 1 Jevons, William Stanley 44n. 6, 45n. 30 Jojima, Kunihiro 26 Kaldor, Nicholas 25 Kant, Immanuel 208 Kay, Geoff 140n. 34 Keynesian political economy 44n. 9 Kicillof, Axel 123–6, 128, 137, 139n. 18 Kluge, Alexander 119n. 43 Krahl, Jürgen 15n. 13, 23n. 14, 94n. 143 labour abstract see abstract labour actual 133 and capitalism 29, 42, 83, 85 commodified 90 concrete labour 42, 43, 93, 122, 124, 126, 128, 129, 130, 132, 134, 135, 137, 140n. 29, 153, 196, 201, 211 division of 22–3, 33–4, 167 dualistic conception of, and money 210–11 free 87–95, 160, 171, 180, 212 liberal reward for 172 necessary and surplus 111–12, 156–7

3/4/2014 11:53:08 AM

INDEX

power 43, 65, 92, 94, 102, 106, 107, 109–14, 122, 176, 177, 186n. 6 productive power of 22, 33, 153, 155 social 30, 37, 54, 85, 98n. 56, 108, 113, 121, 130, 134, 135, 149, 150, 152, 176 standpoint of 3, 9, 37, 54, 55 and surplus value 109–14 trans-historical materiality of 29–30 types of 142n. 68 labour theory, of value 122 Laissez-faire 175, 188n. 44 see also capitalism Lapavistas, Costas 48n. 67 Lebowitz, Michael 217n. 60 Lenin, Vladimir 204 Linebaugh, Peter 99n. 62 List, Friedrich 162n. 31 Lucas, Robert 46n. 31 Lukács, Georg 13n. 4, 54, 55, 68, 71nn. 11, 12, 13, 16, 73n. 65, 118n. 25, 222 Luxemburg, Rosa 80, 179, 190n. 77 McChesney, Robert W. 163n. 70 Man 15n. 41, 34, 35, 56, 63, 65, 67, 69, 83, 153, 162n. 42 concrete 128 as economic Man 22, 27 in existentialism 73n. 60 as free labourer 89–90, 189n. 61, 214 as highest being for Man 38 image of 198 as member of definite form of society 39 as objectified Man 220 Mandel, Ernest 13n. 10, 138n. 11 Marcuse, Herbert 4, 73n. 60, 185n. 3, 224, 226n. 2 Marx, Karl 13n. 11, 15nn. 36, 42, 21, 23, 24, 27, 41–3, 55, 62, 66, 80, 83, 93, 97n. 32, 118n. 29, 119n. 59, 121 Capital 4, 6, 7, 15n. 34, 28, 32, 60, 82, 88–90, 107, 125, 140n. 29, 185n. 4, 211

9781441161390_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 243

243

Communist Manifesto 108, 151, 182 Critique 127, 135 critique of political economy 6, 34–9, 47n. 42, 97n. 22, 117n. 23 ad hominem 38, 39 reducio ad hominem 39 critique of Smith and Ricardo 36 critique of trans-historical conceptions of economic nature 38 German ideology 184 Holy Family 171 new reading of, and critique of economic reforms 3, 4, 6–10, 13n. 14, 15n. 41, 16n. 49, 39, 41, 82, 95, 138n. 1, 165, 175 Paris-Manuscripts 28 Trinity Formula 104 see also individual entries Meinhof, Ulrike 205 Menger, Carl 59 modern economic theory, conventional view of 34–5 money, as automatic fetish 66 moral sentiments 169–71, 173, 175, 180, 187n. 30, 189n. 66 moral sociability 171 moral support 202 Mott, James 140n. 34 Müller-Armack, Alfred 175 Murray, Patrick 31, 142n. 68 Nasioka, Katarina 228n. 43 nation state 148, 150–2, 159 see also world market negation and affirmation 221–3 difficulty of expressing 224–5 realism of 225–6 negative dialectics 4–5, 11, 120n. 77, 228n. 29 Negri, Antonio 62, 197 Negt, Oskar 119n. 43 neoliberalism 80, 166, 174–8, 188n. 44 American 117n. 22 Neumann, Franz 185n. 3

3/4/2014 11:53:08 AM

244

INDEX

non-cocentputality 56, 69, 220 non-identity 54, 69, 73n. 63 objectivity 3, 5, 10, 15n. 42, 54, 56, 58, 62–3, 65, 129, 132, 166, 198, 213, 220 of abstract value, time, and value 133 economic 23, 36–40, 168 irrationality 61 social 56 of social labour 135 value 132 Panitch, Leo 160n. 3 Pashukanis, Evgeny 186n. 6 perfect liberty, system of 169–71 personifications of capital 2, 3, 5, 6, 12, 27, 35, 56, 60, 61, 63, 84, 91–3, 101, 108–9, 113–14, 127, 135–6, 156, 177, 184, 195–7, 211, 220 perverted forms 7, 12, 15n. 42, 21, 23, 39, 40, 50n. 113, 54, 59, 62, 64, 66, 68–70, 84, 89, 92, 102, 108–9, 114–15, 158, 206, 211, 220 Petras, James 202 Picciotto, Sol 185n. 4, 186n. 6 political economy, critique of 6, 34–9, 47n. 42, 54, 97n. 22, 105, 108, 117n. 23, 122, 182–5 ad hominem 38, 39 appearance of essence and 63–7 as critical social theory 3–6 dialectics and 67–9 reducio ad hominem 39 social praxis and 60–3 society concept and 54–60 subversion and 1–3 political form and force of law 165–8 and neoliberalism 174–8 on police, justice, and moral sentiments 168–74 and political theology 178–81 Postone, Moishe 2, 3, 9–10, 29, 37, 48n. 60, 74n. 86, 90, 102, 105, 116n. 11, 118n. 24, 122, 138n. 1, 140n. 29, 163n. 59, 217n. 62 post-war political economy 147

9781441161390_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 244

Poulantzas, Nicos 28, 116n. 16, 118n. 24, 185nn. 1, 4, 186n. 5 practical humanism 28, 35 praxis 14n. 22, 222 social 53, 60–3 present, critique of 220–2 primitive accumulation 43, 70–82, 115 secret of 82–7 and value form and free labour 87–95 protectionism 151 Proudhon, Pierre Joseph 27, 36, 196 Psychopedis, Kosmas 16n. 49, 75n. 108, 98n. 50 Ptak, Ralf 188n. 44 racism 199–200 real abstraction 1, 6, 8, 9, 24, 25, 38, 39, 63, 66, 67, 70, 71n. 10, 90, 91, 96n. 22, 127, 132, 133, 134, 136, 137, 223 Realpolitik 188n. 44 reason, significance of 1, 67, 96n. 22, 137, 205–8, 223 Reich, Robert 151 Reichelt, Helmut 3, 7, 8, 10, 15n. 33, 16n. 49, 39, 44n. 1, 45n. 16, 50n. 106, 61, 73nn. 54, 63, 89, 120n. 71, 138n. 13, 140n. 29, 142n. 68, 165, 185n. 4 reification 2, 28, 35, 36, 54, 55, 57, 58, 63, 69, 70, 92, 222 and abstract labour 122 of consciousness 224 of economic categories, subversive of 38 ideology of 38 of time 133 and value 122 Ricardo, David 4, 22, 36, 122, 130, 137, 149, 213 Ritsert, Jürgen 116n. 5 Robbins, Lionel 34 Robertson, William 169 Robinson, Joan 24, 25, 26 Robinson, William I. 160n. 3 Röpke, Wilhelm 175, 180, 183 Rose, Gillian 14n. 22, 216n. 40 Rosenberg, Alfred 198

3/4/2014 11:53:09 AM

INDEX

Rossiter, Clinton L. 180, 181 Rubin, Isaak 121–2, 124–6, 137, 143n. 112 Rüstow, Alexander 175, 188n. 44, 189n. 61, 191nn. 86, 88 Saad-Fhilo, Alfredo 48n. 67 Samuelson, Paul 49n. 75 Sartre, Jean-Paul 215n. 20 Scheuermann, William E. 191n. 85 Schmidt, Alfred 4, 28, 34, 46n. 42, 73n. 60, 75n. 95 Schmitt, Carl 178–81, 190n. 77, 191n. 85 Schrader, Fred 140n. 29 Schumpeter, Joseph 25–6, 119n. 53, 179 scientific Marxism 28–9 Smith, Adam 12, 22, 33, 36, 57, 87, 97n. 32, 110, 129, 131, 162nn. 26 social antagonism 9, 60, 64, 114, 160 social autonomization 8 social constitution and political economy 21–2 economic nature and capitalistic anatomy 28–36 and economic theory 22–8 economic objectivity and 36–40 social individual 5, 9, 56, 60, 61, 64, 92, 99n. 69, 103, 120n. 74, 153, 175, 195, 217n. 60, 220, 226 appearance of 91, 115 in capitalism 38, 147 and value 63 social labour 4 social laws 34, 57 abstract 61 social life 54, 60, 91, 137 social objectivity 56 social order 160, 168 social praxis 53, 60–3 social reality 1, 27, 39, 122, 131, 132, 166 social relations 5–9, 22, 23, 27, 29, 34, 36–7, 40, 58, 91, 129, 158, 162n. 42, 182, 197, 220 autonomization of 116n. 11 and capitalism 47n. 42, 196 definite, critique of 37

9781441161390_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 245

245

depoliticization of 176, 185 of exchange value 38 historically specific 30 humanization of 35 and objective conceptuality 220 real 54, 66, 70 disappearance of 91 and social reproduction 62 social reproduction 62, 66, 93, 117n. 23, 157, 196 social stratification 103 social wealth 33, 132 social world 63, 84, 91 socialism 31, 34, 68, 137 national 211 socially necessary labour time 128 Sohn-Rethel, Alfred 54, 65, 71n. 10, 185n. 3 sovereignty 181 Stalin, Joseph Marxism and the National Question 201 Starosta, Guido 123–6, 128, 137, 139n. 18 state see individual entries Stoetzler, Marcel 16n. 57, 216n. 37 Strange, Susan 158, 163n. 70 structuralism 29, 31, 48n. 66, 49n. 90 structuration 90 subjectivity 62, 63, 206 supersensible world 21, 44n. 1, 54, 61–3, 67, 70, 109, 129, 132, 141n. 41, 195, 221 surplus value 3, 43, 59, 66, 80, 87, 88, 150, 156, 158–9, 166, 176, 177 and equivalence 106–9 and labour 109–14 reconversion into capital 93 systematic dialectics 15n. 41, 88–9, 126 Thompson, Edward Palmer 99n. 62 thought and reality, radical separation between 31–2 ticket thinking 203, 224 time, significance of 133 Tischler, Sergio 190n. 77 Tomba, Massimiliano 14n. 23, 228n. 43 totalitarianism 198

3/4/2014 11:53:09 AM

246

INDEX

traditional Marxism, renouncing of 13n. 16 traditional social theory 5–6, 67–8, 73n. 60 trans-historicalness 3–5, 9, 22, 24, 29–30, 35–8, 41, 47nn. 42, 56, 49n. 84, 87, 122–6, 128, 130, 137 Tribe, Keith 189n. 66 Trotsky, Leon 201 use-values 3, 30, 42–3, 65, 112, 122, 126, 128–35, 154, 156, 163n. 59, 196, 211, 212 validity, as social category 25 value 39, 61, 68–9 and abstract labour 122, 124–5 as capital 43 conceptuality of 82, 150 equivalence 131 exchange 3, 9, 38, 42–3, 65, 91, 122, 128, 129, 131–2, 134–5, 196, 210 form 8, 15n. 41, 126 and concrete labour 130–2 and double character of labour 128–30 and free labour 87–95, 160 and real-time abstraction of abstract labour 133–6 labour theory of 122 law of 47–8n. 56, 65, 90, 113, 147, 170, 183, 221

9781441161390_Index_Final_txt_print.indd 246

money and 64–5 perverted form of 66, 132 phantom-like objectivity of 131–2 as sensuous, supersensible thing 62 and social individuals 63 use- 3, 30, 42–3, 65, 112, 122, 126, 128–35, 154, 156, 163n. 59, 196, 211, 212 and utility 46n. 30 valorization of 106, 109, 150, 155, 157, 175–6 world-market movement and 154 Vercellone, Carlo 118n. 24 Vincent, Jean-Marie 138n. 7 Volksgenosse/ Volksgenossen 207, 210, 212 von Mises, Ludwig 188n. 44 Wallerstein, Immanuel 201 Washington consensus 197 Weber, Max 119n. 45, 204 world market 147–8 and crises 155–9 and fetishism 152–5 and society 148–52 worldview Marxism 5, 35, 55 Wright, Steve 185n. 4 Wright, Erik Olin 118n. 24 Zarembka, Paul 95n. 1 Žižek, Slavoj 202–3

3/4/2014 11:53:09 AM