139 121 6MB
English Pages 245 [250] Year 1982
LONDON MATHEMATICA-L SOCIETY' LECTURE NOTE SERIES Managing Editor:
Professor I.M.James,
Mathematical Institute, 24-29 St Giles, Oxford
1.
General cohomology theory and !(-theory, p. HILTON
4~
Algebraic topology:
5.
Commutative algebra, J.T.KN!GHT
a student's guide, J.F.ADAMS
B.
Integration and harmonic analysis on compact groups, R.E.EDWARDS
9.
Elliptic functions and elliptic curves, P.DU VAL
10. 11.
Numerical ranges II, F.F.BONSALL & J.DUNCA.N
New developments in topology, G. SEGAL ( ed.)
12.
Symposium on complex analysis, Canterbury, 1973, J.CLUNIE & W.K.HAY'MAN (eds.)
13.
Combinatorics: T.P.McDONOUGH
14.
Proceedings of the British combinatorial conference 1973, &
V.C.MAVRON (eds.)
A.nalytic theory of abelian varieties, H.P.F.SWINNERTON-DYER
15.
An introduction to topological groups, P.J.HIGGINS
16.
Topics in finite groups, T.M.GAGEN
17.
Differentiable germs and catastrophes, Th. BROCKER
18~
A geometric approach to homology theory, S.BUONCRISTIANO, C.P.ROURKE 1ir B.J.SANDERSON
20.
Sheaf theory, B.R.TENNISON
21.
Automatic continuity of linear operators, A.M.SINCLA.IR
23.
Parallelisms of complete designs, P.J.CAMERON
24.
The topology of Stiefel manifolds,
25.
Lie groups and compact groups, J. F. PRICE
26.
Transformation groups:
&
L. LANDER
I.M.JAMES
Proceedings of the confer-ence in the University of
Newcastle upon Tyne, August 1976, C.KOSNIOWSKI
27.
Skew field constructions, P.M.COHN
28.
Brownian motion, Hardy spaces and bounded mean oscillation, K.E.PETERSEN
29.
Pontryagin duality and the structure of locally compact abelian groups, S.A.MORRIS
30.
Interaction models, N.L.BIGGS
31.
Continuous crossed products and type III von Neumann algebras, A.VAN DAELE
32.
Uniform alqebras and Jensen measures, T.W.GAMELIN
33.
Permutation groups and combinatorial structures, N.L.BIGGS
34.
Representation theory of Lie groups, M.F.ATIYAH et al.
35.
Trace ideals and their applications, B.SIMON
36.
Homological group theory, C.T.C.WALL (ed.)
&
A.T.WHITE
37.
Partially ordered rings and semi-algebraic geometry, G.W.BRUMFIEL
38.
Surveys in combinatorics, B.BOLLOBAS
39.
Affine sets and affine groups, D.G.NORTHCOTT
(ed.)
40.
Introduction to Hp spaces, P.J .KOOSIS
41.
Theory and applications of Hopf bifurcation, B.D.HASSARD, N.D.KAZARINOFF & Y-H.WAN
42.
Topics in the theory of group presentations, D.L.JOHNSON
43.
Graphs, codes and designs, P • .J.CAMERON & J.H.VAN LINT
44.
Z/2-homotopy theory, M.C.CRABB
45. 46.
Recursion theory:
its generalisations and applications, F.R.DRAKE
p-adic analysis:
a short course on recent work, N.KOBLITZ
47.
Coding the Universe, A. BELLER, R. JENSEN
48.
Low-dimensional topology, R. BROWN & T.L. THICKSTUN (eds.)
&
lir
S.S.WAINER (eds.)
P. WELCH
49.
Finite geometries and designs, P. CAMERON, J.W.P. HIRSCHFELD & D.R. HUGHES (eds.)
50.
Commutator Calculus and groups of homotopy classes, H.J. BAUES
51.
Synthetic differential geometry, A. KOCK
52.
Combinatorics, H.N.V. TEMPERLEY (ed.)
53.
Singularity theory, V.I. ARNOLD
54.
Markov processes and related problems of analysis, E.B. DYNRIN
55.
Ordered permutation groups, A.M.W. GLASS
56.
Journees arithmetiques 1980, .J.V. ARMITAGE
57.
Techniques of geometric topology, R.A. FENN
(ed.)
58.
Singularities of differentiable functions, :J. MARTINET
59.
Applicable differential geometry, F.A.E. PIRANI and M. CRAMPIN
60.
Integrable systems, S.P. NOVIKOV et al.
61.
The core model, A. DODD
6 2.
Economics for rna thematic i ans, J. W. S. CASSELS
63.
Continuous semiqroups in Banach algebras, A.M. SINCLAIR
64.
Basic concepts of enriched category theory, G.M.
KELLY
London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series.
64
Basic Concepts of Enriched Category Theory
GREGORY MAXWELL KELLY, F.A.A.
Professor of Pure Mathematics, University of Sydney
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS CAMBRIDGE LONDON
NEW YORK
MELBOURNE
SYDNEY
NEW ROCHELLE
Published by the Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 lRP 32 East 57th Street, New York, NY 10022, USA 296 Beaconsfield Parade, Middle Park, Melbourne 3206, Australia ~Cambridge University Press 1982
First published in 1982 Printed in Great Britain at the University Press, Cambridge
Library of Congress catalogue card number: 81-18015
British Library cataloguing in publication data Kelly, G.M.
Basic concepts of enriched category theory.-(London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series 64 ISSN 0076-0552.) 1. Categories (Mathematics) I Ti t1e. II Series 512'.55 QA169 ISBN 0 521 28702 2
Q_A/~
1
/ /(Lftf
!9tZ
To my wife and my children
TABLE OF CONTENTS page
Introduction
Chapter 1.
9
The elementary notions
1.1
Monoidal categories
1.2
The
2-category
1.3
The
2-functor
1.4
Symmetric monoidal categories; the t€nsor
21
V-CAT
for a monoidal
( ) : V-CAT --+ CAT
symmetric monoidal
V-CAT
for a
V
28
1.5
Closed and biclosed monoidal categories
1.6
V as a
V;
representable
Extraordinary
1.8
The
1.9
The (weak) Yoneda Lemma for
1.10
Representability of
V-functors
35
V-naturality
39
V-naturality of the canonical maps
object as a
Chapter 2.
33
V-category for symmetric monoidal
1.7
1.11
23 26
0
product and duality on
closed
V
43
V-CAT
45
V-functors; the representing
V-functor of the passive variables
Adjunctions and equivalences in
47 49
V-CAT
Functor categories V
54
2.1
Ends in
2.2
The functor-category
CA,BJ
2.3
The isomorphism
B,C]
[A®
for small ~
[A,[B,CJ]
A
58
61
page
2.4
The (strong) Yoneda Lemma for Yoneda embedding
A--+
2.5
The free
2.6
Universe-enlargement cases;
Chapter 3. 3.1
as a
the
0
[A P,VJ
V-category on a
[A,BJ
V-CAT;
65
Set-category
V c V'
68
in concrete
V'-category for large
A
69
Indexed limits and colimits Indexing types; limits and colimits; Yoneda isomorphisms
71
3.2
Preservation of limits and colimits
74
3.3
Limits in functor categories; double limits and iterated limits
3.4
The connexion with classical conical limits when
3.5
76
V
=
Set
81
Full subcategories and limits; the closure of a full subcategory under a class of colimits
85
3.6
Strongly generating functors
87
3.7
Tensor and cotensor products
91
3.8
Conical limits in a
94
3.9
The inadequacy of conical limits
3.10
Ends and coends in a general
V-category
V-category;
completeness 3.11
99
The existence of a limit-preserving universe-enlargement
3.12
96
V c V'
104
The existence of a limit- and colimit-preserving universe-enlargement
V c V'
107
page
Chapter 4. 4.1
Kan extensions The definition of Kan extensions; their expressibility by limits and colimits
112
4.2
Elementary properties and examples
116
4.3
A universal property of
LanKG;
its
inadequacy as a definition 4.4
Iterated Kan extensions; Kan adjoints;
[A 4.5
120
0
P,V]
as the free cocompletion of a small
V;
initial and final functors when
V = Set
127
Filtered categories when commutativity in
Set
V =Set;
the
of filtered colimits 131
with finite limits 4.7
125
Initial diagrams as the left Kan extensions into
4.6
A
The factorization of a functor, when
V
Set,
into an initial functor and a discrete 136
op-fibration 4.8
The general representability and adjoint-functor theorems; the special case of a
140
complete domain-category 4.9
Representability and adjoint-functor theorems when
4.10
145
V = Set
Existence and characterization of the left Kan extension along a fully-faithful K:
A --+
C in terms of cylinders in
to colimits by the
C(KA,-)
C sent
150
page
Chapter 5. 5.1
Density Definition of density, and equivalent 156
formulations 5.2
Composability and cancellability properties of dense functors
5.3
159
Examples of density; comparison with strong generation
5.4
Presentations of the density of a fully-faithful K
5.5
164
in terms of
K-absolute colirnits
170
The characterization of functor-categories 0
[A P,VJ;
small projectives and Cauchy
completion; Morita equivalence 5.6
174
Existence and characterization of the left Kan extension along a fully-faithful dense functor in terms of a density presentation; adjoint-functor theorems involving density
5.7
The free completion of
A
with respect to
all colimits with indexing-type in 5.8
178
F
182
Cauchy completion as the idempotent-splitting completion when
V
Set
5.9
The finite-colimit completion when
5. 10
The filtered-colimit completion when flat and left-exact functors
186
v
Set V
188
= Set; 190
page 5.11
The image under general dense
[K,l]: [C,B]--+ [A,BJ, K,
for a
of the left-adjoint functors;
examples and counter-examples 5.12
193
Description of the image above in terms of K-comodels; generalization to an equivalence Lanz
5.13
A
--1
dense
[Z,l]
between categories of comodels
K: A--+ C,
with
A small and
197
C
cocomplete, as an essentially-algebraic theory with 5.14
C as the category of algebras
The image under a dense
K,
[K,l]: [C,B]--+ [A,BJ,
for
of the equivalences;
characterization theorems for
Chapter 6.
202
C
203
Essentially-algebraic theories defined by reguli and sketches
6.1
Locally-bounded categories; the local boundedness of
6.2
V
The reflectivity in
in all our examples 0
[A P,VJ
of the category
of algebras for a regulus 6.3
213
The category of algebras for a sketch, and in particular for an
6.4
W8
F-theory; algebraic functors
and their adjoints
218
The
224
F-theory generated by a small sketch
page 6.5
The symmetric monoidal closed structure on the category of
F-cocornplete categories and
F-cocontinuous functors
228
Bib 1 i og ra phy
231
Index
239
Introduction (i)
Although numerous contributions from divers authors, over the
past fifteen years or so, have brought enriched category theory to a developed state, there is still no connected account of the theory, or even of a substantial part of it.
As the applications of the
theory continue to expand - some recent examples are given below the lack of such an account is the more acutely felt. The present book is designed to supply the want in part, by giving a fairly complete treatment of the limited area to which the title refers.
The
bcs~c
concepts of category theory certainly include
the notions of functor-category, of limit and colimit, of Kan extension, and of density; with their applications to completions, perhaps including those relative completions given by categories of algebras for limit-defined theories.
If we read "V-category" for "category"
here, this is essentially the list of our chapter-headings below, after the first chapter introducing
V-categories.
In fact our scope is wider than this might suggest; for what we give is also a self-contained account of basic category theory as described above, assuming as prior knowledge only the most elementary categorical concepts, and treating the ordinary and enriched cases together from Chapter 3 on.
(ii)
In order to include the enriched case we begin in Chapter 1 by
introducing symmetric monoidal closed categories elementary properties, and defining the
V,
2-category
examining Lheir
V-CAT
of
Introduction
10
V-categories,
V-functors, and
with the forgetful easy and brief.
2-functor
V-natural transformations, together ( ) : V-CAT---+ CAT;
this much is
0
Next, developing the basic structure of
tensor products of
V-categories,
V-CAT
V-functors of two variables,
V itself as a
extraordinary
V-natural transformations,
representable
V-functors, and the Yoneda lemma - requires verifications
of diagram-commutativity, whose analogues for trivial equations between functions.
V
V-category,
= Set reduce to fairly
This seems to be an inevitable
cost of the extra generality; but we have been at pains so to arrange the account that the reader should find the burden a light one. With this done, the discussion of representability, adjunction, and equivalences in
V-CAT,
which closes Chapter 1, is simple and direct.
The short Chapter 2 takes up the closed structure of given by the
~B,CJ.
V-functor-category
is to be an object of
Since the hom
V-CAT, [B,C](T,S)
V and not merely a set, more work is once
again required than in the
V
B is quite a simple limit in
= Set case. V
0
-
However this hom for small
now supposed complete - of the
special kind called an end, precisely adapted to the extraordinary V-natural transformations; and from this definition flow easily the desired properties. The indexed limits and colimits of Chapter 3, along with their various special cases, are constructs of the greatest importance even when
V = Set;
and the relations between double and iterated indexed
limits express a rich content. by their reducibility when
This impor_tance is scarcely lessened
V • Set to classical limits - any more
than the importance of these classical ones is lessened by their reducibility in good cases to products and equalizers.
Even in the
Introduction
11
V = Ab/ of additive categories, the indexed limits - although
case
here they e~st when all the classical ones do - are no longer
direatZy reducible to the latter; while for a general
V the indexed
limits are essential, and the classical ones no longer suffice.
V into a bigger universe,
Chapter 3 ends by showing how to expand
without disturbing limits and colimits, so as to allow the free use of functor-categories
[B,CJ with large B.
The remaining chapters 4, 5, and 6, dealing respectively with Kan extensions, density, and algebras defined by limits (or more generally by "topologies"), make use of these limit- and colimit-notions to complete the development of our chosen area of basic category theory. Most of the results apply equally to categories and to
V-categories,
without a word's being changed in the statement or the proof; so that scarcely a word would be saved if we restricted ourselves to ordinary categories alone. of a general
Certainly this requires proofs adapted to the case
V·, but these almost always turn out to be the best
proofs in the classical case
V = Set as well.
This reflects the hopes
with which Ellenberg and the author set out when writing Lawvere's observation in logic "applies directly [symmetric monoidal]
[54]
to structures valued in an arbitrary
closed category
certain results peculiar to the case
V "
Set,
V = Set;
there are of course and we accordingly
an occasional section to this case alone.
the commutativity in
and
that the relevant segment of classical
Because of the special properties of
devote
[26],
Some examples are
Set of filtered colimits with finite limits;
the notions of initial functor and of discrete op-fibration; and the
Introduction
12 classical adjoint-functor theorems.
We treat all of these for
completeness - partly to keep the account self-contained, and partly to compare them, where appropriate, with analogues for a general
V.
The little prior knowledge that we do assume is easily available for instance from
[60] - and to have included it here, with examples
to enliven it, would have involved an unjustifiable length.
increase in the
For Chapter 1, it consists of the basic notions of category,
functor, and natural transformation, including functors of two or more variables and contravariant functors; representable functors and the Yoneda lemma; adjunction and equivalence; and what is meant by a faithful or a fully-faithful functor.
From Chapter 2 on, we also
need the classical notions of limit and colimit; with the names of such special limits as product, equalizer, pullback, and terminal object; and the meanings of monomorphism and epimorphism.
In the
rare places where more is assumed but not expounded here, references are given.
(iii)
We now turn to what we have omitted from the present book; the
list includes many important notions, well meriting an extended treatment, whose inclusion would
howe~er
have disturbed the essential
simplicity of an initial account such as this. First (to return to the title), the basic concepts of category theory concern categories- in our case, objects of discussion. but
.V-categories -as the
These form, or live in, a
2-category
V-CAT;
2-categories are not yet the formal objects of discussion, any
Introduction
13
more than categories are when we study group theory. casts light on group theory, as does theory.
Category theory
2-category theory on category
Hence the step to this next level, where weaker notions of
natural transformation naturally arise, is an important one; but it is quite properly deferred pending experience of some particular 2-categories, and we do not take it here. aspects of it in the forthcoming
We make a start on some
[46].
Closely connected to this is our decision not to discuss the "change of base-category" given by a symmetric
V
---+-
V1
and the induced
V
induced by the canonical
V-CAT ---+- V 1 -CAT.
2-functor
we said, consider the forgetful --+
2-functor
Set;
monoidal' functor
( ) : V-CAT 0
We do, as
--+
CAT
but this is entirely elementary,
not involving even the definition of a symmetric monoidal functor. The general change of base, important though it is, is yet logically secondary to the basic
V-category theory it acts on.
properly needs a careful analysis of the
To treat it
2-category of symmetric
monoidal categories, symmetric monoidal functors, and symmetric monoidal natural transformations - including adjunctions therein and the dual concept of op-monoidal functor.
There is evidence in
[43]
that this itself is best studied in the more general context of categories with essentially-algebraic structure, which draws on the matter of this book together with
[45]
and
[46].
Since the natural setting for the important work of Day [14],
[16])
([12],
on the construction of symmetric monoidal closed
categories as functor-categories, or as reflective subcategories of these, involves the
2-category of symmetric monoidal categories,
this too has been omitted.
Introduction
14
One thing we particularly regret omitting is the theory of monads; it could certainly be seen as basic category theory, yet there was no convenient place to put it, and it would have required an extra chapter to itself.
Luckily, besides the account of Mac Lane
in the classical case, we have the articles of Linton [22],
and Kock
[51],
We also have the elegant
[57],
2-categorical treatment by Street
have been more closely studied.
[70], 2-categories
A consequence is our failure to
discuss the completeness and the cocompleteness of the of small
Dubuc
covering various aspects of the enriched case.
which provides some argument for deferring the topic until
V-Cat
[60]
2-category
V-categories - which is most easily referred back to
the completeness and the cocompleteness of the algebras for a monad. Finally, our account covers only what can be said for every well-behaved
V (except for those things special to V =Set).
Results valid only for a special class of
V are best treated in
separate articles, of which the author's forthcoming
[45]
is one
example.
(iv)
Our concern being to provide a development of basic category
theory that covers the enriched case, we have given illustrations of many of the results in isolation, but have not thought this the place to discuss detailed applications to particular areas of mathematics. In fact, applications needing the enriched case are rapidly proliferating; the following is a selection of recent ones that have come to the author's notice.
Introduction
15
The discussion of dualities in topological algebra, taking for
V
a suitable category of topological or quasitopological spaces, and
initiated by Dubuc and Porta
[23],
articles by Dubuc, Day, and Nel.
V
Kan extensions where
has been continued in numerous
Pelletier
is Banach spaces.
[67]
has made use of
Recent Soviet work in
representation theory (see the articles by Kleiner and Roiter, and by Golovashchuk, Ovsienko, and Roiter, in graded modules for
V.
[64])
has differential
The present author, as part of a study of
essentially-algebraic structures borne by categories, has extended in
[45]
the classical results on "cartesian theories" (finite-limit
theories) from the case where
V is sets to those where it is groupoids
or categories. The study of homotopy limits by Gray
[32]
takes him into the
area of change of base-categories, involving the connexions between the closed categories of categories and of simplicial sets.
The work
of May on infinite loop spaces, involving from the beginning the base category him
[62]
[61]
V of compactly-generated spaces, has of late led
to very general considerations on categories
V with two
symmetric monoidal structures and a distributive law between them. Mitchell
V
[63]
has related monoidal structures on
to low-dimensional cohomology groups of the group
[G,VJ G.
for suitable These latter
applications go beyond the basic theory presented here, but of course presuppose the relevant parts of it, Recent work of Walters theory, but with
([75],
[76])
does concern the basic
V generalized to a symmetric monoidal closed
bicategory; in this context he exhibits the sheaves on a site as the
In traduction
16 symmetric Cauchy-complete
V-categories.
It is plain that continued
expansion of the applications is to be expected.
(v)
Writing in text-book style, we have not interrupted the development
to assign credit for individual results.
To do so with precision and
justice would in any case be a daunting task; much has been written, and many insights were arrived at independently by several authors. Such references as do occur in the text are rather intended to show where more detail may be found.
What we can do, though, is to list
here some of the works to which we are particularly indebted. Perhaps the first to advocate in print the study of enriched categories was Mac Lane
[59];
although published in 1965, this
represents basically his Colloquium Lectures at Boulder in 1963. There were some early attempts by Linton make a start;
Benabou
([4],
[5])
[56]
and Kelly
[40]
went further; while Eilenberg
and Kelly wrote a voluminous article
[26]
covering only the
"elementary" notions, but including change of base-category. present Chapter 1 draws mainly on
to
[26]
Our
and on the author's article
[ 42].
The principal source for Chapter 2 is Day and Kelly see also Bunge
[ 10].
[20];
but
The ideas in Chapter 3 of co tensor products,
of ends, and of limits in a
V-category, go back to
[42]
and
[20];
and the concept of their pointwise existence in a functor-category to Dubuc
[22].
However the general notion of indexed limit, which
makes Chapter 3 possible in its present form, was discovered independently by Street
[72],
Auderset
[1],
and Borceux and
In traduction Kelly
[9].
articles
17 The last two sections of Chapter 3 call on Day's
[ 121
and
[ 14].
Chapter 4, on Kan extensions, is certainly indebted to the three articles
[20],
Dubuc in
[ 22]
[22],
[9]
already mentioned; in particular it was
who pointed out the importance of the "pointwise"
existence of Kan extensions, which we make part of our definition. The chapter also contains many more-or-less classical results for
V =Set;
all but the best known are credited in the text to their
authors. It is especially in Chapter 5, on density, that we have been heavily influenced by writers who themselves dealt only with namely Gabriel and Ulmer
[31]
and Diers
presentation" we have taken from Day meaning somewhat.
[21].
[16],
V = Set;
The term "density
although modifying its
Again, writers on particular aspects are given
credit in the text. Chapter 6 shows its debt Gabriel and Ulmer.
to Ehresmann
[24],
as well as to
The form of the transfinite construction used
here to prove the reflectivity of the algebras, although it is taken from the author's article
[44],
ultimately depends on an idea from
an unpublished manuscript of Barr (reference
[3]
of
[44]),
which
makes cowellpoweredness an unnecessary hypothesis, and so enables us to include the important example of quasitopological spaces. The author's original contributions to the book are perhaps most visible in the arrangement of topics and in the construction of proofs that apply equally to the classical and enriched cases.
For instance,
Introduction
18
many readers will find the way of introducing Kan extensions quite novel.
Beyond
thi~
the work in 5.11- 5.13 on Kan extensions along
a non-fully-faithful dense functor seems to be quite new even when
V = Set,
as is its application in 6.4; while the whole of Chapter 6
is new in the enriched setting.
(vi)
In the early chapters the formal definition-theorem-proof style
seemed out of place, and apt to lengthen an essentially simple account. Deciding to avoid it, we have accordingly made reference to a result either by quoting the section in which it occurs, or (more commonly) by quoting the number of the displayed formula most closely associated with it.
In the later chapters, now more concerned with applying the
logic than developing it, it seemed best to return to formally-numbered propositions and theorems. The end-result is as follows. refers to section 6 of Chapter 5.
A symbol 5.6 without parentheses All other references occur in a
single series, consisting of displayed formulae and proposition- or theorem-numbers, with the first digit denoting the chapter.
Thus
in Chapter 5, formula (5.51) is followed by Theorem 5.52, itself followed by formula (5.53), which in fact occurs in the statement of the theorem.
To assist cross-referencing, each left-hand page bears at its head the number of the last section to which that page belongs, and each right-hand page bears the numbers of the formulae, propositions, and theorems that occur on the two-page spread (in parentheses, even if they are theorem-numbers).
Introduction (vii)
19
It remains to thank those who have made the book possible.
Over the last twelve months I have had the happy opportunity to present early drafts of the material to acute and stimulating audiences at the Universities of Sydney, Trieste, and Hagen; their encouragement has been of inestimable value.
Equally important has been the support
of my colleagues in the Sydney Category Theory Seminar - including the visiting member
Andr~
Joyal, whose presence was made possible by
the Australian Research Grants Committee.
I am indebted to Cambridge
University Press, for suggesting this Lecture Notes Series as suited to such a book, and for their careful help with the technical details of publication.
It was they who observed that the original typed
manuscript was already suitable as camera-ready copy; I regard this as a compliment to the intelligence and taste of my secretary Helen Rubin, whose first mathematical job this was, and I thank her very sincerely.
Finally I thank my wife and children, who have
borne several months of shameful neglect.
Max Kelly, Sydney, January 1981.
(1.1)-(1.2)
1
The
1.1
21
elementary notions V = (V0 ,0,I,a,~,r)
A monoidaZ category
a functor
0•
isomorphisms
V0 x V0 aXYZ:
--+
(X
V0 Y)
0
an object
,
0
Z--+ X
0
consists of a category
,
0
I (Y
V
V
of
0
Z),
0
,
and natural
tX: I
0
X--+ X,
subject to two coherence axioms expressing the
rX: X ® I --+ X,
commutativity of the following diagrams: ((W®X)®Y)®Z ---~a'---- (W®X)®(Y®Z) _ _ _.:::a_ _--r W®(X®(Y®Z))
r
a®l
ll®a
(W®(X®Y))®Z - - - - - - - - - a - - - - - - - - - + W®((X®Y)®Z), (1.1)
(X®l)®Y
a
X®(I®Y)
~~ X®Y
I t then follows (see
[58]
and
.
( 1. 2)
[ 39 J) that every diagram of natural
transformations commutes, each arrow of which is obtained by repeatedly applying the functor
® to instances of
here an "instance" of
of the functors
0
and
their inverses, and
is a natural transformation, such as
in the diagrams above, formed from
or
see
a
a,~,r,
I
to its variables.
a
1•
w®X,Y,Z
by repeated application
For a precise formulation,
[58]. A special kind of example, called a cartesian monoidal category, is
given by taking for
V0
'
~-
any category with finite products, taking for
1.1
22 0
and
a,~,r
the product
I
and the terminal object
X
the canonical isomorphisms.
Set,
are the categories
Cat,
and taking for
1,
Important particular cases of this
Gpd,
Ord,
Top,
CGTop,
HCGTop,
QTop,
Shv s, of (small) sets, categories, groupoids, ordered sets, topological spaces, compactly generated topological spaces, hausdorff such, quasi-topological spaces
[69],
and sheaves for a site
S;
here "small"
is in reference to some chosen universe, which we suppose given once for all.
Other cartesian examples are obtained by t&king for
ordered set with finite intersections, such as the ordinal
V
0
an
2 = {0,1}.
All of these examples are symmetric in the sense of 1.4 below, and all the named ones except
Top
are closed in the sense of 1.5 below.
A collection of non-cartesian (symmetric, closed) examples is given
Ab,
by the categories groups,
G-R-~lod,
DG- R-Mod
R-modules for a commutative ring
differential graded ®j
R-Mod,
the category
R,
of (small) abelian
graded
R-modules, each with its usual tensor product as
Ban of Banach spaces and linear maps of
with the projective tensor product;
the category
CGTop*
compactly-generated spaces with the smash product for ordered set
R+
R-modules, and
0'
'
norm~
1,
of pointed and the
of extended non-negative reals, with the reverse of
the usual order, and with
+ as
®.
A non-symmetric example is the category of bimodules over a non-commutative ring
R,
with
®,
Another is the category of
endofunctors of a small category, with composition as a,~,r
0;
here
are identities, so that the monoidal category is called strict.
(1. 3)
23
the tensor produat, and
~
In general we call
I
We suppose henceforth given a particular monoidal ~s
locally small (has small hom-sets).
V0 (I,-): V0
functor
Set,
Ord,
Top,
--+
Ab,
CGTop*'
X;
(Set,
Ab,
reflecting).
Gpd,
Ban,
VX
is the
Ban) it is even conservative (• isomorphism-
Yet
is not faithful in general; in the cases
V
Cat and
VX is the set of objects of X, and in the case DG-R-Mod,
is the set of
convenient to call an element V0
an element
)
1.2 A V-category A(A,B)
E
V0
VX
0-cycles.
In spite of the failure of
in
In such cases as
V is faithful, while in some of them
in these cases
R-Mod,
V0
it is (to within isomorphism)
the ordinary "underlying-set" functor; in the case of unit ball of
V such that
We then have the representable
Set, which we denote by V.
R-Mod,
the unit object.
f
V
f
of
to be faithful in general, it is VX
A consists of a set
identity element
®
f: I --+ X
of X.
for each pair of objects of
M = MABC: A(B,C)
(that is, a map
A(A,B)
--+
A(A,C)
jA: I--+ A(A,A)
obA
of objects, a hom-object
A, a composition law
for each triple of objects, and an for each object; subject to the
associativity and unit axioms expressed by the commutativity of (A(C,D)~(B,C))®A(A,B)
----=a=-----+ A( C,D) 0(A(B ,C) ~A(A,B))
j
M01
A (B,D)o.I(A,B)
~
!OM
/o.I(A,C)
avariant functor from
B·• while a functor T: A 0 B --+ C may be thought of as a
to
funato1' of two variables. T(A,-): B
E
Such a
B--+ C for each A
B. Here T(A,-)
E
T
A and
gives rise to partial. funato:t>s T(-,B): A--+ C for each
is the composite
B- I
08---:~A0B----+
A®1
T
fromwhich can be read off the value of
c,
( 1. 20)
T(A,-)BB''
Suppose, conversely, that we are given a family of functors T(A,-):
B--+ C indexed by obA and a family of functors
T(-,B): A--+ C indexed by T(A,-)B T: A 0
= T(-,B)A, =
T(A,B)
obB,
such that on objects we have
say,
Then there is a functor
B --+ C of which these are the partial functors if and only if
we have commutativity in
1.4
32
A(A,A')®B(B,B')
T(-,B')®T(A,-)
C(T(A,B'),T(A',B'))®C(T(A,B),T(A,B'))
1M C(T(A,B) ,T(A' ,B'))
c
lM 8(B,B )®A(A,A') 1
I
, -)
®T (- 'B)
T is then unique, and
Moreover (1.21). ( [ 26]
T(A
C(T(A',B) ,T(A' ,B'))®C(T(A,B) ,T(A' ,B)).
T(A,B),(A',B')
is the diagonal of ca~
The verification is easy, and the details Ch. II I,
§ 4)
T,S: A® 6--+ C,
constitutes a
a family
B,
each fixed
a
A, a
T --+ S
V-natural
in
C
0
if and only if it
T(A,-)
--+
T(-,B)--+ S(-,B).
V-natural
V-naturaZity may be ver>ified
C) to verify that,
aAB: T(A,B)--+ S(A,B)
V-natural transformation
constitutes, for each fixed for
be found in
.
It is further easy (using (1.21), and (1.3) for if
( 1. 21)
S(A,-),
and,
In other words,
variab~e-by-var>iab~e.
In relation to the underlying ordinary categories, we have of
(A 0 p)
course not
A0
A
o
X
0
B • o'
x B0 --+
(A
= (A ) 0 p
and
0
(T0 p)
=
0
(T ) 0 P. 0
However
(A
8
B)
is
0
rather there is an evident canonical functor 8
B) 0 ,
and a similar one
1 --+
I0 .
For
T: A
8
B
--+ C,
the partial functors of the composite ordinary functor
A
o-
are precisely
®
T(A,-)
0
6
(A
0
and
T(-,B)
0
8
6)
0
•
We could discuss, in the present setting, the extraordinary
V-naturaZ families of 1.7 below.
However, the techniques that make
( 1. 22)
(1.21)-(1.26)
33
this simple arise more naturally, and at a higher level, when closed; which is the case of real interest. [17]
V is
Moreover it is shown in
that any symmetric monoidal category can, by passing to a higher
universe, be embedded in a closed one; see also 2.6 and 3.11 below.
1.5
The monoidal category
V (symmetric or not)
is said to be closed
(cartesian closed, when V is cartesian monoidal) if each functor -®Y: V
0
--+
V
0
has a right adjoint
[Y,-J;
so that we have an
adjunction (1.23) with unit and counit (the latter called evaluation) say d: X--+ [Y,X ® Y], Putting
X= I
in (1.23), using the isomorphism
recalling from 1.1 that
V = V (I,-): V --+Set, 0
(1.24)
e: [Y,Z] ® Y--+ Z •
0
~:I®
Y ~ Y,
and
we get a natural
isomorphism (1.25)
since
[Y,Z]
V (Y,Z), 0
is thus exhibited as a lifting through
it is called the internal hom of
Putting
Y • I
y
and
V of the hom-set
z.
in (1.23) and using the isomorphism
r: X® I~ X,
we deduce a natural isomorphism (1.26)
i: Z - [I,Z]
it is easy to verify that of (1.25).
Replacing
Vi: VZ- V[I,Z]
X by
W ®X
is just the case
in (1.23), and using the
Y
I
1.5
34
a: (W ®X)® Y
isomorphism
~
W 0 (X® Y), we deduce a natural
isomorphism (1.27)
p: [X® Y,ZJ- lX,:Y,ZIJ
and it is easy to verify that
Vp
modulo the isomorphisms (1.25). and convenient to replace
agrees with the
n
of (1.23)
In many concrete cases it is possible
V by an isomorph in such a way that (1.25)
becomes an equality; this should be clear from the examples of closed categories given in 1.1, and we do not labour the point. The monoidal category every
-®
Y have a right adjoint
right adjoint with
V is said to be bialosed if, ·'not only does
rrx,-].
[X,-] = [X,-].
When
v
but also every
X®-
bialosed biaategory of left-R-,
has a
is symmetric, it is biclosed if closed,
The non-symmetric monoidal category of
mentioned in 1.1, is biclosed.
S
[Y,-],
R-bimodules,
It is part of a larger structure, the right-S-, bimodules,
where
R
and
vary over all rings; and it seems to be typical that non-symmetric
biclosed monoidal categories occur in nature as a small part of such a bicategory. see of
[6 ],
(The notion of bicategory, for an exposition of which
generalizes that of
2-category, the strict associativity
1-cells being replaced by associativity to within coherent
isomorphisms; a one-object bicategory is a monoidal category, just as a one-object
2-cat~gory
is a strict monoidal category.)
of R.F.C. Walters ([75], [76]) "V-categories
A" where
Recent work
suggests the importance of studying
V is a biclosed- bicategory with an appropriate
kind of symmetry; but that goes beyond the scope of the present account.
(1.27)
35
There also do occur in nature important closed monoidal categories that are not biclosed.
A typical example is given by the strict
monoidal category of small endofunctol'o (in some suitable sense of "small") of a well-behaved large category such as For such a monoidal closed
V,
Set;
see
[45].
we can develop part of the theory of
V-categories; we have the results of 1.2 and 1.3, but not those of 1.4; and we have the Yoneda Lemma of 1.9 below, but not its extra-variable form.
However, we do not pursue this at all, for in practice it seems
that the interest in such a
V lies in V itself, not in V-categories -
which become interesting chiefly when
V is symmetric monoidal
closed. We end this section with two further comments on examples. the symmetric (cartesian) monoidal
Top
is not closed:
-xY
First,
cannot
have a right adjoint since it does not preserve regular epimorphisms; see
[19].
Next, to the examples of symmetric monoidal closed category
in 1.1, we add one more class.
An ordered set
V with finite inter-
sections and finite unions is called a Heyting algebra if it is cartesian closed; a boolean algebra is a special case.
1.6 From now on we suppose that our given V is symmetric monoidal closed, with
V
0
locally small.
The structure of
V-CAT then becomes
rich enought to permit of Yoneda-lemma arguments formally identical with those in
CAT.
Before giving the Yoneda Lemma and its extensions
in 1.9, we collect in this section and the next two some necessary preliminaries: less so here.
results many of which are almost trivial in
CAT,
but
1.6
36
The proof of each assertion of these sections is the verification of the commutativity of a more-or-less large diagram.
This verification
can be done wholesale, in that each diagram involved is trivially checked to be of the type proved commutative in the coherence theorems of
[47]
and
[48].
Yet direct verifications, although somewhat
tedious, are nevertheless fairly straightforward if the order below is followed.
V "makes V itself
The first point is that the internal-hom of into a call is
V-category". V,
[X,Y].
More precisely, there is a
whose objects are those of Its composition-law
V0 ,
M: [Y,Z]
V-category, which we
and whose hom-object [X,Y]--+ [X,Z]
0
V(X,Y)
corresponds
under the adjunction (1.23) to the composite ([Y,Z] ® [X,Y]) ®X~ [Y,Z] ® ([X,Y] ®X)~ [Y,Z] and its identity element ~:
I
0
X--+ X.
jX: I--+ [X,X]
0
Y ~ Z,
corresponds under (1.23) to
Verification of the axioms (1.3) and (1.4) is easy
when we recall that, because of the relation of the definition (1.28) of
M is equivalent to
e e(M
w of (1.23),
to the 0
1)
=
e(1
0
e)a.
It is further easily verified that (1.25) gives an isomorphism between
V0
and the underlying ordinary category of the
V-category
V; we
henceforth identify these two ordinary categories by this isomorphism, thus rendering the notation
V
0
consistent with the notation
A
0
of 1.3.
Next we observe that, for each A E A, B
E
we have the ~ep~esentabZe
A to
A(A,B)
(1.28)
E
V,
and with
V-category V-functor
A and each object
A(A,-): A--+ V, sending
( 1. 2 8) - ( l. 32 )
37
A(A,-)BC: A(B ,C) -
[A(A,B) ,A(A,C) I
corresponding under the adjunction (1.23) to Axioms (1.5) and (1.6) for a
A(A,C).
( 1. 29)
M: A(B,C)
®
A(A,B)
--+
V-functor reduce easily to (1.3)
and half of (1.4). Replacing
Aop
A by
funotor A(-,B): Aop
--+
gives the contravariant representable
v.
The families 0
partial functors of a functor A(A,B);
A(A,-)· and
HomA: A p
®
A --+
A(-,B)
are the
V sending (A, B)
to
for the condition ( 1. 21) again reduces easily to (1.3) for
homA: Ao op
We write
x
Ao
--+
v0
for the ordinary functor
v
A op x A 0
it sends
0
(A,B)
to
( 1. 30)
0
A(A,B),
A(f,g): A(A,B)--+ A(A',B'),
A.
and for its value on maps we write where
By 1.4, the partial functors of
f: A'--+ A and
homA
g: B--+ B'.
are the functors underlying
A(A,-)
and A(-,B), so that our writing their values on morphisms as
A(A,g)
and
A(f,B) is consistent with (1.12).
the definition (1.29) of A(A,C)
we see that
A(A,g): A(A,B)--+
is the composite
A(A,B) ~I while
A(A,-)BC'
Combining (1.11) with
®
A(A,B) ~ A(B,C)
A(f,B): A(D,B)--+ A(A,B)
A(D,B)
-;:y+
A(D,B)
® I ~
®
A(A,B) ~ A(A,C)
( 1. 31)
®
A(A,D) ~ A(A,B)
( 1. 32)
is A(D,B)
From these it follows easily that we have commutativity in
1.6
38
A op
x
When
A = V,
[ , l : V op
A
~.'""'
0
we see at once that x
0
V
homV
v 'set
( 1. 33)
V •
--+
0
0
to
(X,Y)
0
is just the functor
Now we observe that there is also a sending
v
Ten(X,Y)
m
and with
X® Y,
[X,X'] ® [Y,Y']--+ [X® Y,X' ® Y']
V-functor
Ten: V
@
V --+ V,
Ten(X,Y) ,(X' ,Y'):
corresponding under the adjunction
(1.23) to the composite ([X,X']®[Y,Y'])®(X®Y)
([X,X']®X)®([Y,Y']®Y) ----+ X'®Y'
m
when we observe that (1.34) is equivalent to
e(Ten ® 1)
(e ® e)m,
V-functor axioms (1.5) and (1.6) is easy.
verification of the
(1. 34)
The
ordinary functor
V0
X
V0
is at once seen to be
(V
V)
--,T=-e-n--+ Vo
0
®: V o
X
underlying ordinary functor of For any
®
V-categories
A
V --+ V ' o
o'
Ten(X,-) and
( 1. 35)
0
so that, by 1.4, the is
X®-,
B we have a commutative diagram
v Ten
( 1. 36)
(1. 33)- ( 1. 39)
39
in terms of the partial functors, this asserts the commutativity of A®B _ _ _(;,;_A:. : .®: . :B)~(~(A:.:.!..:,B:.!_)..!. .,-_!.):____-+
v
A(A,-)®:S(B,( 1. 37)
which is easily checked.
At the level of the underlying functors
hom,
this gives (A® B)((f,g),(f',g'))
1.7
A(f,f') ® B(g,g').
The point to be made in the next section is that all the families
V,
of maps canonically associated to a
( 1. 38)
V-functor
T,
or to a
a,
such as
or
M: A(B,C)
or
e: [Y,Z] ® Y--+ Z,
or
--+
B(TA,TB),
V-natural in every variable. case of
M,
V-category
V-natural
X® (Y ® Z), T: A(A,B)
or to a
or
a:
I--+
B(TA,SA),
A, or to
a: (X® Y) ®
®
Z--+
A(A,B) --+ A(A,C),
are themselves
To deal with a variable like
B
in the
we must now introduce the notion of extraordinary
V-naturatity; which later plays an essential role in the definition of V-functor-category. First we observe that the formulae (1.31) and (1.32) allow us to write the "ordinary"
V-naturality condition (1.7) in the more compact
form A(A,B)
----=1'---->- B(TA, TB)
s B(SA,SB) ----=~--:-:---+
B(aA,l)
B( TA, SB) •
( 1. 39)
1.7
40
By (extraordinary)
V-naturaZity for an
B,
in
where
K
E
B
obA - indexed and
family of maps
0
T: A p ® A
--+
B,
we
0
mean the commutativity of each diagram T(A -)
A(A,B)
E(T(A,A),T(A,B))
T(-,B)j
B(I3A,1)
E(T(B,B),T(A,B))
E(13B, 1)
---+
Duality gives the notion, for the same family
yA: T(A,A)
--+
K;
T
( 1. 40)
E(K,T(A,B))
and
K,
of a
V-natural
namely the commutativity of
A(A,B) _ _ _....::.T~(B::..L--!-)- 4 E(T(B,A) ,T(B,B))
T(-,A)j + ----.---~-..,----4
E(T(B,A),T(A,A))
Such extraordinary
V
= Set;
of the
B(l ,y A)
B(T(B ,A) ,K)
(1.41)
V-naturality is of course fully alive in the case
it is exhibited there, for instance, by the "naturality in d
and the
e
of (1.24).
V • Set,
In this case
Y"
(1.40) and
(1.41) have more elementary forms obtained by evaluating them at an arbitrary
f
extraordinary
E
A(A,B).
Clearly extraordinary
Set-naturality:
V-naturality implies
we have only to apply
V
to (1.40)
and ( l. 41) . Just as for ordinary SA: K--+ T(A,A)
Q: B--+ C, a
is
V-natural as above, and if
then the maps
V-natural family
V-naturality, it is clear that if
QSP.
P:
V--+
QI3PD(=Q 0 SPD): QK---+ QT(PD,PD)
A and constitute
(1.40)-(1.42) If is
41 0
T: (A ® V) P ® (A ® V) (A,D)
V-natural in
each
fixed
D and in
D for each fixed and
BAD: K ~ T(A,D,A,D)
a family
if and only if it is
T(-,D,-,D)
partial functors
-+ B,
A,
T(A,-,A,-)
V-natural in
A for
with respect to the respectively.
The most
direct proof involves translating (1.40) via (1.32) into a form analogous to (1.7); then,as in the proof for ordinary
V-natural
transformations, it is a matter of combining (1.21) with (1.3) for Thus here, too,
V-naturality can be verified variable-by-variable.
That being so, we can combine ordinary and extraordinary and speak of a
V-natural family
T: A. ® Bop ® B --+ C
C.
v
and
V-naturality,
o.ABC: T(A,B,B) --+ S(A,C,C),
0 S: A® C p ®
c --+ v.
If each of
where
A,B, and
stands for a finite number of variables, this is then the most
general form. The analogue of "vertical composition" for such families is the calculus of
[25].
There are three basic cases of composability, in
addition to that for ordinary these three are dual.
V-natural transformations; and two of
Each of the three, however, is in fact a sequence
of sub-cases indexed by the natural numbers.
The reader will see the
pattern if we just give the first two sub-cases of the only two essentially-different sequences; the proofs are easy using (1.39) - (1.41). For
A and if
T,S: A0 p ®A.--+ B,
if
BAB: T(A,B) --+ S(A,B)
o.A: K--+ T(A,A)
is
is
A and
V-natural in
V-natural in
B,
the
composite
K - - - - > - T(A,A)
S(A,A)
( 1. 42)
1.7
42 is
V-natural in
s: A0 P ®A--+ B, B and if
and
For
A. if
is
aAB: K--+ T(A,A,B,B)
SABC: T(A,B,B,C) --+ S(A,C)
V-natural in
V-natural in
is
A
and
A,B, and
C,
then the composite
K ---,~ T(A,A,A,A) -
:-AAA--+
0
a~
is
V-natural in
A.
( 1. 43)
S(A,A)
" The next one in this series has
aABC: K--+ T(A,A,B,B,C,C)
and
SABCD: T(A,B,B,C,C,D) --+ S(A,D);
and there is of course a dual series.
and
R: A--+ B;
are
V-natural in
if
A and
TA
is
V-natural in
aAB: TA B,
---+
A.
-->-
S(A,B,B)
S: A ® A p ® A --+ B, BAB: S(A,A,B) __,. RB
and
the composite ( l. 44)
S (A, A, A)
For the same
S: A ® A0 P ® A ® A0 P ® A - - + B, BABe: S(A,A,B,B,C) --+ RC
0
T: A --+ B,
The self-dual series begins with
are
if
T
and
R,
but for
aABC: TA--+ S(A,B,B,C,C)
V-natural in
A,B, and
C,
and
then the
composite
TA
-------+
aAAA
is
V-natural in
S(A,A,A,A,A)
( 1.45)
- - - - + RA
8.\AA
A.
In each case a handsome geometrical picture is produced if, to the diagrams (1.42) - (1.45), there are added curves above the diagram linking variables which must be set equal in
a,
and curves below the
diagram linking variables which must be set equal in
s;
the
(1.43)-(1.45)
43
geometrical union of these curves, thought of as meeting at the variables, then links the variables which must be set equal in the composite.
Of
course the associativity of this kind of composition, whenever it makes sense, is a triviality.
1.8
We turn now to the
the beginning of 1.7.
V-naturality of the canonical maps mentioned at Of course such an object as
here thought of as the value appropriate (a) is
Ten(HomA(B,C),HomA(A,B))
First, it follows at once from (1.29) that
a: T --+ S
Next, for a
verify
of the
is
is a
in
T: A--+
B,
the map
V-natural in both variables B;
A and
TAB: A(A,B) --+ B.
It suffices to
and here the appropriate diagram of the
This last gives, for a A
and
this is also
A'
of
V-functor
T: A
@
B --+ C,
T. the
T(-,B): A(A,A')--+ C(T(A,B),T(A' ,B)).
V-natural in
V-natural
in the sense of (1.7).
V-functor
V-naturality in
a
form (1.39) reduces, in the light of (1.29), to (1.5) for (c)
is
aA: I --+ B(TA,SA)
V-natural in the sense of (1.40) precisely when
B(TA,TB)
A(A,B)
@
V-functor.
transformation (b)
A(B,C)
B·,
V-naturality However
the appropriate instance of (1.40)
reduces via (1.29) to (1.21). (d)
In particular, for a
[A(A,B),A(A,C)]
V-category
of (1.29) is
(e)
Composing the
the
V-naturality in
A(A,-)BC A of
A,
the
A(A,-)BC: A(B,C) --+
V-natural in all variables. of (d) with
g: I--+ A(B,C)
A(A,g): A(A,B)--+ A(A,C).
gives, by (a),
1.8
44 (f)
The
V-naturality in both variables of
e: [Y,Z]
~
Y--+ Z
is an
easy consequence of (1.29) and (1.34). (g)
Since, by (1.29),
M: A(B,C)
0
A(A,B)
->-
A(A,C)
for a
V-category
A is the composite A(B,C) it is (h)
0
A(A,-)®l ~(A,B),A(A,C)]
A(A,B)
i.: I
A(A,C)
V-natural in all variables by (d), (e), (f), (1.42) and (1.44). The
V-naturality of
follows from (a), since (i)
--e-+
A(A,B)
0
The ~
jA: I--+ A(A,A) 1: 1 --+ 1: A --+ A
V-naturality in every variable of
X ---+ X,
for a
r: X ® I ---+X,
is
V-category
A
V-na tural.
a: (X ® Y) ® Z ---+X® (Y ® Z),
c: X ® Y ---+ Y ® X,
follows easily
from (l. 34) . (j)
From the definition (1.27) of the isomorphism
definition (1.34) of
Ten(-,Y),
p- 1 : [X,[Y,Z]]---+ [X® Y,Z]
p
and the
we easily see that
is the composite
[X' [ y' Z]] -=Te_n_(r--,~Y")-+ [X® Y,[Y,Z] ® Y] -,-[-.-l-,-=-e-r]-' [X® Y,Z] . It follows from (c), (e), (f), and (1.44) that
p -1
all variables; whence the same is true of its inverse (k)
is
V-natural in p.
The composite X ----;;--:y+ I®X
~
IC
]""
1
[X®Y,X®Y]®X - - + [X,[Y,X®Y]]®X--+ [Y,X®Y] p® 1 e
is easily verified to be the is therefore
d: X--+ [Y,X ® Y]
of (1.24); the latter
V-natural in every variable by (i), (h), (j), (f), (e),
(1.42), and (1.44).
(1.46)
(2)
45
The composite X----.. d
is the isomorphism
[I,X
0
I]
i: X--+ [I,X],
[I ,X]
l1,r]
which is therefore
V-natural.
This completes the list of canonical maps, and we end this section with a general principle,
Since a map
f: X--+ [Y,Z]
~
=
and
f
e(f
for
V-functors
0
under the 1),
f: X
0
Y --+ Z and its image
of (1.23) are related by f
it follows from (f), (k), (e)
T,S,R
= [1,f]d
and (1.42) - (1.44) that,
of suitable variances with codomain
V,
we
have: (m)
A family
f: T(D,D,A,B)
0
S(E,E,A,C) --+ R(F,F,B,C)
is
V-natural
in any of its variables if and only if the corresponding f: T(D,D,A,B)--+ [S(E,E,A,C),R(F,F,B,C)]
1.9
is so.
The form of the Yoneda Lemma we give here is a weak one, in that
it asserts a bijection of sets rather than an isomorphism of objects of
V;
a stronger form will be given in 2.4 below. Consider a
each
V-functor
F:
V-natural transformation
element
n:
I--+ FK
of
I
FK
~
A --+ V
and an object
K of
A.
To
a: A(K,-) --+ F we can assign the given by the composite
A(K,K)
K
The Yoneda Lemma asserts that this gives a bijection between the set
V-nat(A(K,-),F)
of V-naturat transformations and the set
( 1. 46)
1.9
46 V (I,FK) (=
VFK)
of elements of
FK;
the component
0
a
A
being given
in terms of n as the composite [ FK , FA]
A(K,A)
----::-[n-,-:1--::]-+ [I , FA]
-i--~1c-+
For the proof, we first note that, for any V-natural in by (1.47),
F,
the
its
A, aKjK
by 1.8 (b), (e), and(£).
n;
is in fact
Set-naturality of
ji
aA' when
A(K,-)
A(K,A)
a
is defined
i,
and the easy verification
It remains to show that (1.47) is in fact
is given by (1.46).
n
Next, if
(a consequence, as we saw in (1.7), of
j
ii: I--+ [l,I].
=
n, (1.47) is indeed
this follows easily from (1.6) for
V-naturality), the naturality of
that
(1.47)
FA •
In the diagram [j '1]
[A(K,K) ,A(K,A)]
[I,A(K,A)]
I[1,aAJ
F
+
[FK,FA] ---,[~__,,...,];-+ [A ( K, K) , FA] ---r[J-.,--:,.]-->-
aK' 1
1
the left square commutes by the
[I,FA]
V-naturality of
--~~-+
i-
a
FA
in the form (1.39),
the middle square trivially, and the right square by the naturality of i.
The proof is complete when we observe that the top edge of the
diagram is the identity; which follows from the definition (1.29) of the axiom (1.4) for
A(K,-), terms of
A, and the definition (1.26) of
i
in
r.
There is an extra-variable form of the result, involving functors F:
0
BP
®
which is
A--+
V and K: B--+ A,
V-na tural in
A
and a family
for each fixed
aBA: A(KB,A)
--+
F(B,A)
B, so that it corresponds
(1.47)-(1.48)
47
as above to a family
nB: I--+ F(B,KB).
It then follows from (1.46)
and (1.42) that
n is
V-natural in
B if
a
is, and from (1.47)
and (1.44) that
a
is
V-natural in
B if
n
is.
It is worth noting an alternative way of writing (1.47) when has the form
B(B,T-)
n: I--+ B(B,TK) image of
1K
for a
V-functor
is then a map
under
T: A--+
n: B --+ TK
in
VaK: A (K,K)--+ 8 (B,TK)). 0
B,
so that
B0
(in fact, the
Then
0
F
is the
composite A(K,A)
B(TK,TA)
B(B,TA) ,
B(n,l)
which is easily seen by (1.32) to coincide with (1.47).
every V-natural
a: A(K,-) --+ A(L,-)
and clearly
k: L --+ K;
1.10 We have called the
for a unique
V-functor K
E
is.
A(K,-): A--+ V representable.
V-functors
representable if there is some Then the pair
A(k,-)
In particular,
is an isomorphism if and only if a
k
More generally, however, a
is
(1.48)
F: A--+
V is called
A and an isomorphism a: A(K,-) --+F.
(K,a) is a representation of
F·
it is essentially ' unique if it exists, in the sense that any other representation
a': A(K' ,-)--+ F k: K--+ K'.
has the form
The corresponding
the representation. contravariant
(We call 0
F: A P--+
For a general n: I --+ FK
a'= a.A(k,-)
V,
n: I--+ FK n
for a unique isomorphism is called the unit of
the counit when we are representing a
V in the form A(-,K).)
there is no simple criterion in terms of an
for the corresponding
a: A(K,-) --+ F
It is of course otherwise in the classical case
V=
to be an isomorphism.
Set;
there we have
l. 10
48
the comma-category are pairs
(A,x)
and only if
1/F
with
=
e"L F
A
~
of "elements of
A and
e"L F
FA;
E
e"L F,
(K,n) is initial in
i f and only i f
x
F",
whose objects
and
a
is invertible if
so that
F
is representable
has an initial object.
However, any such kind
of "universal property" criterion ultimately expresses a bijection of sets, and cannot suffice in general to characterize an isomorphism in
V • 0
0
Now let
F: B p ®A--+
admits a representation
V be such that each F(B,-): A--+ V
aB: A(KB,-)--+ F(B,-).
one way of defining
~c: B(B,C) --+ A(KB,KC)
V-funator for which
aBA: A(KB,A) --+ F(B,A)
as weU as
that nv.kes is
K a
V-natural in
B
A.
For by 1. 9, the that of
Then there is exactly
V-naturality in
B of
is equivalent to
nB' which by (1.40) means the commutativity of
B(B,C)
~
A(KB,KC) F(B,-), [F(B,KB),F(B,KC)]
F(-,KC)
+ [F(C,KC) ,F(B ,KC)] --...,.----=----+ [I,F(B,KC)] .
Cnc,1J
Now the composite
[nB,l]F(B,-)
( 1. 49)
in this diagram is, by (1.47), the
composite isomorphism A(KB,KC) - - - - + F(B ,KC) aB,KC so that (1.49) forces us to define
[I,F(B,KC)]
i ~C
as
( l. 50)
(1.49)-(1.52)
49
This composite (1.50) is
V-natural in
B, by 1.7 and 1.8; and from
this the proof of 1.8(b), read backwards, gives the (1.5) for
K;
while the remaining
V-functor axiom
V-functor axiom (1.6) is a trivial
consequence of (1.49).
1.11 As in any
2-category (see
n,e:: S-l T: A-+ B
adjoint) and
S:
(the unit) and
equations
Te:.nT
adjunctions in
in
V-CAT
an adjunction
[49])
T: A-+ B
between
(the right
B-+ A (the left adjoint) consists of n: 1-+ TS (the aounit) satisfying the triangular
e:: ST--+ 1
=1 V-CAT
and
e:S.Sn
= 1.
By the Yoneda Lemma of 1.9, such V-natural isomorphisms
are in bijection with n: A(SB,A) = B(B,TA)
for by (1.48) a n = B(n,l)T A(SB,A) nn • 1
V-natural map
for a unique
has the form and
nn = 1
n,
n: A(SB,A) while a
n = A(1,e:)S
(1.51) B(B,TA)
--+
has the form
V-natural map· n: B(B,TA) -+
for a unique
e:,
and the equations
reduce by Yoneda precisely to the triangular
equations. The
2-functor
) : V-CAT -+ CAT 0
into an ordinary adjunction
carries such an adjuction
n,e:: s0 - t T :0A -0- + B0
in
CAT.
It
is immediate from (1.33) that the corresponding isomorphism of hom-sets is Vn:
A0 (SB,A)
~
B0 (B,TA)
•
( 1. 52)
Note that the unit and counit of this ordinary adjunction are the same n
and
e:,
now seen as natural rather than
V-natural,
1.11
50
By 1.10, a
V-functor
T: A--+ B has a left adjoint (which is
then unique to within isomorphism, as in any each
8(B,T-)
is representable.
2-category) exactly when
More generally, if those
8(B,T-) is representable constitute the full subcategory we get a
V-functor
v
When
is conservative - faithfulness is not enough
5
0
s0
for
---1 T0 ),
(1.52) is.
A by
n
= 8(n,l)T
and deduce that Thus, taking
n
B,
of
-
0
define a map
n
the
that is
as above (using the unit
n
is an isomorphism since the
V = Ab
T.
implies that of a left
T
s for T: we set SB = S0 B'
V-natural in
8'
for which
called a partial left adjoint to
S: 8' --+A
existence of a left adjoint adjoint
B
for Vn
of
for instance, an additive functor
has a left adjoint exactly when its underlying functor has one. Again by 1.10, in the extra-variable case of a T: C p ~A--+ 8, 0
S
if each
T(C,-)
cutomatically becomes a
has a left adjoint
V-functor
n: A(S(B,C),A) ~ 8(B,T(C,A))
is
V-functor
8
~
S(-,C),
then
C --+ A in such a way that
V-natural in all three variables.
An evident example, with
A = 8 = C = V,
p: [X~ Y,Z] ~ lX,[Y,Z]]
of (1.27).
is the adjunction
For a typical adjunction (1.51) as above, we have a commutative diagram
(1.53)
(1.53)
51
this follows from Yoneda on setting
j,
with
(Vn)(EA) ~ 1.
since
conclude that
A'
Because
=A
and composing both legs
n
is an isomorphism, we
is fully faithful if and only if
T
In consequence, a right adjoint
T
is an isomor>phism.
E
is fully faithful exactly when
is so.
T
0
As in any
2-category, a
equivalence, and we write
A ~ B,
T:
n: 1 ~ TS
and isomorphisms any
V-functor
and
A --+
B.
B is called an S: B --+A
if there is some
p: ST ~ 1.
2-category) by the isomorphism
E = p.Sn- 1T.p- 1ST,
T: A--+
E: ST
Replacing
~
1
p
(still in
given by
we actually have an adjunction
n,E: S
---1 T:
The word "equivalence" is sometimes used to mean an adjunction
in which, as here, In the
n
and
2-category
are isomorphisms; we write
E
S
--1
T:
A ~ B.
T: A--+ B is an equivalence if and
V-CAT,
only if T is fuZZy faithful and essentially surjective on objects; the latter means that every to
TA
for some
For, if
T
A
E
A;
B
E
B is isomorphic (in B
we often omit the words "on objects".
is an equivalence,
T
is fully faithful since
an isomorphism, and is essentially surjective since is an isomorphism. SB
E
A
-in-A
As for the converse, we
and an isomorphism
isomorphism because automatically a
n : B --+ TSB. 5
TE,
T.
S
Since
by the triangular equation
is
E
B an
V-natural-
is then an
becomes n
is an
TE.nT
= 1;
is an isomorphism by (1.12), since a fully-faithful conservative.
B
The corresponding
is fully faithful, so that
V-functor left adjoint to
isomorphism, so is
choose for each
B
T
E
nB: B--+ TSB
n = B(n ,1)T: A(SB,A) --+ B(B,TA)
transformation
of course)
,
0
T
0
whence
is certainly
l. l l
52 In any
2-category (see
[49])
adjunctions can be composed, forming
a category, of which the equivalences are a subcategory. from Yoneda that the composition of adjunctions in to the composition of the
It is further true in any
n,£: S
and
1-cells
--l
2-category (see
and
2-cells
A and
~
~:
S'Q--+ PS.
In
--l
n' ,£': S'
B--+ B',
Q:
V-CAT
( l. 54)
[49 ])
that, given
B'
T': A'--+
there is a bijection
(with appropriate naturality properties) bebNeen and
corresponds
B(B,T'TA) .
=
T: A--+ B and
P: A--+ A'
V-CAT
V-natural isomorphisms in
A(SS'B,A) - B(S'B,TA)
adjunctions
It follows
A: QT--+ T'P
2-cells
it follows from Yoneda that
determine one another through the commutativity of
A(SB ,A) ----.;n~---. B(B, TA) -
Q
A' (PSB,PA)
B' (QB ,QTA)
A'(p,l)j
B' (l,;>..)
A'(S'QB,PA) such a pair
)..,~
S ---1 T
and
A• = A with
s' ---1
have a bijection bebNeen the adjunctions become a to
S' --1 T'
(1.55)
may be called mates,
In particular, when so that
B I ( QB •T 'p A)
n'
T'
p
z
1
and
are both adjunctions
A: T --+ T'
and the
2-category when we define a
to be such a pair
B' = B
(A,~).
~=
A
s'
with
Q : 1'
--+
B,
we
--+
s.
The
2-cell from
s --l
T
(1.54)-(1.55)
Any
53
A--+ 8
T:
full image
A'
of
the replete image some to
TA.
A
if
T,
A"
T
determined by those of
A'
Clearly
B;
determines two full subcategories of
T,
and
B of the form
determined by those
A"
the
TA,
and
B isomorphic to
are equivalent; and each is equivalent
is fully faithful.
A full subcategory which contains all
the isomorphs of its objects is said to be replete; any full subcategory has a repletion, namely the replete image of its inclusion. T: A --+ 8
fully-faithful inclusion
A" --+ 8
A'
--+
Clearly a
has a left adjoint if and only if the
B has one, and if and only if the inclusion
has one.
A full subcategory
T: A--+ 8
A
has a left adjoint.
reflective in
8 , 0
is called reflective if the inclusion
8
of
This implies, of course, that
but is in general strictly stronger.
A
is
0
It follows -
since it is trivially true for ordinary categories - that every retract
8 )
(in
of an object of the reflective
0
When
A
is reflective we may so choose the left adjoint
£: ST--+ 1
that
satisfies
R2
lies in the repletion of A.
A
=
R,
idempotent monad on
is the identity. nR = Rn
B.
=
1.
Then
Such an
(R,n)
is called an
Conversely, for any idempotent monad
is formed as above, the full image is
uniquely determined by of
A·,
A.
8 --+ A
n: 1--+ R = TS: B--+ B
both its full image and its replete image are reflective in R
S:
A
again; but
The replete image of
(R,n),
B.
(R,n)
If is not
R is the repletion
and there is an evident bijection between full replete
reflective subcategories of monads on
B.
8
and isomorphism classes of idempotent
2. I
54
2.
Functor categories
2.1
So far we have supposed that
V
is symmetric monoidal closed,
and that the underlying ordinary category
v0
is locally small.
v
Henceforth we add the further assumption that
is complete, in the
0
sense that it admits all small limits; and from 2.5 on, we shall
v
suppose as well that Consider a
universal every
is cocomplete. 0
V-functor
T: A p ®A--+
V-natural family
V-natural
unique
0
V.
If there exists a
AA: K--+ T(A,A),
aA: X--+ T(A,A)
in the sense that
is given by
T·
we call (K,A) the end of
f: X---+ K,
= A~f
aA
'
it is clearly
unique to within a unique isomorphism when it exists.
JAEA T(A,A)
for the object
The
T:
then the universal
K
V-natural
may be called the counit of this end.
V-naturality condition (1.40), in the case
under the adjunction
We write
K, and by the usual abuse of language
also call this object the end of AA: fA T(A,A)--+ T(A,A)
for a
V0 (X,[Y,Z]) : V0 (X®Y,Z) AA
------=-=-----
~
B = V,
V0 (Y,[X,Z])
transforms into
T(A,A)
j PAB [A(A,B),T(A,B)]
where
and
It follows that, when
are the transforms of A is small, the end
exists, and is given as an equalizer
T(A,-)AB
( 2. 1)
and
JAcA T(A,A)
T(-,B)BA" certainly
(2.1)-(2.4)
JAEA
55 p
T(A,A) ~ lljAEA T(A,A) ~ ~A,BEA [A(A,B),T(A,B)] , If
A,
(2.2)
while not necessarily small, is equivalent to a small
V-category, then the full image in
A'
subcategory
A of the latter is a small full
for which the inclusion
A' --+A
is an equivalence.
A,B
Since it clearly suffices to impose (2.1) only for
JAEA T(A,A)
follows that
still exists, being
JAEA'
consequence, !Je henceforth change the meaning of
to include those
A',
it
T(A,A),
In
E
smaU", extending it
11
V-categories equivalent to small ones in the sense
of 1.2. The universal property of the end - expressed, as it stands, by a bijection of sets - in fact lifts to an isomorphism in sense that
[X,AA]: [x,JA T(A,A)]--+ [X,T(A,A)]
V0 ; in the
expresses its domain
as the end of its codomain:
[X,jA T(A,A)] ~fA [X,T(A,A)] For
Y--+ [X,T(A,A)]
is, by 1.8(m). if
JA
T(A,A)
on taking If
X
is
(2.3)
(with counit [X,AA]).
V-natural if and only if
Y ®X--+ T(A,A)
Note that the right side of (2.3) exists for all
X
exists; the converse of this is also true, as we see
=
I.
a: T--+ T':
A0 p ®A--+ V,
and if the ends of
T and
T'
exist, the top leg of the diagram !,A _ _ _..:.;___ _-+
fA
T' (A,A)
;.'
T(A,A)
T' (A,A) A
(2.4)
2. l
56
is
V-natural by (1.42); so that, by the universal property of
JA
there is a unique
aAA
A',
rendering the diagram commutative.
This "functoriality" of ends lifts, in the appropriate circumstances, to a
V-functoriality.
the end
HB
=fA
Suppose namely that, for exists for each
T(A,A,B)
one way of making H into a V-functor AAB: HB ->- T(A,A,B)
V-naturaZ in
For, by (1.39), the
T:
A0 P ® A® B --+ V,
Then there is exaatZy
B.
H: B--+
v
that renders
B as well as in
V-naturality in
B
A.
is expressed by the
commutativity of
B(B, C)
[HB,HC]
T(A,A,-)j
![l,AAC~ t'
[T(A,A,B), T(A,A,C)]
The bottom leg is
- - 7 r . , - - -,-.,],.------>
') AB' 1
V-natural in
then follow from the
The
(2.5)
A by 1.8(c), 1.8(e), and (1.43).
The right edge is itself an end by (2.3), the diagram commutative.
[HB,T(A,A,C)]
Hence a unique
HBC
renders
V-functor axioms (1.5) and (1.6) for
V-naturality of
M and
j
H
(1.8(g) and (h)),
the composition-calculus of 1.7, and the universal property of the counit
ll,,\J.
In these circumstances, if
fA
T(A,A,B)
is
V-naturaZ in
R: B--+ V, a family
s
8
:
RB--+
B if and pnZy if the composite
RB - -- > - fA T(A,A,B) 8
T(A,A,B)
B
ir. ~o.
One direction is trivial, while the other follows easily
(2.6)
(2.5)-(2.9)
57
from (2.5) and the universal property of the counit
[l,A].
In fact
this result can also be seen- using l.B(m) to view (2.6) as a V-natural family
I--+ [RB,T(A,A,B)]
and using (2.3) -as a special
case of the following. T: (A~ 8) p ~ (A~ 8) 0
Let 0
0
(A~ 6) p
=Ap
fAEA T(A,B,A,C) 8°p ~ in
B--+ V.
A
~ 6°P.
V, recalling that
--+
Suppose that, for each
B,C
6, the end
E
exists; then, as above, it is the value of a Every family
aAB: X--+ T(A,B,A,B)
that is
V-functor V-natural
factorizes uniquely as X ---~--+
68
fAEA
T(A,B,A,B)
T(A,B,A,B)
-------+
(2.7)
AABB
and it follows again from (2.5) and the universal property of that the
in
B
V-naturaZity in
of
B of aAB
is equivalent to the
[l,A]
V-naturaZity
s8 •
Since, by 1.7, coincides with its
Fubini Theorem:
V-naturality of V-naturality in
if every
fA
aAB
(A,B) E A
T(A,B,A,C)
f(A,B)EA~B T(A,B,A,B)
in
A and ~
B,
B separately we deduce the
exists, then
f BE B f AE A T(A,B,A,B),
(2.8)
either side existing if the other does. This in turn gives, since
A® B ~
6 ®A, the following
interchange of ends theorem, often itself called the Fubini Theorem: if every
fA
T(A,B,A,C)
and every
f AE A f BE B T(A,B,A,B)
fs
T(A,B,D,B)
fscB fAcA
either side existing if the other does.
exists, then
T(A,B,A,B)
(2.9)
2.2
58
2.2
For
V-functors
T,S: A--+
B we introduce the notation
fA
[A ,B](T ,S)
(2.10)
8 (TA,SA)
for the end on the right, whenever it exists; and we write the counit as
EA,TS We write
[A,BJ (T,S)
for the set
0
a: I--+ [A,B](T,S)
(2.11)
[A,BJ(T,S)--+ B(TA,SA)
of this end.
V[A,BJ(T,S)
of eZements
These of course correspond to
V-natural families EAr:~.:
( 2. 12)
I--+ B(TA,SA)
which by l.B(a) are precisely the
V-natural transformations
a: T-+S:A--+8.
Note that, by (2.3) and the adjunction
[X,[Y,Z]]-
[Y,~X,Z]],
we have [X,! A, VJ(T,S)]
either side When
existing for all [A,BJ(T,S)
X
E
V if the other does.
exists for all
T,S: A--+ B, as it surely does
by 2.1 i f A is small, i t is the hom-object of a with all the
T: A
--+
(2.13)
[A,VJ(T,[X,S-])
"¥
B as objects.
V-category
The composition law of
is, by 1.8(g), (1.43), and the universal property of uniquely determined by the commutativity of
.
EA TR,
[A,BJ [A,BJ
(2.10)-(2 .17)
59 M
[A,B](S,R)®[A,BJ(T,S)
[A,Bl(T ,R)
j
EA®E A
B(SA,RA)08(TA,SA) - - - - M ; - ; - - - - - > B(TA, RA)
(2.14)
and its identity elements are similarly determined by
(2.15) the axioms (1.3) and (1.4) follow at once from the corresponding axioms for
B and the universal property of We call
[A,B]
0
[A,BJ
EA.
the functor category; its underlying category
is by (2.12) the ordinary category of all
and all
V-functors
A--+ B
V-natural transformations between them - that is,
(2.16)
V-CAT(A,B) • Even when use
[A,BJ
[A,BJ 0
When
does not exist, it may sometimes be convenient to
as an abbreviation for [A,BJ
V-CAT(A,S). T ~ TA
exists, the function
of (2.11) constitute, by (2.14) and (2.15), a called evaluation at
EA: [A,BJ--+ B, functor underlying component
EA
sends a map
a
A. €
and the maps
EA,TS
V-functor
By (2.12), the ordinary
[A,B] 0 (T,S)
to its
aA·
There is a
V-functor
E: [A,BJ ® A --+ B, simply called
evaluation, whose partial functors are given by E(-,A)
EA: [A,BJ --+ B,
E(T,-)
T: A --+ B
(2.17)
2.2
60 To show this we must verify the appropriate instance of (1.21); but, by the proof of 1.8(c) read backwards, this instance reduces via (1.29) to the instance of (1.40) expressing the
More generally,
[A,BJ(T,S)
V-naturality in
may exist, not for
all those in some subset of the set of example would be the subset of those
V-functors A
~
B
A of
aZZ T,S, A
~
but for
B;
a typical
which are left Kan
extensions, in the sense of 4.1 below, of their restrictions to some fixed small full subcategory of
A.
Then we get as above a
V-category
[A,BJ'
with these functors as objects, whose underlying category
[A,B]~
is the corresponding full subcategory of
have the evaluation functor
E: [A,B]' ® A
--+
V-CAT(A,3);
B.
Still more generally, we may wish to consider for certain particular pairs
T,S
Yoneda isomorphism of 2.4 below.
and
V
®A~
D.
B such that
[A,B](T,S)
just
for which it exists - as in the To discuss its functoriality in this
generality, suppose we have functors Q:
and we
P: C ®
A~
[A,B](P(C,-) ,Q(D,-))
Then there is, by 2.1, a unique
B and
exists for each
V-functor
C
H: C0 p ® V ~ V
having H(C,D) with respect to which is
V-natural in
[A,BJ(P(C,-),Q(D,-))
(2.18)
EA: [A,B](P(C,-),Q(D,-)--+ B(P(C,A),Q(D,A))
C and
D as well as
A-
Moreover by (2.6)
(2.7), in the situations (the second of which has
V =C)
and
(2.18)-(2.22)
a
is
61
V-natural in
C
When
or even some
[A,BJ,
or
if and only if B is.
D
[A,BJ', exists, the
H of (2.18)
can be given more explicitly - see 2.3 below.
2.3 We return to the case where E: [A,8] ® A ~
[A,BJ
exists.
The
V-functor
B induces, for each V-category C, an ordinary
functor
V-CATCC,[A,BJ) sending
G: C
~
C and sending
[A,BJ
®
~
V-CATCC
®
A,B)
(2.20)
to the composite
A --G®::c-:--+ [A,BJ 1
®
8: G--+ G': C--+ [A,BJ
Clearly the map (2.20) is
2-natural in
A
--E-~
B
to the composite
C·,
(2.21)
E(B ® 1A).
and in fact it is an
isomorphism of categories. To prove this we must first show that every the form (2.21) for a unique
G.
P: C ® A
---+
B
Equating the partial functors of
has P
and (2. 21) gives
P(C,-)
GC,
The first of these determines asserts the commutativity of
(2.22)
G on objects, whereupon the second
2.3
62
rA,B](P(C,-),P(D,-))
C(C,!"l) P(- ,A) Cll
""~ B(P(C,A),P(D,A)) Since GCD
P(-,A)CD
is
V-natural in
A by 1.8(c), this determines a unique
by the universal property of
EA.
By this same universal property,
together with the composition-calculus of 1.7, the (1.5) and (1.6) for
V-functor axioms
follow at once from those for
G
(2.23)
P(-,A).
Before showing that (2.20) is bijective on maps as well as on objects, let us analyze the If
P: C
®
A
--+
G: C--+ [A,B]
B
and
Q:
V-functoriality (2.18) when
0
CA,BJ P
we have the composite
®
[A,BJ
---:::--------+
Hom[A,BJ and with respect to this, V-natural in
C and
D,
exists.
V ® A --+ B correspond by (2.20) to
F: V --+"[A,BJ,
and
[A,B]
V-functor
v
EA: [A,B](GC,FD) --+ B(EAGC,EAFD) by 1.7 and 1.8(b).
By (2.22), this
EA: [A,B](P(C,-),Q(D,-))--+ B(P(C,A) ,Q(D,A));
hence the
(2.24)
is EA
is
H of (2.18),
by its uniqueness, must be (2.24). To complete the proof that (2.20) is an isomorphism of categories, it remains to verify that, if of
G
and
S: G --+ G'. -form
G'
'
every
a: P
P and --+-
P'
P' is
By (2.22) the equation
aCA = EASe•
are the images under (2.20)
a
for a unique
= E(S
®
lA)
has the component-
which by (2.12) is
(2.25)
(2 .23)-(2 .25)
63
Be: GC--+ G'C
Thus
must be the
cxc_:
P(C,-)--+ P'(C,-);
that
Be· so defined, is
map
V-natural transformation
and the proof will be complete when we show
H
as a
Sc
is identified as (2.24).
More generally, [A,B]'
if
[A,BJ
does not exist but some full subcategory
does, in the sense of 2.2, we have by the same arguments an
isomorphism between the category subcategory of
V-CAT(C ® A,B)
for which each
P(C,-)
(2.24) with The
[A,BJ'
V-CATCC.[A,BJ')
lies in
[A,B]';
replacing
then
[A,BJ
replaced by --+
and
C(0,1)
V(T,S)
B;
V,
0.
l,
with
C
when it exists,
V-CAT(-®A,B).
It is
C
to be
V - at least if
I
we identify the objects of to be the
X of
V
0
in (2.20), with
V
with the
V,
has an [A,B]
V-functors
V-category with two objects
C(O,O) = C(l,l) =I,
an arbitrary object
=fA
2-functor
[A,BJ,
2-functor is representable by some
For taking
while taking
A --+ B
®
[A,BJ.
exists and is isomorphic to
initial object
P: C
for we have the analogue of
2-natural isomorphism (2.20) exhibits
conversely true that, if this
and the full
determined by those
as a representing object for the
0
I f we look on
I--+ [A,BJ(GC,G'C), this follows from 1. 8 (m) and (2.19), now
that
A
c.
V-natural in
V,
with
C(l,O) = 0,
and with
we easily see that
B(TA,SA).
It follows from 1.10 that, so far as it exists, 2-functorial in
A and
B
in such a way that (2.20) is
every variable; which by 1.9 is equivalent to the each variable of
[A,BJ
E: [A,BJ ® A
--+
B.
is uniquely
2-natural in
2-naturality in
Using this latter criterion
2.3
64
we easily see that, for [M,N]: [A,BJ --~ [A',B'J
M: A '
A an d
--+
sends
T
to
N··
NTM
B --+ B'
,
the
V-functor
and is determined on
hom-objects by [M,N]TS
[A' ,B'](NTM,NSM)
[A,B](T,S)
i E'A
l
while the
(2.26)
B' (NTMA,NSMA)
B(TMA,SMA)
V-natural transformation
[u,v]: [M,N]--+ [M' ,N'J
is
given by '· Tu: NTI1 -~ :,; 'T'1'
As for the interplay of functor have a
cat~gories
( 2. 2 7)
.
with duality, we clearly
2-natural isomorphism (2.28)
either side existing if the other does. The when
2-functor -®A: V-CAT--+ V-CAT
[A,B]
exists for
has an initial object.
a~~
B;
has a right adjoint
This right adjoint surely exists when
For instance, a result of Freyd
V = Set,
A is necessarily small if
an ordered set, as in the cases for every
A and
B.
v
and by the above, only then, if
small, in the extended sense of 2.1; and for many then.
[A,-]
(see [A, lfJ
v=2
and
V
[73]) exists.
v = R+'
0
A
is
it exists only shows that, when Yet when [A,BJ
v0
exists
is
(2 .26)- (2. 31)
65
In this sense the symmetric monoidal
2-category
"partially closed"; while the synunetric monoidal of small
V-CAT is
2-category
V-Cat
V-categories is actually closed.
The partial closedness is sufficient to imply the isomorphisms (1.26) and (1.27) of 1.5, which here read: [I ,BJ ~
B ,
[C ® A,BJ
~
[C,[A,BJJ ,
(2.29)
the latter in the sense that either side exists if the other does, provided
[A,BJ
exists - which follows alternatively from the
Fubini Theorem (2.8).
2.4 We can now give a stronger version of the Yoneda Lemma of 1.9, no longer expressed by a mere bijection of sets, but by a Yoneda
isomorphism in Given a
v. 0
V-functor
1.9, we have the map in
A by 1.8(b).
FKA
in
A by 1.8(m).
expresses
V-natural
(2.30)
FK----+ [A(K,A),FA]
V (X,[Y,Z]) 0
~
V (Y,[X,Z]) 0
is
V-natural
The stronger Yoneda Lemma is the assertion that (2.30)
as the end ~:
FK
JA [A(K,A),FA], so that we have an isomorphism ~
(2. 31)
[A,VJ(A(K,-),F) •
For the proof, consider any transform
which is
The transform
under the adjunction
FK
V and an object K of A as in
FKA: A(K,A) --+ [FK,FA],
~A:
of
F: A --+
aA: A(K,A) --+ [X,FA]
V-natural
aA: X--+ [A(K,A),FA];
under the adjunction, being
its
2.4
66 V-natural in
for a unique (1.48). unique
A by
1.8(m), is the composite
A(K,A)
-----+
FKA
n: X--+ FK,
[FK,FA]
by the Yoneda Lemma of 1.9 in the form
This is equivalent to the assertion that n;
V = V (I,-): V0
A(K,-)--+ F,
--+
0
V0 (I,FK)--+ [A,V] 0 (A(K,-),F).
or
aA =¢An
for a
which completes the proof.
The image under
~n:
[n,l]' [X,FA]
This sends
whose component
n: I--+ FK
A(K,A)--+ FA
By the definition (2.30) of
the composite (1.47).
Set of (2.31) is a bijection
is
to EA~Tl
by (2.12),
¢A, this is at once seen to be
Hence the weak Yoneda Lemma of 1.9, which we
have used to prove the present strong Yoneda Lemma, is subsumed under the latter as its underlying bijection. The special case
F = A(L,-): A--+ V of the present Yoneda Lemma
strengthens the last assertion of 1.9 to
A ( L. K) -
I A.
v
I
(A ( K,-) 'A I L'-) I
(
Since (2.31) is true without any smallness restriction 0n
V-naturality must in general be discussed (cf. 2.2) in terms of
the
V-functor
P: C 0 A--+
0
V.
0
A--+ V
and some
V-functor
We_assert that ¢CK: P(C,K) - [A,V1(A(K,-),P(C,-))
ts
V-natural -:n
as in (2.18).
32)
A,
its
HomA: A p
~.
C and
K,
when the right side is made
This follows form (2.19); for
(2.33) V-functorial
(2.32)-(2.38)
67
EA¢ =¢A: P(C,K) l.B(m), since When
[A(K,.:\) ,P(C,A)] is V-natural in
A(K,A)--+ [P(C,K),P(C,A)]
[A,VJ
(2.20) to a
--+
exists,
0
HomA: A
p
C and
K by
is so by l.B(b) and l.B(c).
®A--+ V
corresponds under
V-functor
(2. 34)
sending
K to
YK
A(K,-)
(2.35)
Y is called the Yoneda embedding.
being fully faithful by (2.32), In these circumstances the
V-naturality (2.33) can be more globally
expressed by taking
for
[A,VJ
C and E: [A,V] ® A --+ V for P;
the right side of (2.33) is then by (2.24) the value of the V-functor
v
A® [A,VJ
(2.36)
so that, with respect to this functoriality,
the Yoneda isomorphism (2.31) is
V-natural in K and
F.
(2.37)
The extra-variable result of 1.9 also has a lifting to the present context.
Let
0
F: B p ® A
we have an isomorphism C and
B.
F(C,KB)
~
--+
V and
K: B
--+
A.
By (2.33)
[A,V](A(KB,-),F(C,-)), V-natural in
The Fubini Theorem (2.8) now gives
jB
F(B,KB)
~
[8°P ® A,VJ(A(K?,-),F(?,-))
either side existing if the other does.
(2.38)
2.5
68
2.5 We henceforth suppose, in addition to all our former assumptions V
V, that the underlying category
on
Then the ordinary functor
• I,
adjoint
Set
The
X
0
V0
--+
E to the coproduct
E· I
of
E
This functor sends the cartesian product in
F) • I
-
2-functor
: 0
,
®
(F • I)'
0
(E • I)
)
V
in that we clearly have 1 • I
has the same objects as L,
=
( 2. 39)
I.
now has a left adjoint
V-CAT--+ CAT
>v . The free V-category LV on the ordinary L
Set has a left
0
to the tensor product in (E
V (I,-):
=
sending the set
V •
in
I
copies of
V
ie cocompZete.
0
ZocaZZy-s~aZZ
and has hom-objects
category
Lv(K,L) = L(K,L) ·I;
its composition Zaw and its identities are induced from those of
L
using the isomorphisms (2.39), For the proof, we have first to verify that satisfies the
LV, as defined,
V-category axioms (1.3) and (1.4); this is trivial
from the corresponding axioms for
L.
There is an evident functor \jJ : L--+ (l )
v
0
which is the identity
on objects, and which is defined on morphisms by the obvious map L(K,L)--+ V (I,L(K,L) • I). 0
This
\jJ
is the unit of the
2-adjunction
in question. In fact it is easy to see that, for a functor with
T: L--+B
To\jJ = T:
o'
there is exactly one
on objects we have
TK
~
TK,
V-category V-functor while
B
and a
T: Lv
--+
B
(2.39)-(2.40) TKL: L(K, L) • I TKL: L(K,L)
69 ----+-
--+
B(TK, TL)
B (TK,TL)
is the transform of under the adjunction
0
Verification of (1.5) and (1.6) for Finally, if a.: T-+-
a.K
E
T
a.: T-+- S: L-+- 8
0
S: LV--+ B
with
is easy.
,
there is a unique
a. 1/J = a.; the component 0
80 (TK,SK), and again verification of (1.7) for
V-natural
a.K
must be
a.
is easy.
This completes the proof. If
L is a small category, LV is clearly a small
and we can form the functor category ordinary category
CLV,B]
0
[LV,B].
Since the underlying
V-CAT(LV,B)
of this is
V-category,
by (2.16),
the
2-adjunction above gives (2.40)
2.6 The possible non-existence of a
V-functor-category
[A,BJ
when
A is large (= non-small) is somewhat tedious, forcing us into such circumlocations as using (2.18) instead of (2.24), or (2.33) instead of (2.37) - which then propagate themselves throughout the applications below. Yet when
V = Set,
albeit not in general a when
A and
B are
however be seen as a
we always do have
as a category;
Set-category (= locally-small category)
Set-categories, unless Set'-category, where
sets in some larger universe containing are taking the view that
[A,BJ
obA
obA
A is small. Set'
It can
is the category of
as an element - we
is always an honest set, and supposing
that every set belongs to some universe.
2.6
70
We may ask whether such a view can be imitated for a general Consider first the various examples of a symmetric monoidal closed
2
ordered set, such as A;
V
or
0
R+'
or
V0
either
These are of two types:
given in 1.1.
v. v
is a particular
[A, m exists for all
in which case
consists of the smaU models of some theory - small sets,
small categories, small abelian groups, small differential graded R-modules, and so on.
V' 0
category
In the latter case we can clearly consider the
of models in a larger
monoidal closed category
V ',
Set',
which gives a symmetric
V
in which
closed structure is faithfully embedded.
with its symmetric monoidal
Moreover
V ' admits all
limits and colimits which are small by reference to
V0
inclusion
V0 •
--+
V0 '
0
Set';
and the
preserves all limits and colimits that exist in
(We are supposing that our
origina~
universe contains infinite
sets; otherwise we do not have the colimit-preservation above.) Then, for [A,B],
V0
--+
where
V0
'
V-categories
Set'
A
and
B, we always have a V'-category
is taken large enough to include
preserves limits, to say that
[A.B](T,S)
sense of 2.2 is precisely to say that the object actually lies in
V;
2.2 - that is, as a all
and to say that
obA.
[A,B]
exists in the
[A,BJ(T,S)
of
V'
exists in the sense of
V-category- is to say that
[A,B](T,S)
E
V
for
T ,S.
That a similar thing is possible for a perfectly general follows from Day
[17].
V
Using his construction, one can show that
there is always a suitable II0 '
Since
II'
whose underlying ordinary category
is a full reflective subcategory of
[ V op Set' J 0
'
'
is embedded by Yoneda.
Since the monoidal structure of
by eornds (relative to
Set'),
into which
V'
V
0
is defined
we defer a description of it until 3.11
and 3.12 below, after these have been introduced.
( 3. 1)
3.
71
Indexed limits and colimits
3.1
For a discussion of completeness, or of Kan extensions, or of
density, in the context of
V-categories, ordinary limits - defined
in terms of the representability of cones - do not suffice; we need the wider notion of indexed limit.
These latter fully deserve the name
of "limit", since they enjoy all the formal properties expected of a limit-notion, and include the classical cone-type limits as a special case.
When V
= Set,
V,
in contrast to the situation for a general
an indexed limit may be expressed as an ordinary limit; yet even here, the indexed limit is a valuable concept in its own right - its meaning is scarcely clarified by its construction as an ordinary limit.
Since
the cone-type limits have no special position of dominance in the general case, we go so far as to call indexed limits simply "limits", where confusion seems unlikely. We may think of a a small one when
V-functor
F: K --+ V as an indexing type -
K is small, which will be the usual case, but not
the only one.
Then we may think of a
diagram in
of type
V-functor
B
B(B,G-):
of the object
For each
K --+ V;
B
E
B,
G:
K --+ B as a
we get from
G a
and we can consider the existence in
[K,VJ(F,B(B,G-)).
surely does when V-functor
F.
V-functor
If this exists for all
B
V
as it
K is small- it is as in (2.18) the value of a
B0 p--+
V.
If this
V-functor not only exists but admits a
representation B(B,{F,Gj) - [K,V](F,B(B,G-))
with counit say
( 3. 1)
J. 1
)1:
(3 .2)
F __,. B({F,G},G-) , G indexed by
({F,G},Jl) the limit of
we call the representation
An evidently equivalent formulation not mentioning is the following:
each component B(B,{F,G})
V-natural in
B
and
(3.3) is an end over
K·'
JlK
----+
of
K for each
B.
induces by Yoneda a family (3.3)
is the limit precisely when
In practice, by the usual abuse
of notation, we call the representing object to the background the counit
explicitly
[FK,B(B,GK)]
({F,G} ,Jl)
and
Jl
[K,VJ
F.
{F,G}
the limit, consigning
or equivalently the choice of the
Jl
V-natural isomorphism (3.1). If we take the view of 2.6, that a
V-category, then as a
[K,VJ
always exists, if not as
V',
V'-category for some larger
be concerned with the existence of
[K,VJ(F,B(B,G-)),
representability in the form (3.1) for some
{F,G}
E
but only with its
B.
representable, the right side of (3.1) in fact lies in left side does.
we need not
If it is so
V,
since the
We shall in future take this view whenever it is
convenient - usually without bothering to change "V-functor" to
"V '-functor", and so on. Applying
V
to the isomorphism (3.1) gives a bijection of sets
B0 (B,{F,G}) but the requirement that
~
[K,VJ (F,B(B,G-)) ; 0
( 3. 4)
({F,G},Jl) induce·a bijection (3.4) is, except
requirement that i t induce an isomorphism (3.1), and doPs not suffice to
make
({F,G},IJ)
t11f? limit; see 3.7 below.
However i t does suffice to
(3.2)-(3.8)
detect
73
({F,G},~)
as the Zimit if the ~imit is known to exist; for
the right side of (3.4) admits at most one representation to within isomorphism.
a: F --+ B(B,G-)
An element
may be called an
(F,B)-cyZinder ove~
G;
of the right side of (3.4) then the bijection (3.4)
is the assertion that every such cylinder factorizes through the counit-cylinder
An
u
as
B( f, 1)
indexed coZimit
in
but it is usual to replace
G: K --+ B,
still have
of G indexed by
F
\.1
for a unique
f: B
---->- { F,
G}.
B is nothing but an indexed limit in
K
by
K0 p
but now have
B0 p;
in the definition, so that we
F: K0 p
--+
V. F
is the representing object
Then the co~imit
* G
in
(3.5)
with unit
(3.6) When
B
V,
we have from (2.13) and (3.1)
{F,G}
= [K,V](F,G)
either side existing if the other does.
for
F,G:
K--+ V
(3. 7)
Hence (3.1) and (3.5) can be
written
B(B,{F,G}) - {F,B(B,G-)},
B(F*G,B)
~
{F,B(G-,B)}
( 3. 8)
Thus, just as classical limits and colimits in an ordinary category
B
are defined, via representability, in terms of the primitive limits sets of cones - in
Set,
so indexed limits and colimits in a
V-category
B are defined, via representability, in terms of indexed limits in
V;
and thus ultimately, by 2.1 and 2.2, in terms of ordinary limits in
v0 .
3. l
74
Again, in the special case ['FK,[GL,B]] ~ [GL,[FK,B]]
the
V-natural isomorphism
gives by (3.5)
for The
B = V,
F:
0
K P --+ V and
(3.9)
K--+ V
G:
V-natural Yoneda isomorphism (2.33) immediately gives the
values of
{F,G} and
F
* G when F is representable, for any
K--+ B; namely
G:
{K(K,-),G}
~
More precisely, the cylinder exhibits
GK
as
K(-, K)
GK,
*
GK_: K(K,-) --+ B(GK,G-)
{K(K,-),G}.
(3. 10)
G ;; GK •
~s
counit
We refer to (3.10) as Yoneda isomorphisms;
by (3.7), the first of them includes as a special case the original Yoneda isomorphism (2.31). When
K
is small, the maps
(F,G)
are by 1.10 the object-functions of 0
{,}: ([K,VJ P ® [K,BJ)'--+
r---+
(F,G) f---+ F
B,
0
*: ([K P ,V] (F,G)
®
(F,G).
for which
We call the limit
V-natural in
or
V-natural
if
K and
G.
(3.12)
{F,G} a sma~~ limit if the indexing-type
K--+ V is small; that is, if K is small.
B eomplete
{F,G}
(3.11)
Then (2.37) gives:
The Yoneda isomorphisms (3.10) are
3.2
* G
[K,BJ)' --.. B ,
* G exists; and in such a way that (3.1) and (3.5) are
in
F:
and
V-functors
where the domain consists of those pairs F
{F,G}
We call the
V-category
it admits all small limits; and, dually, cocomp~ete i f
it admits all small colimits.
By (3.7) and 2.2,
V is complete;
shall see in 3. 10 below that V is also cocomplete.
we
(3.9)-(3.15)
75 T: B--->- C
A V-functor
is said to prese!'Ve the limit
{F,G}
if
the composite cylinder
F ~ 8({F,G},G-) ~ C(T{F,G},TG-) ~
where
is the counit of
in other words, if
{F,G},
exhibits
T{F,G}
(3.13)
as
{F,TG};
exists and if the evident canonical map
{F,TG}
T{F,G}---->- {F,TG}
(3.14)
is an isomorphism.
We call preserves all
T: B---->- C continuous (the dual is cocontinuous) if it
smaZZ limits that exist; of course this condition is of
interest particularly when The representables
B is complete.
B(B,-): B--+ V are more than continuous:
by (3.8) they preserve every limit that exists; while in their totality, by definition, they "detect" the existence of
{ F, G}.
For a very general result on the preservation of limits, consider a functor those
Q: Cop B
0
B--+ V, and let B' c B be the full subcategory of
for which
Q(-,B)
is representable, say as
we shall refer to the objects of Let
{F,G}
for each
be a limit in C.
its values in
Finally, let
B'.
B
~
C(C,TB);
B' as "those B for which TB exists".
which is preserved by
TG
Q(C,B)
Q(C,-):
exist; that is, suppose that
B--+ V G takes
Then we clearly have T{ F, G} - { F, TG} ,
(3.15)
3.2
76 either side existing if the other does; for, using (3.7), the two sides of (3.15) represent the isomorphic ~
[K,VJ(F,C(C,TG)) If then
T:
~
[K,VJ(F,Q(C,G-))
Q here is defined by
B'
V-functors
exist.
and
{F,Q(C,G-)}.
Q(C,B)
= B(SC,B)
S: C--+
where
--+ C is the partial right adjoint of
preserves all limits, we have (3.15) whenever TG
Q(C,{F,G})
Since
S.
{F,G},
T{F,G},
B,
B(SC,-) and
partial right adjoints,
This conclusion may be expressed as:
in so far as they are defined, preserve limits. In the special case where
S
right adjoints preserve aZZ Zimits that exist.
the conclusion becomes:
3.3 We now consider limits in a functor category G: --+
K--+ [A,BJ
B.
B--+ C,
in fact has a right adjoint T:
correspond under
th~
[A,BJ.
adjunction (2.20) to
Let
P: K ®A
In order to avoid formulae containing various letters whose
inter-relation must be explained in a subordinate clause, let us write
(2.22) with cyphers for variables, in the form in particular, Then, if [A,BJ
(G-)A
denotes
{F,(G-)A}
P(-,A):
exists for
P(-,?) =(G-)?;
K--+ B.
e~oh
A,
Let
F:
the limit
so that,
K--+ V. in
{F,G}
exists, and we have {F,G}A
For, if we define
{F,G}
given by (3.16), we have
to be the
{F,(G-)A} . V-functor whose value at
(3.16) A
is
( 3. 16)
77
fA
[A,8](H, {F ,G})
-fA
B(HA,{F,(G-)A})
by (3.16)
[K,V](F,B(HA,(G-)A))
by (3.1)
fA
- [K,VJ(F,
B(HA,(G-)A)) by (2.3)
[K,VJ(F,[A,BJ(H,G-))
by (2.10) .
In these circumstances we say that the limit
{F,G}
exists pointwise; it comes to the same thing to say that and is preserved by each
[resp. cocomplete]
existing pointwise in When in
[A,BJ,
B
all small limits
[A,BJ,
[A,BJ
exists
{F,G}
Clearly if B is complete
EA: [A,BJ --+B.
so is
in
[resp. colimits]
[A,BJ.
is not complete, fortuitous non-pointwise limits may exist
even when
V =Set.
Take
A= 2
and let
B be the category
generated by the graph
with the relation
hf • hg.
Then the map _ _ _f=-_
(f,h): g--+ h
given by
_,.
h
g
------+
h
in x
[2,BJ
is monomorphic, although
h
is not monomorphic in
is monomorphic in any category precisely when
B.
Since
3.3
78 . __!__ _ _,.
X
is a pullback, the pullback of -pointwise limit.
[A,BJ
B·,
by itself in
is a non-
[2,8]
The existence of a non-pointwise limit in
[A,BJ
says something about
A and
(f,h)
[A,BJ
as a category, ignoring its relation to
while the existence of a pointwise limit says something about
seen precisely as the functor category, and is really a
completeness assertion about
E.
[K,V]
Applying the above, in the colimit case, to
where
K is
small, we get from (3.9) and (3.10) a pointwise colimit
F
K--+ V,
*
y
(3.17)
F '
for any
F:
(2.34).
This gives a canonical expression of any
(indexed) colimit of representables. limits exist in for
K0 p--+ [K,V=
Y being the Yoneda embedding
E Y ~ K(-,K): K P K
--+
poin~ise
K--+ Vas an
F:
Y preserves ~hatever
In contrast,
sending them to 0
of
limits
i~
V.
We can now give the general Fubini Theorem relating repeated limits to double limits.
Suppose that
latter corresponding.to
P: K ®A--+ B,
exists pointwise; and let
for the functor sending
F: K --+ V and
H: A --+ V. (K,A)
to
G: K
--+ ~A,B~,
are such that the limit Writing
FK
® HA~
{F
®
F
®
H: K
®
the {F,G}
A --+ V
we have a canonical
isomorphism (H,{F,G}}
either side r.xisting if
th~
=
other does.
H,P\
(3.18)
(3.17)-(3.19)
79
For by (3.1) the left side of (3.18) represents [A,VJ(H?,B(B,{F,G}?)),
= [A,V](H?,B(B,{F-,(G-)?}))
by (3.16)
= [A,VJ(H?,[K,V](F-,B(B,(G-)?)))
by (3.1)
I A [HA, f [ FK,B(B, (GK)A)]] K
by (2.10)
-
I A f K [HA,[FK,B(B,(GK)A)]]
by (2.3)
-
I I
by ( 1.27)
[HA
®
FK,B(B,P(K,A))]
A K
I I
and by the Fubini Theorem (2.8) we can replace
here by
A K
f
(A,K)'
giving by (2.10) and (3.1) the object represented by the right side of (3.18). The use of the cyphers "?" and "-" here to keep track of unexpressed variables is presumably self-explanatory. it by allowing
{F-,G-}
If we extend
as an alternative notation for
can write (3.18), suppressing the letter (H?, (F-,P(-, ?) I 1
(H?
®
G,
as
F-,
P(-,?))
{F,G},
we
(3.19)
Then there is no need for explicit mention of the functor category [A,BJ,
which may exist only as a
V'-category in the sense of 2.6; nor
for explicit mention of the pointwise existence of just the existence of
{F-,P(-,A)}
{F,G},
for each value of
A.
which is
3.3
80
In this notation the general Fubini Theorem gives at once the
generaZ interchange of limits theorem: and
P: K ®A~ B;
A and that
and suppose that
Let
{F-,{H?,P(-,?)}}
K.
H:
A-
V,
exists for each
{F-,P(-,A)}
exists for each
{H?,P(K,?)}
K --+ V,
F:
Then (3.20)
{H?,{F-,P(-,?)}},
=
either side existing if the other does. 0
F: K p ~
For the colimit form of (3.19) and (3.20), let H:
A0 p
~
V,
P: K
and
®A--+ B;
F- * (H? * P(-,?))
then, under similar hypotheses,
(F ®H)* P =
=
V,
H?
*
(3.21)
(F- * P(-,?))
In fact (3.20) also follows alternatively from the general principle of (3.15); for the right side of (3.1) clearly preserves rointwise limits in the variable
G
E
[K,B].
FE [K,VJ,
In the variable
the right side of (3.1) sends
arbitrary colimits, by (3.8), to limits; of course all smal: colimits in
[K,VJ are pointwise, since we have remarked that
Hence we get from the principle (3.15) the general
to be cocomplete.
theorem of the continuity of a limit in its in~qx: G: K--+ [A,VJ, tJ~t
each
T: A--+ B;
and
{GK,T}
exists.
and supp0se that
=
and
T
F: K0 P
--+
V,
F * G exists and
{F,{G-,T}}
eithf'r eide existing if thq other do•:s. F
Let
Then
{F * G,T}
culimits, with
V will be shown
(3. 22)
The corresponding form for
as above but now with
0
G: K--+ [A P,ll], is
(3.20)-(3.27)
81 (F
*
*
G)
T
F
* ( G- *
T) •
(3. 2 3)
In future, when we equate limits in a general theorem, the phrase "either side existing if the other does" is to be understood.
3.4 We now consider,in the special case V
Set, the relation of indexed
limits to the ordinary classical limits. Writing
6B:
K --~ B for the constant functor at BE B, we have a
natural bijection [K,B](t1B,G)
=
[K,Set](LI1,B(B,G-))
between the set of (projective) cones over set of cones over
B(B,G-)
G with vertex
with vertex the one-point set 1.
or classical, or conical limit representing object
(3.24)
[resp. colimit]
lim G [resp. colim G]
of
B and the The ordinary,
G: K --~ B is the
in
B(colim G, B) - [ K,BJ (G,11B),
B(B,lim G) - [K,B](AB,G),
existing when the right side here is representable.
(3.25)
Using (3.24) we
conclude from (3.1) and (3.5) that lim G
{61 ,G},
colim G
K --> B, often called
Thus the classical limit of
G:
K,
G indexed by
is in fact the limit of
111
Al:
*
( 'J. 26)
G. a limit indexed by
K--+ Set.
Of course the
counit (3.2) now corresponds to the limit-cone lim G--+ GK .
~k:
Set,
taking
t
=
(3.27)
in the first cqualion of (J.25) gives
3.4
82 lim r.
!K ,Set }(I'll, G)
Z'
for
G: K
--+
(3.28)
Set ,
so that here the limit ie the set of cones with vertex l.
Then, as we said
in 3.1, all conical limits and colimits are defined representably in terms of these primitive ones in
Set;
for (3.24) and (3.28) allow us to re-
-write (3.25) in the form (analogous to(3.8)) B(B,lim G) = lim B(B,C-), Now consider an arbitrary
eZ
category K
E
F
K and x
f: K--+ K'
of elements of
E
in
functor sending
FK,
B(colim G,B) =lim
F: K F,
(K,x)
to
K,
l~e
Set.
(K,x)----> (K',x')
(Ff)x = x'.
Write
G: K
and let
---->
(3.29)
have as in 1.10 the
whose objects are pairs
and whose maps
K for which
---->
B(c~,B).
Set
with
are the e~
d:
(K,x)
F--+
K for the
be arbitrary.
Then
we have
lim (
eZ
F~
K ~Set)
~
tK,Set](F,C) .
For an element of the left side is by (3.28) a cone give such a cone is to give for each of
GK;
and the naturality of
naturality of
Cl
X
E
FK
(3. 30)
a(K,x): 1
an element
(:
X
K
---->
GK;
to
= a (K, x)
as a cone translates exactly into the
SK: FK----> GK.
Since a map of a representable Yoneda to an element
x
E
FK,
K(K,-)
into
F
corresponds by
we have a canonical inductive cone
(3.31)
in
LK,SetJ
whose base is indexed by
the expressibility of an!!
F: K----> Set
(al F) 0 P.
The classical result on
as a aanonicaZ (conicat) aolimit
of representabZes is the assertion that this is a colimit-cone; more precisely,
(3. 2 8)- (3. 34)
83
=
F
colim ((e~ F) p----+ ~P ----+Y [K,Set]) , dop 0
with unit (3.31), where
Y
is the Yoneda embedding.
(3.32)
This follows from
(3.30) and the characterization (3.29) of the colimit, since the left side of (3.30) is also
lim[K,Set](Yd 0 P-,G)
by Yoneda.
Because indexed limits are continuous in their index in the sense F ~ colim K(K,-)
of (3.22), the colimit-expression for any
G:
of (3.32) gives,
K--+ B, a limit-expression {F,G} =lim {K(K,-),G};
so that
by the Yoneda isomorphism (3.10) we have {F,G}
eZ
lim (
F ~ K ~ 8)
(3.33)
,
of which (3.30) is a special case by (3.7).
V = Set,
We conclude that, when
the classical conical limits are
special cases of indexed limits by (3.26), while the general indexed limit can be expressed as a conical limit by (3.33).
K is small, a Set-category
Since
eZ F is small when
B is complete in our sense of 3.2 above
exactly when it admits aZZ smalZ conical Zimits - that is, when it is complete in the classical sense.
functor
T:
It follows in the same way that the
B-+ C is continuous in our sense of
3.2 above exactly when it
preserves aZl emaZl conical limite. For
F: ~p
--+
Set
and
G: K
--+
B,
the corresponding colimit-
-form of (3.33) is
F * G We had in (3.17), for any as a colimit
F
0
colim (( el F) p
V,
(3.34)
K---+ 8) • G
the general expression of any
F:
K --+ V
* Y of representables; observe that when we use (3.34)
3.4
84 to evaluate that, when
*
F
Y in the case
B =Set,
V =Set,
~1:
components of
K--+ Set
K,
Note too
there is a second expression (3.34) for
since this is then isomorphic to colimit of
were-find (3.32).
G
* F by (3.9).
is clearly the set
taking
G
= ~1
F
*
G,
Finally, since the
n(K)
of connected
in (3.34) and using (3.26) and (3.9)
gives TI(
colim F
el
for
F)
F:
(3.35)
K--+ Set .
We conclude this section with some remarks about conservativeness and faithfulness for ordinary functors
equalizers and T preserves equalizers, conservative; for if T
Tf
=
Tg,
B.
n,e: S
First, if
A has
T is faithful if it is
the equalizer of
Next, if
to an isomorphism.
T: A --+
f
and
g
is sent by
--1 T: A--+ B is an adJunction,
T is faithful if and only if each
eA: STA--+ A is an epimorphism;
this is immediate from (1.53), for
!AA'
each
A(eA,A')
is.
Finally, if T
is a monomorphism exactly when
is a right adjoint as above, and if
A admits equalizers, then T is conservative if
and only if each
£A
is an extremal epimorphism (one that factorizes through no proper subobject of its codomain). To prove this, first note that any through no proper subobject of exist.
Suppose then that
factorizes through a 1: TA--+ TA
T
f:
A~
B is an epimorphism, because equalizers is conservative.
~onomorphism
i: B--+ A,
If
i
is.
Conversely, let each
epimorphism; then, by the remark above,
T
f: A--+ B
Tf
is surely a monomorphism if
£A: STA--+ A
then (by the adjunction)
factorizes through the monomorphism
isomorphism, whence
B in A which factorizes
Ti;
hence
Ti
is an
be an extremal
is faithful,
so that
is an isomorphism.
But
(3.35)
85
in this case, by the naturality of that
f
E, we have
EB = f.EA.(STf)-1;
so
is an isomorphism.
V, we now consider some properties
3.5 Returning to the case of a general
of (indexed) limits in relation to fully faithful functors.
A fully faithful for F:
J: A --+ B refleats limits; in the sense that,
K --+ V and G: K --+ A,
A as the limit
{F,G}
in
F --+ A(A,G-) --+ B(JA,JG-)
a cylinder
expresses
it is the assertion that
{F,JG},
If the full subcategory
JA
as the limit
if it lies in
~:
B(JS{F,JG},JG-)
By 3.4, the cylinder f: JS{F,JG} we have of
A,
--+
fn = 1.
~
{F,JG}; Hence
A,
~
factorizes as
exists,
B
and
By (1.48) the
B({F,JG},JG-) B(f,1) ~
is
B(n,1).
for a unique
and by the uniqueness part of the same result {F,JG}
is a retract of the object
and so by 1.11 lies in the repletion of
fuZZ subaategory
{F,JG}
which is therefore
F--+ B({F,JG},JG-).
A(S{F,JG},G-)
B(n,1)- 1 ~
B.
in
is also
n,1: S --4 J: A--+
To see this, let the adjunction be
isomorphism
A,
A here is reflective, and
let the counit of the limit be
{F,JG}
A is a full subcategory of
then the latter is isomorphic to an object of {F,G}.
expresses
A whenever the composite cylinder
This is immediate; and in the case where
B,
F--+ A(A,G-)
A.
A of B is alosed under limits,
JS{F,JG}
Thus a refZeative
and in partiaular is
aompZete if B is so. As for colimits in this reflective situation, if the colimit exists,
S
preserves it by 3.2, giving
S(F
particular, therej1eative fuZZ subaategory
B os.
*
JG) = F
A of
*
SJG
=F *
F
* JG
G. In
B is aoaompZete if
3.5
86 Consider now a family in a
B,
subcategory of
such that each
B,
V-category
= (F y :Ky op
¢
with the property that, if any
Fy
*
A
called the aZosuroe of
c.
lies in
¢
-type in
F; then
type
A
If
C containing
A
c,
F=
lF 0
in the
v to be conservative,
be a strong generator for
It is of course true for
vo'
V
= Set,
v0;
i t is
and for
for instance, sets on which a commutative monoid
acts, with a tensor product analogous to that for modules over a commutative ring, Hhat is true when any
X
E
V , 0
V is conservative, by Proposition 3.41, is that
although not the canonical colimit of the maps from .I,
3.9
98
f I}
is in all reasonable cases in the closure of it is, so to speak, an
iterated colimit of
I.
under small colimi ts;
In this case an
F: K ~ V is an iterated colimit of representables; and so
arbitrary
B does imply the existence
the existence of all small conical limits in
{F,G},
of all indexed limits
as we shall show formally in 3.10 below-
{F,G} cannot be expressed as a single conical limit.
even though
In the study o: enriched universal algebra, it is an important
Cat
observation that, for many
V
isomorphism whenever
left exact; see
F
is
including
Gpd,
and
(3.56) is
an
[45].
Before ending this section, we look at the possible existence in certain cases of more general conical limits.
The notion of a cone
involves the notion of a constant functor; yet in general there is no such thing as "the object
B
B may be seen as a
E
canonical
K--+ I;
V-functor
There is certainly a unique terminal
1(0,0), --+
V
I
K
V-functor
~~.
I
CGTop*,
S,
K--+
of
0
E
B ".
The
but there is no
V
0
where
but there is no
;
V
in
is the
V-functor
which is false for
0
and so on.
conical limits as above, taking for
1,
and with, for hom-object
is a retract of
DG-R-~~od,
= R-Mod,
B
in fact there may well be none at all.
V-functor
the terminal object
I
V-functor
V-category with one object
unless
B constant at
This is why we have defined
K a free
there are always constant ordinary functors
V-category
L
--+
LV;
for
B • 0
Yet in the special case of
cart£?$ian closed
other cases as well), it happens that V-categories 11
l'eser>ve this right Kan extension if
P~·
P: B
exhibits
~
PT
V as
is said Ra~PG.
Obviously:
Propositi on 4.14
P
pr>eserves thr riaht i:a;~ cxk"lsio;z
only if P preserves the limit
{KC,G}
for a?"
c.
Ra~G
if anC:
0
In particular, therefore, a r>ight adjoint preserves any right Kan
extension that exists; and the representables
B(B,-):
B--+ V not
( 4. 13)
(4 .10)-(4.19)
on"ly presePVe
115
RanKG
but, in their total-ity, detect it (which by (3.7)
and (4.9) is a re-statement of Theorem 4.6(iii)). For the dual notion we observe that a diagram
A -----G-=------->- B induces, for any
H: C0 p
--+
V,
a map
0
(K,¢)*: HK p we say that
along
¢ exhibits
S
*
G----+ H
¢
*
S
(4.16)
as the "left Kan extension
K if (4.16) is an isomorphism for each
exists; equivalently, if
( 4 .15)
of G
LanKG
H whenever either side
induces an isomorphism of
S with the
functor
(K-) * G ,
( 4. 17)
which exists when the colimit
KC * G does so for each cocomplete.
C:
C(K-,C)
as it surely does if
(4.18)
A is small and
B
is
Then (4.16) becomes
for aU Any left adjoint
H:
C0 P
-+
V ,
Q: B --+ V preserves the left Kan extension LanKG;
and a representable extension in
* G
8(-,B): 8°p--+
V - giving
V turns it into a right Kan
(4.19)
4.1
116 0
[A P,VJ(C(K-,C),B(G-,B))
B((La~G)C,Il)
as a further equivalent characterization of
La~G.
(4.20)
Since left Kan
extensions occur more than right ones in our applications below, we shall give our further results in terms of these; of course the two notions are precisely dual,
)
0
p
turning a left Kan extension (4.15) into a
right one. For the genesis of these ideas, see Kan
[38J.
4.2 We continue with a collection of elementary results, formulae, and examples.
The accepted term "extension" is somewhat misleading here, for in the diagram
(4.21) (LanKG)K~ G,
it is not in general the case that The fact is that
Kx:
0
A--+ [A P,VJ
we have a canonical map
sends
A
as (4.34) below shows.
to
K_A: A(-,A) --+ C(K-,KA),
A-component of a canonical map
K:
KKA
~ C(K-,KA),
and
which is the
Y--+ KK: A--+ [A 0 P,Vl
where
y
is the Yoneda embedding: and clearly v: Y ~ KK ir; an iBomopz,hism ~·f m1C: rov:?:J if K is f'A.lZ:· f7.ithfuZ.
(4.22)
We now have:
Proposition 4. 23 fr>.ithfuZ; u!hac·
1-: G -·· (LanKG)K r!MllFr•.-;dy
K
z.r· an icomory·hism if
i~ fuZZy faiihrul if
rp
K 7-s fuUy
in an isomor>phism
(4.20)-(4.27) for all
B,G
I I7 ~.Jith
Lan G ;:J-:~st-in . :>. K
*
(LanKG)K = (KK-)
Proof
G by (4 .17), while
Yoneda isomorphism (3.10); clearly
~:
(LanKG)K--+ G is
hence it is by (4.22) an isomorphism if
8
converse take isomorphism and
K
=V
¢A=
and
G
* A(A,-)
(K-)
is
G by the
(K-) * G;
K is fully faithful.
For the
then by (3.9) and (3.10) the so that
KA'
K
is an isomorphism
C
is fully faithful.
When
A(A,-);
=
*
G ;; (Y-)
B has cotensor products [resp. tensor products]
the
formulae (4.10) and (4.17) have by (3.69) and (3.70) the more explicit forms Ra~G
-
fA
C(-,KA) ~ GA,
(4.24)
(4.25) either side existing if the other does.
V
In the classical case
=
Set we can use (3.33) and (3.34) to
express the Kan extensions by conical limits and colimits. that
el C(C,K-),
where
C/K;
an object is
(A
is some has
g: A--+ A'
el C(K-,C) (Ra~G)
E
C(C,K-): A--+ Set,
A,
with
= (K/C) 0 P, C =
(LanKG)C
=
f: C--+ KA), Kg.f
= f'.
Observe
is the comma-category
while a map
Similarly
(A,f)--+ (A' ,f') 0
C(K-,C): A p--+ Set
Hence (3.33) and (3.34) give
--c-+
B)
for
v
Set
colim(K/C ~ A --c;+ B)
for
v
Set
lim(C/K ~ A
again either side existing if the other does.
'
(4.26)
(4. 27)
4.2 118
Clearly (4.18) simplifies if for then
(La~G)C
= C(K-,C) *
Yoneda isomorphism (3.10).
K: A--+ C has a right adjoint
G ~ A(-,LC)
* G,
GLC
which is
L,
by the
Thus GL
e-
(4.28)
K-1 L •
if
Note that obviously:
Any functor Q: B--+ V preserves the LanKG cf (4.28) . We pass to some particular examples. Y: A--+ [A 0 P,vJ is
be the Yoneda embedding.
Let
G: A --+ B,
Since
YF
(4.29)
and let
0
= fA P,v~(Y-,F)
F by the Yoneda isomorphism (2.31), we have
-
(4.30)
y
Hence (4.17) gives (4.31)
On the other hand, (4.17) also gives
LanGY
(G-)
* Y,
that by the
S
A
in any commutative diagram
.\
where
K
that
A =
is initial and
d
iH a dof.
eZ
F:
3
F
for some
--+
Set.
We may as vJell suppose at once Then
P
corresponds as above
(4. 78)
139
to a functor FdP
=
FQK.
the form
Since a
B with
S: C --+
=
K
SK
dP
R: V
A
--+
If we write
a: ~1
and a cone
S: 1 --+ FQ.
with
R.
dR
Q,
R': D
It is evident that any
must coincide with
S,
A
Now
Q
and
J:
dR' = Q and
with
gives a reflexion
Cat
for the full subcategory of
0
/B
--+
dof/B.
Cat /B
[B,Set].
On the other hand
determined
--+
B,
fully faithful.
Here
and nay be called
left adjoint
~
sends
0
sends
S
V
is
F:
0
!B ,
B--+
Set
( 4. 78) ·to
d:
el
F
the discrete Grothendieck construction; its to the
F
of (4.77).
While this is special to the case to the important cases
dof/5
Thus we get an adjunction
Q ~ 0: CB,SetJ ----+ Cat
0
=
Gpd
and
V
V
=
=
Cat,
Set,
it has generalizations the latter being the
setting for the original Grothendieck construction
[34].
We do not give
these here, for they transcend the context of. enriched category theory as developed in this account, and involve "transformations" more general than the
Gpd-natural or
Cat-natural ones; we shall treat them in
l46). Note finally that
Q8S
means by (4.76) that, for any extension
p
that are dofs, it is clear that this factorization
evidently equivalent to
with
R'K
This completes the proof.
dof/B
A --+ B
S
and clearly with
0
by those
=
--+ FS
is initial, this cone is by Theorem 4.67(ii) of
for a unique cone
constitute a functor RK = P.
=
~
S, F:
since
B
S
is fully faithful.
--~Set,
we have a l~ft Kan
This
4.7
140
el F
(4.79)
- - - - - f 1 , -, - - - - - - +
1
since this asserts by (4.77) that
FB- colim B(d-,B),
it is precisely
a restatement of (3.32).
4.8
In this section and the next we look at conditions ensuring the
representability of a
V-functor
simplest case of a complete T: C--+
B
C.
F: C
~
V,
especially in the
Since by 1.11 the
has a left adjoint precisely when each
V-functor B(B,T-)
is
representable, the same considerations yield conditions for a left adjoint to exist. Since a colimit in functor
C--+ V,
C
is itself the representing object for a
the representing object for
F: C--+ V,
exists, is in some sense a "generalized colimit".
if it
Representing objects
are, in fact, very commonly constructed as colimits: consider some examples.
First, in the case
V = Set,
a representation for
corresponds, as we observed in 1.10, to an initial object in that is, to the colimit of the empty diagram in Proposition 3.36, a functor
el F.
F
elF;
Next, in
F: C --+ V was in effect given as an
iterated limit of representables; and we constructed its representing object as the corresponding iterated colimit of the representing objects for these.
Again, the left Kan adjoint
constructed via the colirnits
KC *
G.
LanK
of Theorem 4.50 was
A free abelian group is
constructed as a coproduct of infinite cyclic groups; the tensor
(4. 79)
141
product of two abelian groups is constructed as a cokernel of a free abelian group; and the free monoid on a set
In~O Xn.
X is the coproduct
More generally, numerous constructions of free algebras, free
monoids, and free monads, as iterated colimits, under cocompleteness but no completeness hypotheses, are given in
[44].
Yet the only general necessary condition that we so far have for the representability of
F
is expressed in terms of limits: by 3.2,
F
must preserve whatever limits exist.
F
must be continuous (and similarly for a
a left adjoint).
Hence if
C is complete,
T: C --+ B
that is to have
We here consider what must be added to this continuity
to ensure representability (or the existence of an adjoint).
Since
the desired representing object is a generalized colimit, this is analogous to the question of what must be added to completeness to ensure cocompleteness - or rather, to ensure the existence of a particular colimit. A smaU complete set
-
for if
at least
2n ,
cardinals
n.
C(A,B) making
Set-category
c
had at least two elements,
c
large if
Bn
C(A,Bn)
would have
existed for all small
Hence, by the classical argument on complete lattices,
a small complete
C is also cocomplete:
the infimum of its set of upper bounds. even if
is of necessity a preordered
C is a preordered set:
cocomplete but not complete.
the supremum of a subset is Not so, if
C is large -
the ordered set of small ordinals is
What must be added is a condition ensuring
that the colimit we need can be manufactured from smaZZ limits. Similarly in the case of representability of condition needed is a "smallness" one on
F.
F: C--+ V;
the extra
4.8
142 We begin with a general result expressing a representing object as a limit:
a
Theorem 4.80
C
~;
and the counit
{F,1},
happens to be small.
F: C--+ V is representatle if and only if the limit
exists and is preserved by
{F,lC}
is
large one, unless
Then the representing object
F.
of this limit is an
F--+ C({F,1},-)
isomorphism giving the representation of F.
Proof
One direction is immediate:
then by (3.10) the limit --+
C(D,-);
isomorphic
if
{C(D,-) ,1}
F is
is the representable D,
similarly, with appropriate changes, when to
C(D,-);
u =
with counit
and the representable
F
F
C(D,-), 1: C(D,-)
is only
preserves this limit.
For the other direction we have by hypothesis that
F
~
is the counit of the limit over
F
{F,F}.
foraunique
--+ F
for the composite
prove
u
C({F,l},-)
i
[g,1]F,
is
Since
through itself as =
I.
has the form
we therefore have
J.jJ = 1;
and to
UA: C({F,1},-) --+
l.
AU= 1
UA
is
C(f,1)u
for a
C(f,1) UA~
we have
However, as the counit of the limit
J.!.
(F,I)-cylinder
\hilin,;
an isomorphism it remains to show that
But by Yoneda, this map --+ {F,1}.
i; F--+ [I,F-J
g:l->F{F,lt. - l
[F{F,l},F-]
Hence by (3.4) the
given by the isomorphism
i=[g,l]FJ-
~
C({F,1},-)
=
u,
{F, 1},
unique
f;
for a unique
f: {F,1}
or
u, = C(l,l)u.
C(f,l)u
the cylinder whence
f
=
u 1
factorizes and
(4.80)-(4.83) There is a corresponding adjunction theorem:
( l.i)
r\:J GS
Theorem 4.81
1
(' Ii)
T: C ---+ B has a left adjoint if and only if Ran 1
exists and is preserved by
and the counit
T.
Then the left adjoint
-
f
g,h: G
of maps
"I
M
the inclusion.
g
and
E
--+
X
h.
D
-->-
be a small
A be the full
and let
-->- D
c
For any
€
c,
is
X
f.
Write
Eg = Eh,
such that
M
X
Gx'
let
c be the canonical map whose
C(G ,C),
X
• G
X
X XEX
de terrnined by the small coproducts of the
E: D = LxEX C(G , C) • G X X -component, for
{G }
let
c,
set of objects in the cocomplete category
~X
= KC
F
(x,f)-
for the set of pairs
and let
,\j!:
E =
(x,g,h)-components are
be the maps whose respective
The commutative diagram (4. 92)
E -----'------+ D ----+ C -----+
E
is not in general a coequalizer diagram; but for each
x
the diagram
C(l ')
( 4. 9 3)
is a split coequaZizer diagram. and C(1,E)t = 1,
C(l,)s = 1,
That is to say, there are maps
s: C(G ,D) --+ C(G ,E) X
and
C(l,\j!)s
implies that (4.93) is a coequalizer. the copro.iection
ix,f
X
= tC(1,E);
To wit,
of the coproduct, while
the coprojection corresponding to the index
for which which easily
t(f): Gx--+ D is s(u): Gx--+ E
(x,u,i
X, EU
).
Any
is
4.10
152
product of the diagrams (4.93) over a family
(xj)
of indices
clearly again a split coequalizer; whence it follows that
x
is
K sends
(4.92) to a coequalizer diagram
A(-,E) ----t A(-,D) ~ KC
in
[A 0 P,setJ.
along
K:
G: A--+ B
We conclude that the left Kan extension of
A --+ C
exists whenever
B admits coequalizers, and is
given as the coequalizer of the two maps
G~,
G~:
--+
GD.
remark that, when (4.92) is a coequalizer diagram for each
C,
C·,
is said to be a regurar generator of
GE
(We
{G } X
it is easily verifi.ed to be
a fortiori a strong generator and a generator.) Clearly Theorem 4.91 could be so modified as to cover the case
KC
where
was expressed as an iterated
colimit of representables.
There is a particularly neat and useful result of this kind when
K
is fully faithful; which we now suppose. Let let
C
E
F: C,
L0 p--+ V, and let
let
P: L--+ C be a diagram of type
a: F--+ C(P-,C)
in the language of 3.1.
Let us say that
be an a
F,
(F,C)-cylinder over is a
P,
K-cyZinder if the
composite cylinder
F
-a--+
C(P- ,C)
is a colimit-cylinder, giving
KC
F * KP.
For this it certainly suffices that, for each
F
~
C(P-,C)
C(KA,-)
(4.94)
A c A,
the cylinder
[C(KA,P-),C(KA,C)]
(4.94)-(4.97)
~3
be a colimit-cylinder, so that C(~~.C)
F * C(KA,P-)
-
(4.9~)
this is just the pointwise existence of the colimit (4.94); and the pointwiseness is automatic if An expression of
KC
by 3.3
L is small.
as a colimit
F
* YQ of representables,
as in Theorem 4.91, has as unit a cylinder
S: F--+ [A0 P,V](YQ-,KC).
The codomain of
S
moveover, since
K is fully faithful, we have
It follows that
S
(KC)Q 0 p
is isomorphic by Yoneda to
Y
~
KK
=
C(KQ-,C);
by (4.22).
has the form
F ~ C(KQ-,C)
(4.96)
in which the second map is in fact an isomorphism. expression of as a
KC
Thus such an
as a colimit of representables is the same thing
K-cylinder in which
P
factorizes through
A
as
KQ.
In this fully-faithful case we have a characterization of LanKG
as follows:
Theorem 4.97 An extension S: C--+ B of G: A--+ B along the fuZZy-faithful
K:
isomorphic to
A --+ C is
La~G
(that is,
S
LanKSK) if and only if it sends each
colimit-cylinder.
If
is canonically K-cyZinder to a
A is small, it suffices to speak of
small K-cyZindePs.
Proof The canonical expression of KC as a colimit KC * Y of representables corresponds as in (4.96) to a C(K-,C).
If
which is
KC
S
K-cylinder
sends this to a colimit-cylinder we have
* G since S is an extension of G;
thus
1: KC--+ SC ~ KC * SK, S ~ LanKG,
4.10
15 4
Conversely, if
LanKG
exists, any
sent to a colimit-cylinder by
K-cylinder
K;
= K- *
~
G sends
Still supposing
(~ : F
=
Y
and P : i
--+-
Y
fully faithful, consider a family
Y
of
K-cylinders, where
YEf
F : L up Y
l'
Y
C is the closure of A under the family
of colimits, we say that
if there is no proper replete full subcategory
A,
~
Generalizing 3.5, where it was a question of a family
--+C.
y
- *G
KPA * G exists; hence
to a colimit-cylinder.
C (P - ,C ) )
Y
L
K
is, by definition,
by (3.23) the functor
preserves the colimit (4.94), since each LanKG
a
and such that
V
C E y
whenever
P y
V
of
C,
containing
V.
takes its values in
Theorem 4.98 Let K: A--+- C be fully faithful, and let C be the closure of A for a family
s: C --+ B is exhibited by
functor
only if s LanKG
of K-cylinders as above.
sends each cylinder of
exists for any
1: SK
--+
as
SK
Then a
La~SK
to a colimit-cylinder.
if and Moreover
A --+ B if B admits FY-indexed colinits
G:
for each y " r.
Proof Theorem 4.97 gives the necessity in the first assertion. the sufficiency, let consisting of those exhibits
SC
as
isomorphisms
V C
be the replete full subcategory of for which
KC * SK.
Then
we have a canonical isomorphism
of
V· '
F
*
SP
c·r V·' (
y
~
KC KC '(
thus
Ac V
SKA ;;:: YA * SK = KKA * SK.
v,
and
S: C(K-,C)
y
~
F * KP y y
* SK.
v
Since
is all of
c,
* SP
-
B(SK-,SC)
C as unit
since
we have canonical
p
takes its values in
y
KP - * SK = y
by (4.90.
F
If
--+
For
SP
y
by the definition
Hence (3. 2 3) gives
c
y
as desired.
by hypothesis, we have The second assertion is
(4.98)-(4.99)
155
proved by a similar argument, taking for which
KC
*
V
c
now to consist of those
D
G exists.
For an example of this, let us modify the example following Theorem 4.91.
With the notation as there, write
c
subcategory of
A'
for the full
determined by the finite coproducts of the
G. X
Since every coproduct is the filtered colimit of the finite coproducts of its summands, every object of of
A'.
Suppose now that each
that each since
C(Gx,-): C--+ Set
A
is a filtered colimit of objects
Gx
is finitely presentable- meaning
preserves filtered colimits.
filtered colimits commute with finite limits in
by Theorem 4.73, each object of
A'
to
Z
is the inclusion
Z-cylinders.
Set
is finitely presentable; and thus
Z:
the filtered colimits in question are preserved by where
Then,
A' --+A--+ C;
C--+ [A' 0 P,setJ,
that is, they correspond
It now follows from Theorem 4.98 that any
--+ B admits a left Kan extension along
Z: A' --+ C if
G: A'
B
admits
coequalizers and filtered colimits. We end with a result, a special case of which we have already used in Theorem 4.51:
Theorem 4.99 Let K: A - - + C be fullw faithful, and denote by
[A,BJ' which
the full subcategory of [A,BJ LanKG
exists.
Then
LanK:
determined by thooe
[A,BJ'
--+
G for
[C,BJ is fuZZy faithful;
so that we have an equivalence
[A,BJ' ~ [C,BJ~,
the fuZZ subcategory of [C,BJ
determined by the functors isomorphic
to some K.
LanKG;
where the latter is
the inverse to this equivalence is composition with
If A is smaU, it follows that
[C,BJ~
is a
V-category.
4.10
156
Proof we have by Theorem 4.38 that [A,BJ(G,(LanKG')K), [A,BJ(G,G').
=
[C,B](LanKG,LanKG')
which by Proposition 4.23 is isomorphic to
II
of course this fully-faithfulness is just a special case of the observation in 1.11 following (1.53), to which we could have appealed: for we are dealing with an adjunction ~
is an isomorphism.
[A,BJ
I
:::
[C,Blt
LanK --i
[K, l]
In practice we use the equivalence
chiefly when
[A,BJ'
rA, B),
is all of
instance under the hypotheses of Theorem 4.98
or when
as for
A is small
B is cocomplete.
and
5.
whose unit
Density
5.1
A function
k: A--+ C,
not necessarily continuous, between
hausdorff spaces is dense (in the sense that its image is a dense subset) precisely when any continuous map from space when
B
into another hausdorff
is uniquely determined by its composite with
Set(k,l): Haus(C,B)--+ Set(A,B)
analogous definition of density for a
For a as a
C
V-category
B,
is injective. V-functor
V'
V'-category for some suitable extension
Consider those
S: C--+
whose indexing-type
that is,
We give an
of
exists at least
V
as in 3.12.
B which preserve every colimit existing in
F: A --+
V
full subcategory
A-Cocts[C,B],
full subcategory
Cocts[C,BJ
that exist.
'
K: A --+ C.
[C,B]
the functor category
k·
has domain which if
of those
S
A; A
C
these constitute a
is small contains the
preserving all small colimits
(5 .1)
157
Theorem 5.1 (i)
FoP a
V-functop
K: A--+ C the following aPe equivalent:
For any
B,
functor
[K,l]: [C,BJ--+ [A,BJ
(ii)
The funator
(iii)
For eaah
the restriction to
K:
C,D
€
0
C--+ [A P ,VJ C the map
K:
of the
A-Cocts[C,BJ
is fully faithfUl. is fuZZy faithful. C(C,D) --+[A 0 P,VJ(C(K-,C),C(K-,D))
is an isomorphism. (iv)
For eaah
C
€
C,
as unit exhibits (v)
The identity
(vi)
Some isomorphism
the identity aylinder
1: C(K-,C) --+ C(K-,C)
c as KC * K.
1: K --+ lcK
exhibits
¢:K--+ lcK
lc
as
LanKK.
exhibits
lc
as
LanKK.
Proof Because a representable C0 p --+ V preserves all limits that exist, its dual
C --+ ~p
preserves all colimits that exist in
Since the Yoneda embedding is fully faithful, and since
K
C.
is the
composite
c
y
it follows that (i) implies (ii).
The direct translation (iii) of (ii)
is equivalent by (3.5) to (iv), which is in turn
equival~nt
by (4.18)
to (v), itself a special case of (vi); so that it remains only to show that (vi) implies (i).
Suppose then that
it thus preserves the colimit in (vi), so that
KC
S¢: SK--+ SK
4.38 we therefore have for any [C,BJ(S,S')
~
[A,BJ(SK,S'K),
* K,
S: C--+
B
is
A-cocontinuous;
and hence the left Kan extension
exhibits
S
as LanK(SK).
By Theorem
S': C--+ B a representation
whose unit is
S¢.
By (1.48), this
5.1
158
isomorphism is the composite of and
r:K,l]: [C,BJ(S,S') ---+- [A,BJ(SK,S'K)
isomorphism since A
V-functor
cp
is,
K:
A ---+-
is said to be dense. the concept for
so is the former- which proves (i).
0
(The original term used by Isbell, who introduced
V =Set
0
0
K p: A P--+ C P
the dense
K:
A --+
in
was left adequate.)
[35],
is dense.
A--+ C
K:
is codense
In the important special case where
C,
leaving
is the one-object full subcategory
in
For the dual
C is the inclusion of a full subcategory, we merely
A is dense in
say that
D
C satisfying these equivalent conditions
notion (Isbell's right adequate) we use aodense; if
the latter being an
[A,BJ(S.P,l): CA,B](SK,S'K) ---+- [A,BJ(SK,S'K);
K
{A},
to be understood; and if we say that
A
A is dense
C.
It
is clear that the density of
class of
K in the
2-category of
K depends only on "the equivalence V-functors"; that is, if
K
is
dense, so is the composite
c where the outer functors are equivalences and where to
map
K'
is isomorphic
K.
When of
(5. 2)
C admits tensor products, the criterion (v) for the density
K: A--+ C becomes by (4.25) the requirement that the canonical
C(KA,C)
®
KA
--+
C express C
while when
V
= Set
= fA
C as the coend
C(KA,C) ® KA
it becomes by (4.27) the requirement that the
canonical cone express
C as the colimit
(5. 3)
(5 .2)-(5 .5)
159
c If
K:
colim (K/C
-A-C) d
K
A ~ C is dense, applying
V:
V
--+
0
(5.4)
'
Set to the isomorphism
in Theorem 5.l(iii) above gives a bijection of sets
= CA0 P,VJ 0 (C(K-,C),C(K-,D))
C (C,D) 0
whose meaning is that every C(K-,D)
is of the form
V-natural transformation
C(K-,f)
for a unique
f:
C
(5.5) ~:
_,.D.
clear that (5.5) is in turn equivalent to the density of conservative, and in particular in the classical case also equivalent to density if cotensor products
v0 :
genera tor of
XB
~
C
if
K
C for some set
{XB}
for if we write (5.5) with
constituting a strong X ~ D
in place of
0
2-category (3.54), and let {l};
isomorphism in
It is
C admits
0
0
is
V
= Set.
is cotensored; or even if
general (5.5) is strictly weaker than density:
subcategory
V
I t is
V (X,C(C,D)) ~ V (X,[A P,VJ(C(K-,C),C(K-,D))).
we easily get
C be the
C(K-,C) --+
take
V = Cat,
D,
Yet in let
K be the inclusion of the full
we have the bijection (5.5), but not the
V of Theorem 5.1(iii).
After first surveying various examples and elementary properties of density, we shall return in 5.11 below to the study of the important map
[K,l]: Cocts:C,BJ--+
[A,BJ of Theorem 5.1(i).
5.2 We begin by considering the composability and cancellation properties of dense functors.
The positive results below are for any
the counter-examples are all for
V = Set;
V, while
the assertions about the
density or the non-density of particular functors in the counterexamples are easily verified using (5.5).
We consider a diagram
5.2
160
/
~~
.
A
in which
""~.
,,
K
"· C
is an isomorphism, so that
L'
of diagrams in C such that each colimit and is
K-absolute,
K-absolute colimit of objects of A,
colimit of the form (v)
as unit
C(K-,C)
K-absolute, and such that
Y
F
y
*
P
y
YEf
exists
C is the closure of
A under this family of colimits. If A is small, the colimits in (iv) and (v) may be taken to be small.
Proof (i) implies (ii) since, when K is fully faithful, it reflects colimits by 3.5.
By the remark preceding the theorem, (ii) gives (iii)
as a special case.
Q
= 1;
if
A
family
Then (iii) gives (iv) by taking
and the domain of is.
F
here is
A,
F
= KC and
so that the colimit is small
From (iv) we get (v) by taking for
~
the one-object
(F,KQ). Finally, by Theorem 4.98 and Lemma 5.18, it follows
from (v) that Theorem 5.1(v).
1: K--+ K exhibits
0
1c
as
LanKK,
giving (i) by
5.4
172 The chief purpose of this theorem is to exhibit (v) as a practical criterion for the density of in
K.
C is presented (or exhibited) by the family
more loosely, by the family
F
y
A
We shall say that the density of
*
p
= (F ,P )
y
may call such a family a presentation of the density of or simple a density presentation.
y yE
r ; or, We
K-absolute colimits.
of
y
- C be the inclusion of the
full subcategory determined by the small set of objects in question. Since
K
Moreover so.
is strongly generating,
K:
0
C--+ [G P,VJ
is conservative.
K preserves all small colimits, since each
In particular it preserves for each
C
Since, by the remarks following Lemma 5.18,
E
C
C(KG,-)
the colimit
K sends
does
- *
KC
K.
1: KC--+ C(K-,C)
to a colimit cylinder, we conclude by the observations at the beginning of 3.6 that 1 is already a colimit cylinder, exhibiting Thus
K is dense by Theorem 5.1(iv); and consequently
C as
KC
* K.
K is fully
faithful. To prove
-
K an equivalence, it remains by 1.11 to prove it
essentially surjective.
Given
0
FE [A P,VJ,
the colimit
F
* K exists
5.5
176
because
A is small and
colimits we have
*
K(F
C is cocomplete; and since K) ~ F
* KK
=F * Y =F.
There may well be various inequivalent 0
[A P,VJ.
equivalent to [A 0 P,VJ
A·
'
A
CGTop; when V = Ab,
of representables; when
A
if
A,
A c
is small.
and for many
v
V • Set,
We shall show in 5.8 that, for
retracts of the representables.
If
it is small whenever
A consists of the V
The same is true for
to
A, A.
consists of the retracts of finite coproducts
V
A.
= R+,
Lawvere
The passage from
as the small-projectives in Then
A
[54]
A.
In all
A and
A ~ B. B· '
to
A
cXOP,vJ
is a closure operation; z [A
0
P,V],
is equivalent
A --+A
A and
B,
we have
is an
[A 0 p, VJ ~ [B 0 p, V]
This relation is called Morita equivalence
it was first studied by Morita
in the case· V
that is, rings
A
In these circumstances it follows at once from the
if and only if
= Ab
R and
the categories of right
s. '
with
A
and
[65]
B one-object
in which case
R-modules and right
situation has been studied by various authors [33]),
A to be
has shown
is Cauchy complete if the inclusion
facts above that, for small
[ 2])
or
V is such that this last is so, we may call A the Cauchy
equivalence.
between
= Cat
A is small when A is.
completion of for
and the
In general
the Cauchy completion of the (generalized) metric space these cases
C is
for which
denotes the full subcategory of
[A 0 P,VJ z [~P,V]
is strictly bigger than
A is.
A
D
determined by the small-projectives, then
proof above gives
A
If
A
K preserves small
(see also Ab-categories-
and
are
S-modules. ( [66],
The general
[68],
[27],
and may be expressed in terms of the profunctors or distributors
(5. 2 7)
177
introduced independently by Lawvere
A
profunctor from
[53]
and Benabou
[8 J;
B is a functor T: B ® A0 p--+ V,
to
these compose by the operation
S(C,-)
* T(-,A)
a
and
to form a biclosed
bicategory.
V,
For some
however,
v0
example is the category
A
A may be large when
separately.
A
x
X.
Here the Cauchy completion of the unit
For such
0
the relation between
V
V and any sma~Z
Theorem 5.27 For any
of the sma~~-projectives in
K:
the inc~usion, [A P,VJ
[A
0
V-category
[A P,VJ
[A 0 P,VJ.
[~P,VJ
and
is
[SS]:
A,
V-category Then if K:
P,VJ--+ c~P.v]
I
Px of subsets
X the lattice
more complicated, and has been given by Lindner
0
A ® B --+ C are
B --+ C which are sup-preserving in each variable
is not small, containing for each set of
An
of complete lattices and sup-preserving
maps, with the tensor product such that the maps the functions
is small.
~et
A
0
P,VJ
[A
A--+
consist is
induces an equiva~ence of
with the full subcategory Acc[~P,V]
determined by the
accessible functors; and the inverse to this equivalence is composition with the inclusion
Proof Since KZ
=
Z: Y:
A
--7
A.
A---+ [A 0 P,VJ
is dense by Theorem 5.13.
Hence
is dense, the fully-faithful
K: [A P,V]--+ [~P,VJ_ is fully
faithful, and it remains to determine its full image. F: is
A0 P--+ V
we have
rA 0 P,V](K-,F*Y).
KF
F? * A(-,Z?). ~p---+
V,
= rA 0 P,V](K-,F),
Since each
isomorphic to the colimit
F?
K
0
KB
For any
which by the Yoneda (3.17)
is small-projective, this is
0
0
* [A P,V](K-,Y?) = F? * [A P,V](K-,KZ?)
The last term here is a small colimit of representables
and hence is accessible by Proposition 4.83.
Moreover
g
5.5
178 composing it with
Z gives
that composition with
Z
F?
is the inverse.
K,
accessible is in the image of representable colimits. A(Z-,B):
A(-,B)
A p--+ V;
it suffices to show that every
A(Z-,B) =
=A(-,B),
verifying
To show finally that every
K preserves small
is in this image, since
but
=F,
~ F? *A(-,?)
Composing this representable with 0
= [A0 P,VJ(K-,KB)
KKB
* A(Z-,Z?)
[A
0
Z
gives
P,VJ(Y-,KB) ~ KB.
Now we have
D
as desired.
This gives at once:
Proposition 5.28 For any equivalence
[A 0 P,VJ
Of course, since
':>
J:em 5.35 is a special case of that of Theo~:em 5.31; what is new here- is the f.,.e/>"""s of the F-cocompletion, which allows us to replace F-Cocts[C,B].
K
Cocts [C,B]
by
(Often, using the word "completion" in a wider sense,
185 we may refer to the
under
F-cocompletion of
A as the completion of
A
F-ooZimits.) As the first example of such an
F-cocomp1etion, take
A
consist of aZZ small indexing types, so that
oooompZetion of A.
F
to
is simply the
From Proposition 4.83 and Proposition 5.34, this
cocompletion is precisely the
V-category
0
small, this reduces to
[A P,VJ,
Acc[A0 P,V].
and were-find
When
A is
(part of)
Theorem 4.51. Other examples with
V
~
Set will be found in the article [45]
on enriched essentially-algebraic structures.
V=
examples discussed below we take
Set.
For the remaining
The colimits we are
interested in will then be conical ones, so that
F
is in effect a
set of small categories. Before we proceed, however, we anticipate a possible misunderstanding that may arise from the very special nature of our main examplei. In the transfinite construction of 3.5 for the closure of
A under
F-colimits in
taking all the
0
[A P,V],
F-colimits in
0
[A P,VJ
the first step consists in of the objects of
important cases the full subcategory given by these itself closed under
F-colimits and hence constitutes
construction then terminates after one step. example above, where
A
A.
In some
F-colimits is A;
the
This was so in the
F consisted of all small indexing types; and
it will also be so in the three important examples of 5.8 - 5.10 below.
However, it is far from true in general.
taking
V = Set
henceforth, if
F
For instance,
consists of the two discrete
5. 7
186 categories 0
and 2,
coproducts, we reach
F
trivially, if
A
so that
A
w
only after
steps of the iteration.
consists of the single category
A
is the closure of
A
has two objects
A
A--+ P,
maps
0
==!
1,
Less
so that
under coequalizers, consider the case where
A, B
f,g,h: A--+ B.
and three non-identity maps P, Q, R
In the first step we add in the coequalizers respective pairs
A under finite
is the closure of
(f,g),
(f,h),
and
(g,h);
of the
but now there are two
and we must next add in the coequalizer of these, and
so on.
5.8
V
For our first main example with
= Set,
let
F consist of
the single category with one object and with one non-identity endomorphism
A
e
=
e.
Then a diagram of type
A with an idempotent endomorphism e.
is an object
has a colimit
e2
satisfying
r: A--+ B
in
A
splits; that is,
e
has the form
i: B--+ A with
ri
=
1.
F
This diagram
if and only if the idempotent
= ir
e
for maps
in
r: A--+ B
e and
Such a splitting is unique (to within
isomorphism) if it exists; so that the split idempotents correspond
A in
bijectively to the retracts of we may call the
In this case
idempotent-splitting completion of A,
of all the retracts in
0
[A P,Set]
it is evidently small if when
A.
A
is.
all idempot~nts split in
of the representables Moreover
B.
B
is
A,
which
clearly consists
A(-,A)
E
A;
F-complete precisely
In fact we have the result promised
in 5.5 above:
Theorem 5.36 For a small
A,
the small-projeatives in
[A 0 P,set]
are
precisely the retracts of the representables; so that the idempotent-
(5. 36)
187
-splitting completion of A is its Cauchy compZetion.
A
Moreover
A.
is Cauchy complete exactZy when all idempotents spZit in
Proof We saw in the proof of Theorem 5.26 that the representables in
[A
0
P,set]
are small-projective, whence so too are their retracts by
Proposition 5.25. -projective.
F: A0 p --+Set
Suppose conversely that 0
Then
[A P,Set](F,-)
preserves all small colimits, and
in particular the canonical expression (3.32) of representables. indexed by
el F) P, Set
0
[A P,set](F,F) with some
[A P,Set](F,F)
0
(
colimits in
0
Thus
of the sets
as a colimit of
0
[A P,set](F,A(-,A)).
is the composite of some A(-,A);
F
is the canonical colimit,
are calculated by (3.35),
i: F---+
is small-
that is,
Since
the element
IF
r: A(-,A)--+ F F
in
of
eZ F
is a retract of some
A(-,A).
To say that inclusion
A--+
A
A
isomorphic to one in
is Cauchy complete is, by 5.5, to say that the
A.
A.
Note that, in this example, the inclusion
A
are
F-colimits as exist in
A.
In fact
A--+
D
preserves
example is quite atypical, however: by no means preserves the
for a general
A(C,A +B)
A
This
F the inclusion
F-colimits that exist in
For instance, consider the completion of
F
F-colimits for this
absolute - they are preserved by any functor whatsoever.
A --+ A
is
Since idempotents split uniquely if at all,
this is exactly to say that all idempotents split in
such
A
is an equivalence, or that every object of
A.
under finite coproducts:
is in general quite different from
A(C,A) + A(C,B).
5.9
188
5.9
V = Set
Our next example with
A
is the completion of
under
finite colimits; since the number of finite categories is small,
the finite-colimit completion of A is small if A is.
Theorem 5.37 The completion of A under finite coZimits is the fuU suhcategor•y of [A 0 P,Set]
determined by aU finite co limits of
the representables.
Proof
A
Let
[A 0 P,Set]
c
consist of all finite colimits of the
representables; we are to show that Clearly
A
objects
F
and
S:
A
is closed under finite colimits.
contains the initial object of
=
colim YT
Q--+ A
and
P
with
G
with any vertex
YT
and
YS,
H
colim YS
Q
and
the functor with components YR
=
T
S.
0
P,Set].
A,
of
finite.
and
[A
Let
Consider
where R:
T:
P + Q--+
P --+ A
A
be
Since an inductive cone over
clearly consists of independent cones over
it follows that
colim YR
=
F
+ G.
A
Hence
is closed
under finite coproducts, and it remains to prove it closed under coequalizers.
With
F
and
G
(pp: A(-,TP)--+ F) a,8: F--+ G. satisfies each
P
€
ya
P.
as above, let the colimit-cones be and
(aQ: A(-,SQ)--+ G),
Since the
= y8 The
are jointly epimorphic, a map
if and only if it satsifies map
and consider
app: A(-,TP) --+ G
yapp
corresponds by Yoneda to
an element of
GTP.
Since
surjective in
Set,
this element is the image under
up e A(TP,SP')
for some
the
P'
E
aQ,TP: A(TP,SQ)
Q.
y: G--+ H
--+
GTP 0
are jointly
P', TP
of some
By the naturality of Yoneda we
then have commutativity in the left diagram of
(5. 3 7)
189 A(-,~)
A(-,TP)
A(-,vp)
A(-,SP')
A(-,TP)
,,j
j'p•
'Pl F
j'P" F
G •
a
A(-,SP")
G
B
while the corresponding right diagram comes from a similar argument applied to
The condition
Define a finite graph
now becomes
G whose object-set is
Q
and whose arrows are all those of xp: P->- P'
and
yp: P->- P"
category generated by
Q),
together with arrows
for each
P
E
P.
Let
S
be the
G subject to the composition and identity Q;
clearly
S is finite.
S--+ A to agree with S on Q,
to send
P
relations that already obtain in N:
(ob P) + (ob
send
and
colim YN
is the coequalizer of
to
and
respectively. a
and
E
P to
Define
TP,
and to
Then clearly
D
B.
(It may not be inferred from the truth of Proposition 5.34 and Theorem 5.37 that, for a generaZ cocomplete
C,
the construction of
the colimit-closure or of the finite-colimit-closure of a full subcategory
Cat 0
A
terminates after one step.
The ordinary category
is by Proposition 3.40 the colimit-closure of the full
subcategory in 5.3.
{2},
since
The category
2
is a strong generator, as we observed
A with one object and one non-identity idempotent
map is in fact easily seen to lie in the finite-colimit-closure of
{ 2 }.
Yet
{2};
through 2
to
A is not the colimit in
A
Cat
0
of any functor factorizing
for it is soon verified that no map from a copower of
is a coequalizer.)
5.10
190
5.10
For our final example with
of a small
Set
we consider the completion Let us write this as
and for the rest of this section keep
completion of
A
for the
A under finite colimits.
A functor F*
=
A under small filtered colimits.
[A 0 P,setJ,
Ac
V
F: A0 p --+ Set
is called j1at if the functor
-: [A,Set] --+Set is left exact - that is, finite-limit-preserving.
Every representable
A(-,A)
which is the evaluation limits.
is flat, for
A(-,A)
EA: CA,Set] --+Set,
Moreover, since
* ? = (?)A by Yoneda,
preserving all small
* is cocontinuous in both variables, it
follows from Theorem 4. 73 that a small filtered colimit of flat functors is flat.
Theorem 5.38
For
0
F: A P--+ Set
with
A small, the fol~ing
are equivalent: el
0
is filtered.
(i)
(
F) P
(ii)
The aanoniaal expression (3.32) of F as a aoZimit of representables is a filtered aolimit.
(iii)
F
is some small filtered colimit of representabies.
(iv)
F
lies in the completion
A of
A under smaZl filtered
aolimits. (v) Proof
F
(i) 0
( al F) p; trivial.
is f1at. implies (ii) since the colimit (3.32) is indexed by that (ii) implies (iii) and that (iii) implies (iv) are Since
A is by Theorem 5.35 the closure of
A
in
(5. 38)- (5. 39) [A
0
P,set]
191
under filtered colimits, (iv) implies (v) by the remarks
preceding the theorem.
Thus we have only to show that (v) implies
(i) .
Let
P--+ elF where
T:
corresponds to a functor By the flatness of
F
P is finite. 0
P --+
S:
we have
F
A p
*
As in 4.7,
and an element
a
lim FS.
E
*
li~A(SP,-) ~ li~(F
and by Yoneda the latter is limPFSP =lim FS.
T
A(SP,-));
By the formula (3.70)
and the dual of (3.68), we have therefore a canonical surjection
LAEA FA
li~A(SP,A) ----+lim FS.
x
Let some inverse image of (x
a
FA,
E
li~A(SP,A)).
E
inductive cone in maps
x
to 0
a
ap
( el F) p
over
filtered.
D
A
under this surjection be given by By (3.28),
over
S
with vertex
by construction, T
with vertex
8
a
we can regard A.
Since
as an
FBp: FA ---+ FSP
is equally an inductive cone in
(A,x).
Thus
(
eZ F) 0 p
is
Proposition 5.39 A f1at functor F: A--+ Set with A small preserves any finite limit that exists in f1at functors
F: A --+ Set
P--+
A.
If A is finitely conrplete, the
are precisely the left-exact ones.
P
Proof
If
of
gives,as in the proof above,that
F
S:
A with
finite has a limit in F
However the left side is now isomorphic to So a flat functor complete. exact,
F
A
F
*
A(-,lim S), ~ F(lim S). A
is finitely
is finitely complete and
F
is left
is finitely complete by Proposition 4.87; hence
is finitely cocomplete and therefore filtered, so that Theorem 5.38.
the flatness
li~A(-,SP) =lim FS.
is certainly left exact if
Conversely, if
eZ F
*
A,
0
F
(
0
el F) p
is fla.t by
5. 10
192 Proposition 5.40
finitely-presentab~e
The
-colimit-completion
A of a
smal~
A are the retracts of the
representabZes; so that they reduce to Proof
objects in the filtered-
Since filtered colimits in
A if idempotents
A are formed as in
sp~it 0
[A P,SetJ,
the proo.f of Theorem 5.36 applies here virtually unchanged. point is that, for a finitely-presentable
F,
in A.
the functor
The new A(F,-)
is
only known to preserve filtered colimits; but now the canonical F is filtered,
colimit of representables giving
Proposition 5.41
If A is the finite-coZimit-compZetion of the small
A--+
then the inclusion
A,
0
0
is, to within equivalence,
[A P,setJ A
the filtered-colimit-completion 0
F: A P --+ Set
A
of
A.
In consequence, every
is a filtered colimit of objects of A,
and A
consists of the finitely-presentable objects of [A 0 P,setJ. Proof
Let
K: A--+
A
be the inclusion, so that by Proposition 5.16 0
the inclusion A--+ [A P,Set]
is
K.
Using
Lex
we have by Theorem 5.38 and Proposition 5.39 that subcategory
Lex[~P,set]
we have an equivalence
of
[K P,l]
with the Yoneda
A
is the full
By the dual of Theorem 5.35
0
RanK 0 P: [A P,Set] ~ Lex[~P.setJ,
inverse is the restriction of 0
[~P,setJ.
for "left exact",
A--+
this gives the first assertion.
0
[K P,l]. cXOP,setJ
whose
:ance the composite of is
K: A--+
[A 0 P,setJ,
Then the second one comes from
Theorem 5.38 and the third from Proposition 5.40.
0
Finally we give the converse to Proposition 4.74 promised in
4.6:
(5 • 40)- (5 • 42)
19 3
Proposition 5.42 For a smaZZ A with finite-coZimit-compZetion
A,
the foZZowing are equivaZent: (i)
A is fiZtered.
(ii)
colim:
(iii)
The incZusion K: A --+
[A,Set] --+ Set is Zeft exact.
A
is finaZ.
Proof Since by (3.26) we have colim F 0
is the flatness of
nl: A P--+
Set.
equivalent to the filteredness of
~ 61
* F, what (ii) asserts
By Theorem 5.38, this is
eZ nl) 0 P,
which is
A;
thus
(ii) is equivalent to (i).
A
Since
is finitely cocomplete and hence filtered, what (iii)
asserts by Proposition 4.71 is the non-emptiness of each F
E
A.
F
E
A so arises.
Any finite diagram in
with vertex for some
5.11
A
A;
E
A has a colimit
F
in
A,
F/K
for
and every
To say that the diagram admits an inductive cone A is exactly to say that there is a map
thus (iii) is equivalent to (i).
F --+ KA
0
From the beginning of 5.4 until now we have dealt only with
fuZZy-faithfuL dense functors - exploiting the notion of a density presentation, which does not seem to generalize usefully to the non-fully-faithful case.
arbitrary dense
Now we drop this restriction, and consider an
K: A
full subcategory of
~
[C,BJ
C.
For any
B,
given by those
write
Ladj[C,BJ
for the
S: C--+ B which are
left adjoints (or which have right adjoints); since left adjoints are certainly
A-cocontinuous, it follows from Theorem 5.1 that the
restriction of
[ K, 11: [C,B~ -
LA,BJ
to
Ladj[C,B I
is fully
5.11
194 faithful, so that
Ladj[C,BJ
is a
equivalent to its replete image in
A
V-category if [A,BJ
under
is small, being
[K,l];
the main
goal of this section and the next is to determine this replete image. In this section, devoted mostly to examples, we suppose for simplicity that
A is small; if it were not, the expressions
Cocts K [C,BJ
would have to be modified.
Cocts[C,BJ
and
Then Proposition 5.11 and
Theorem 5.33 give Cocts[C,BJ
Ladj [C,BJ
if C
~s
(5.43)
cocompZete.
We also abbreviate fuZZ subcategory to subcategory, since we consider no others.
Finally, we loosely write
[K,l]
restrictions, specified by the context,
and
LanK
for various
of the functors properly so
named. The following remarks, to the end of this paragraph, apply to any
K: A --+ C,
dense or not, and do not need
A to be small.
In
Theorem 4.51, and in its generalizations Theorem 4.99 and Theorem 5.35, we have used the notation G:
A --+ B
for which
more than one functor
[A,B]'
La~G
K,
for the subcategory given by those
exists.
Since we have soon to deal with
we replace this notation by
[A,BJ(K).
Similarly we have used, in Theorem 4.99 and elsewhere, the subcategory given by those some
G;
we now change this to
subcategory of G---..
(La~G)K
subcategory of 1: SK--+ SK
[A,BJ(K)
[C,BJ9.K.
given by those S
as
LanKG
for
Write [A B] (K)
'
G
is an isomorphism; and write
exhibits
for
S: C--+ B of the form
given by those
[C,BJ9.K
[C,BJN
LanKSK.
s
*
for the
for which the unit [C,BJ!K
for the
for which the identity
It is immediate from Theorem 4.38
that we have an equivalence (with the evident unit and counit)
(5.43)-(5.48)
195 [A BJ(K)
'
where (as we warned) we are using restrictions. [A BJ(K)
, *
[K,1]
and
(5. 44)
*
LanK
loosely for their
By Proposition 4.23,
= [A
'
BJ(K)
and
[C BJ'~.K
,
for fully-faithful
[C,BJtK
*
K; (5.45)
and in this special case, (5.44) becomes the equivalence
La~
--1
of Theorem 4.99:
[K,1]: [C,BJJ!.K ~ [A,BJ(K)
(5.46)
B
(and in particular for
B
V)
=
K is not fully faithful, so that (5.46) then fails too.
whenever
Henceforth we suppose once again that proof of Theorem 5.1, a cocontinuous
* K;
K
but by the same Proposition 4.23, the first equality
in (5.45) fails for a general
KC
for fully faithful
K is dense.
As in the
S: C--+ B preserves the colimit
so that by Theorem 5.l(iv) we have
s
E
[C BJJ!.K
'
*
(from which,
using (5.44), were-find the conclusion of Theorem 5.l(i), that the restriction of
[K,l]
to
Cocts[C,BJ
is fully faithful).
We therefore
have inclusions Ladj[C,BJ
c
Cocts[C,] B
c
[c , B] *l!.K c [C,B ] tK c
CB I.,].
The first of these inclusions is by (5.43) an equality when cocomplete, but is proper in general - the inclusion into
(5. 4 7)
C is
Set of
the small full subcategory of finite sets is continuous but has no left adjoint.
The third inclusion is by (5.45) an equality when
K is
fully faithful, and in fact Theorem 5.29 then gives the common value explicity as [C BJtK
'
*
[C,BJtK
K
Cocts [C,BJ
for fully-faithful
K.
( 5. 48)
5.11
196 However the second and fourth inclusions above are in general proper
V ; Set,
even when
B are complete and cocomplete, and
C and
K is fully faithful.
For an example of this, let 1
E
= (O--+ 1);
2
maps
in
A----+ B
A; 0,
it is clearly dense.
B;
0 --+ B
A--+ B to
which
0
B;
and
When
B
= Ladj[2,B]
Cocts[2,B]
B.
BE
B.
[2,BJ~K.
is not so on
{0,1},
object of
[2,6]
this is sent by (D,C)
and let
[2,BJ: of
B
for
V = Set,
0
again
(B,A)
to
to the projection
E
--+
A in
[2,Set] ; Set x Set;
D x C
--+
C.
For an
is the disarete
2
B
B
and
K is clearly dense.
may be identified with a map [K,l]
C
K is surjective on objects.
B = Set P;
consists of those. B --+A
Clearly
An
Set;
and
LanK
[2,B]tK
isomorphic to such projections, while
consists of such projections for which the other projection
D )( C --+ D is an isomorphism - that is; the maps maps
[K,1]
given by those
K: 2 --+ 2 be the inclusion, where
category
*
[K,l],
K is not fully faithful, the second, third, and fourth
example, let
'
LanK
is epimorphic.
are complete and cocomplete, and
[2 BJtK
but
The replete image under
B
consists
Here of course
inclusions in (5.47) may all be proper, even when
sends
consists of all
[A,B]~K) = [A,BJ(K) = [A,BJ = B;
is the proper subcategory of --+
[2,B]
consists of those with
although necessarily fully faithful on
Ladj[2,BJ
Then
that are epimorphisms in
is fully faithful on
it sends
correspond to
while
the initial object of
of those
K: 1--+ 2
0 --+C.
of the maps
Finally (as in the last example) --+ 1
and
0
--+
1.
D --+ 1 Ladj[2,BJ
and the consists
Observe how badly (5.46) fails:
19 7
although
[K,l]
is conservative on
essentially surjective and
LanK
K),
and
[K,l]
but even a left adjoint SK;
of
(D,l)
Ladj[2,8]
K,
S: C--+ B may be
Since the unique map extension of
LanKG
(5.47),
2 --+ 1
K along
V =Set
With
--+
sends
[K,l]
B;
2--+ 1
A--+ B
for some
G must lie outside
again,, let
K =I'll: 2--+ 2.
is
I'll: 1--+ 2
to
LanK
sends
l:B--+B.
by Theorem 4.67; K by Proposition 5.7. C --+ D
lie in
B,
while
[A 8] (K)
• -*
consists of the maps Ladj[C,BJ
1: D - D.
consists of those
0 --+ D,
As in
0--+ B which LanK
which need not in general - for instance, if [A,B
to
Here
are epimorphic; and such an object is the image under --+
G other
K is not fully faithful - each consisting of the maps
the penultimate example,
C
while
is obviously initial, the left Kan
B cocomplete, we see that
even though 0
(O,C),
consists of the pairs
since the latter functor is clearly dense, so is
while
and
The example above does not illustrate this possibility, but
the following one does so.
Taking
Clearly
not only does Proposition 4.23 fail,
in which case, by (5.44) and
[A,BJ;K).
[2,8J~K;
(O,l).
For a non-fully-faithful
than
[2,8] = [2,B](K).
consists of the pairs of the forms
the replete image under (l,l)
(as it must be for an
it is not fully faithful on
is not fully faithful on
[2,BJ:K)
[2,8]
of any 0
8 = Set P -
J (K).
*
5.12 We now answer the question raised in 5.11 for a dense K: A--+ C by identifying the replete image of certain sub category
K-Com[A,BJ(K)
[K,l]: Ladj [C,8J
of
--+ [A,B]
[A,8J;K) c [A,8J;
the result is independent of the smallness of
A.
as a
in this form,
5.12
198
G: A--+ B a· K-aomodel if
We call a functor
K:
factorizes through
0
C--+ lA P,VJ
-
G for some
T: B --+ C.
as
(5.49)
KT
0!
K is fully faithful by Theorem 5.1,
Since
(5.49) more explicitly as a
We can write
V-natural isomorphism
B(GA,B)
=
(5.50)
C(KA,TB) .
K trivially factorizes through itself, we have:
The dense We write
K: A --+ C is always itself a
K-Com[A,BJ
K-comodels, and
for the subcategory of
K-Com[A,BJ(K)
exists.
More generally, for any
K-Com[A,BJ(Z)
for the intersection
The name
"K-comodel" for a
[A,BJ
A and
given by the
K-comodels Z: A--+
G for which
V,
we write
K-Com[A,BJ n [A,BJ(Z).
G: A--+ B satisfying (5.49) is
inspired by the fact (see 5.13 below) that a dense least for small
( 5. 51)
K-comodel.
for the intersection of this with
[A,BJ(K) - that is, the category of those LanKG
B--+ [A P,V]
T is unique to within isomorphism if it exists.
such a
Since
0
G:
cocomplete
C,
K: A--+ C,
at
may be thought of as a very
general kind of essentially-algebraic theory, a model of which in is a functor
0
H: A P --+ P
in the sense above. K-Mod[A0 P,PJ
of
such that
G
= H0 p:
A
0
P p
--+
P
is a comodel
These models constitute a full subcategory 0
[A P,PJ,
isomorphic to
0
(K-Com[A,P P]) 0 P,
If we talk
here of comodels rather than models, it is because we have elected to emphasize left Kan extensions and colimits, rather than their duals. Particular examples of such theories are given in 6.2
and 6.3 below.
(5 . 49)- (5. 54)
199
Rather than establish directly the promised equivalence Ladj[A,BJ
~
K-Com[A,BJ(K),
we first prove a more general result,
itself of value in practice:
A~
Theorem 5.52 Let the dense K: of
V and a fully-faithful
Z: A-+
z
Theorem 5.13, both
and
C be (isomorphic to) the composite V-+ C (so that, by
J:
are also dense).
J
Then
~e
have an
equivalence Lanz ~hose
[Z,l]: J-Com[V,BJ ~ K-Com[A,BJ(Z),
--1
unit and counit are the canonical maps.
Proof Let HE J-Com[V,B],
so that, corresponding to (5.50), we have
B(HD,B) for some
T:
C(JZA,TB)
~
(HZ) (K
(5. 53)
B--+ C.
explicitly as
D = ZA
Putting
C(KA,TB);
C(JD,TB)
showing that KT.
(5.54)
in this gives
HZ
is a
Since (4.49) gives
B(HZA,B)
~
K-comodel, and giving Z
~
KJ,
we have
being fully faithful)
which by (4.20) shows that
H
~
Lanz(HZ);
moreover the unit of this
Kan extension is easily calculated by Theorem 4.6 to be 1: HZ--+ HZ. Since we have seen that (Z)
K-Corn[A,BJ
that
Z~
H
for
KJ,
is a
K-cornodel, it does indeed lie in
. G E K-Corn[A,BJ
Now let Writing
HZ
LanZG, we have
(Z)
,
so that
G;;;
KT
for some
T: B--+ C.
using (4.20) for the first step, and recalling
5.12
200
C(JD, TB),
B(HD,B) H = Lan 2G belongs to
which is (5.54), showing that Putting
D
=
ZA
G ~HZ,
B(HZA,B) ~ C(KA,TB); the
in (5.54) gives as before
latter now being
B(GA,B)
J-Com[V,BJ
by (5.50), Yoneda gives an isomorphism
which is easily verified to be the unit
G --+ (Lan 2 G)Z
of
0
the Kan extension.
Since the unit and counit of the equivalence (5.53) are the canonical maps, it follows that J-Com[V,BJ
and
[V BJJ/.Z
c
'
*
K-Com[A,BJ(Z)
[A,BJ(Z) ,
c
(5.55)
""
and that the equivalence (5.53) is just the restriction of the
[V BJJ/.Z ~ [A BJ(Z)
equivalence
'
*
, *
of (5.44).
Now consider the special case of Theorem 5.52 in which J
=
1c,
and
for which
Z
K.
=
B(SC,B)
-adjoint functor.
~
A
1c-comodel is by (5.50) a functor
C(C,TB)
for some
T;
V
=
C ,
S: C--+
B
that is, it is a left-
Thus Theorem 5.52 (together with (5.43)) gives the
following answer to the problem proposed at the beginning of 5.11:
Theorem 5.56 For a dense LanK
-I
[K, l]: [C ,BJ:K
K: A--+ C and any
o::::
K-Com[A,B](K)
Here, if C is cocomplete and A is smaZ!, Cocts[C,BJ;
aZong
K,
and if every
as when
may be replaced by
the equivalence
~ [A,BJ;K) restricts t(l an ef?uivale>tce
La~ --j [K,l]: .Ladj [C,BJ
by
B,
Ladj[C,B]
may be replaced
G: A--+ B admits a left Kan extension
A is smaU and B is cocompZete, K-Com[A,BJ.
(':>.57)
0
K-Com[A,BJ(K)
(5.55)-(5.58)
201
A is small and
Note that, when Y:
A--+ [A
0
by (4.30). (4.55),
P,VJ,
K
is the Yoneda embedding
A~ B,
Y-comodel is any functor
a
since
Y
Thus (5.57) is another generalization of the equivalence
different from
the generalization given by Theorem 5.31.
In the situation of Theorem 5.52, combining that theorem with Theorem 5.56 gives a diagram of multiple equivalences
~
Ladj[C,BJ
~
J-Com[V,BJ(J)
K-Com[A,BJ(K)
n
n
~
J-Com[V,BJ
K-Com[A,SJ(Z),
(5.58)
in which the horizontal maps from left to right are restrictions, and those from right to left are left Kan extensions. inclusions here, although equalities when cocomplete, are in general proper, even if
V
and
are small.
A= V
For let
and
Z
1,
J-comodel, since
1
Y
take
need not exist.
J:
V --+
and take
2;
To see this, let
since
{1}
by Theorem 5,17,
whence
a retract of
Clearly
[{2}
0
P,SetJ;
object of
2.
so that
{2}.
fails to exist.
Since
B
A is small and C
V;
then
{2}
A
1:
V--+ V JJ;
and let
is a Lan 1 3 0
yet J
be the
determined by the single two-
Set
by (5.17), so is
{1,2}
is dense by Proposition 5.20, as
JO
*
= V = Set,
{2}
is
be fully faithful and dense,
is dense in
{2}
JO
C
B
is cocomplete and
is isomorphic by (4.22) to
inclusion of the full subcategory -element set
C
The vertical
is
lv
bO,
the initial object of
would, if it existed, be the initial
has no initial object,
LanJlV
is
5.13
202 5.13
We now settle on the precise definition of an essentially
algebraic theory:
We have:
Theorem 5.59 For any dense equivalence
is
K: A--+ C with
K-Mod[A 0 P,VJ ~ C', UJhere
given by those C
C
A small and
V itself are usually called its
The models of the theory in
cocomplete.
algebras.
K: A--+ C with
namely, a dense
such that
C
X rh C
C'
small, there is an
is the subcategory of C
exists for aU
K-Mod[ Aop, VJ ~ C.
cotensored,
A
X
E
V.
Thus if
This is so in partiau lar if
C is cocomplete. Proof Since
V0 p
Ladj[C,V 0 P],
or equivalently
is cocomplete, Theorem 5.56 gives
-adjoint functors
C p--+
0
0
K-Mod[A P,V] ~ (Ladj[C,V p]) p; 0
this last category is equivalent to 0
0
K-Com[A,V P] ~
0
Radj[C P,V].
and
But all right-
V lie in the subcategory C c [C 0 P,V]
given by the representables, and constitute in fact the category of the theorem.
C'
The last assertion follows from Proposition 5.15. ~
This leads to the following point of view.
If
C is a cocomplete
category admitting a small dense subcategory, any choice of a dense K: A--+ C with small which
A gives an essentially algebraic theory, for
C is the category of algebras.
As long as we consider models
of the theory only in complete categories
.
K·
is independent of the choice of called a
C-object in
P,
the concept of a model
a model of the theory in
P,
also
is by Theorem 5.56 just a continuous (and
hence right-adjoint) functor P .__,. P'
P,
0
C P
P.
--+
At this level, any continuous
carries models to models; and any model in
by applying the continuous functor
0
C p --+ p
P is so obtained
to the generic model
(5. 59) in
203
0
C p
1.· C0 p - C0 P.
given by
generic model in
0
C P
corresponds to
0
c,
K: A --+
In terms of 0
0
K P: A P--+ C P,
this
which is a
model by (5.51). The choice of
P when P is not complete.
a model in
dense functor with in
C of
C affects to some extent the notion of
K: A->-
A'
K and of
Theorem 5.13.
small, let
.
K'.
V
be the union of the full images
then the inclusion
J:
V->-
C is dense by
Thus Theorem 5.52 gives, in an evident notation,
K-Mod[A P,P](Z) ~ K'-Mod[A' 0 P,PJ(Z'). 0
0
and
K': A'--+ C is another
If
K'-Nod[A' P,P]
coincide when
all right Kan extensions along
It follows that
K-Mod[A 0 P,PJ
P is "complete enough" to admit
Z: A--+
V
and
V.
Z': A'--+
A
concrete example of such "sufficient completeness" will occur in 6.4 below. We end with three remarks.
First, it is easily seen that, for
P and P' • a right-adjoint functor P --+ P'
any to
K-models.
Secondly, the dense
theory of an object"; for, for any
P.
Thirdly, if
I
K-models
takes
I: I-->- V of (5.17) is "the
being
1,
we have
0
I-Mod[I p ,P] ar P
P too is cocomplete with a small dense
subcategory (and hence complete by Proposition 5.15), the notion of a C-object in right-adjoint
P coincides with that of a P-object in C: C0 p --+ p has as its left adjoint
in effect a right adjoint
5.14
S:
C ~B.
0
p --+ C p
what is
0
P p->- C.
We now determine the image, under the equivalence
K-Com[A,BJ(K)
for a
Ladj[C,BJ ~
of (5.57), of the subcategory of equivaZenaes
We do not suppose
A small nor C cocomplete; but we do
restrict ourselves to the simpler case of a fuZZy-faithful dense K: A --+ C.
5.14
204
B to be equivalent
We thus get a criterion for a given category to
C,
in terms of there being a
G: A--+ B
K-comodel
satisfying
our characterization of the image in question; this contains as a
B to be
special case the criterion of Theorem 5.26 above for 0
[A P,VJ.
equivalent to
We give only a few applications below;
numerous others can be found in the article the results (in the case
V
= Set)
If there is an equivalence
under (5.57) is the B(GA,B) = B(SKA,B) (5.50), exhibits -inverse of
S.
~
this
T
T: B
'="
C,
the image of
SK: A--+
B.
Since we have
K-comodel
G
C(KA,TB),
the unique
G~
=
KT
S
T which, as in (5.49) or
K-comodel, is precisely the equivalenceK-comodel
G: A--+ B,
as in (5.49), and seek conditions for
to be an equivalence.
This isomorphism B(GA,B) :;;; C(KA,TB) the form
---1
We therefore start with any
exhibited as such by
of Diers, to whom
are due.
S
G as being a
[21]
a=
a:
G-
KT,
written as a
V-natural isomorphism
as in (5.50), is (by Yoneda in the form (1.48)) of
C(p,l)T
(1.39) expressing the
for some
V-natural
V-naturality of y
p
---------------~
p: K--+ TG.
The diagram
may be written as
KK
GG - - ---::G:-----+ KTG 0
where
K
is the map of (4.22), according ·to which
isomorphism exactly when
G is fully faithful.
K
G
Since
is an K is fully
faithful, both the horizontal maps here are isomorphisms; whence,
205
since
K is fully faithful,
is an isomorphism if and only if G
p
is fuZZy faithful. By Theorem 5.56,
admits a left adjoint
T
admits a left Kan extension
S
n
an equivalence precisely when
TSK.
Let
Y
*
F
y
of
py
c; ;,
so.
Since the left-adjoint
finally that n
and the coZimits Once
n
KT,
preserves these colimits if and only i f
TS
S
with K
n:
1 --+ TS
is an isomorphism and TS
p
preserves and reflects these colimits, and because conclude that
is
A under the
Because the fully-faithful
.
T
It is
p: K--+ TG
It now follows that
~.
is an isomorphism if and only if preserves the coUmits of
are isomorphisms.
is the closure of
C
Then
be a density presentation of
Y YE
as in Theorem 5.19, so that
E
G
Suppose for the moment
identifies
= (F ,P ) r
t
K-absolute colimits
and
G ~ SK
clear that the isomorphism ~
K.
precisely when
n,E: S ~ T be the adjunction.
that this is so, and let
nK: K
along
S
K both we GS
does
preserves all colirnits, we have
is an isomorphism if and onZy if G is fully faithful F
y
*
SP
y
are
G-ahsoZute.
is known to be an isomorphism,
by the triangular equation
Tc.nT
=
T£
is an isomorphism
1 of the adjunction.
So
£
too
is an isomorphism if T is conservative; which of course T must be if it is an equivalence.
Since
G - KT
T is conservative if and onZy if
G
where
K
is fully faithful,
is conservative; that is, if
and only if G: A--+ B is strongly generating.
(In contrast to 3.6,
we are using "strongly generating" here without thereby implying that
A
is small.)
5.14
206
s.
It remains to ensure the existence of the left adjoint
y ~ r,
colimits for all
F -indexed
B admits all
Propositions 3.36 and 3.37 give this if
y
but this is more than we need.
The proof of
Proposition 3.36 shows that we only need the (inductive) existence of
Fy * SPy
the particular colimits
in
B.
Since we can run
simultaneously the inductive proof of the existence of
n: 1
inductive proof that
TS
--+
S
and the
is an isomorphism, we have finally:
Theorem 5.60 Let K: A --+ C be fully faithful and dense, with (F ,P )
density presentation K-aomodd with
G :o:
y
y y
Then
KT.
~
r T
>
G: A --+ B be a
and let
is an equivalenae if and only if the
following aonditions are satisfied (whereupon
K ~ TG):
is fuZly faithful.
(i)
G
(ii)
G is strongly generating (or, equivalently,
(iii)
Whenever exists in is
Py
;;;
T'- [A P,VHYPY-,Y'\) 0
y
(6.9)
corresponds by (3.5) to a map
9 : F y
y
*
YP
y
--...,. YA
y
(6.10)
(6. 7)-(6.12)
219
in the cocomplete maps; because
8
Theorem 6.11
is small, the set of codomains in (6.10) is small, so
A
If the regulus
~-Com[A,BJ
then ~-Alg
for any category
is the reflective subcategory
when the cylinders Proof
8 corresponds as above to the sketch
= 0-Com[A,BJ
8-Alg
K: A --->- ~Alg
corresponding dense functor
B(G-,B)
P,V](F y
*
In particular
of [A0 P,V].
The
is fuZZy faithful precisely
G: A --+
is orthogonal in
0
that is, when each
B.
~.
are already colimit-cylinders in A.
~Y
By the remarks at the end of 6.2,
precisely when each
0
for the set of these
{e } yyEf
e is indeed a regulus in the sense of 6.2.
that
[A
=
B is a
0
[A P,VJ
8-comodel
to each
e ; y
0
[A P,V](8 ,1): [A P,V](YA ,B(G-,B))--->Y y YP ,B(G-,B)) is an isomorphism. By (3.5) and Yoneda, y
this map is isomorphic to a map
B(GA ,B) y
----+
[L 0 P,V](F ,B(GP -,B)) , y
y
(6.12)
y
whose unit is easily verified to be (6.8); to say that it is an isomorphism is therefore by (3.5) to say that (6.8) is a colimit-cylinder, or that G is a
~-comodel.
Theorem 5.59 the equality By Proposition 5.16, contains the representab1es
~-Alg
gives by
K is fully faithful if and only if A(-,A).
To ask each
A(-,A)
¢-Alg
to be an
0
A(A y ,A)--+ [L yP,VJ(F y ,A(Py -,A))
be an isomorphism, and hence by (3.5) that each
0
Vp
= 8-Alg.
algebra is by (6.12) to ask that each
-cylinder.
0
Applying this to the comodels in
~
y
be a colimit-
6.3
In particular,
· · is re fl ect1ve 1n
~Alg
of all small colimit-cylinders in
[ V op , S e t'-.I
v0 '
r,
A0 p, V -]
when
"'~
consists
V0 " in
A; the reflectivity of
of 3.12 above is an example of this.
0
A very important special case of Theorem 6.11 is that where
F
F-cocomplete for some set
=
(A 0 P,~)
F-Cocts[A,BJ
~-Alg
and
~
of the sketch
F-colimits in
0
small
V
For instance, with
([52], [ 7 ]) Ap
In this case
0
F-Cts[A P,Vj.
The full name 0
might here be replaced by
also suggestive to refer to a small
F-theory.
=
A.
0
is a small category
A p
0
A p
It is as an
a Lawvere-Benabou theory with finite products; while a
sometimes called a finitar;~
with finite limits is
essentially-aZgebraic theory.
(A P,F).
F-complete category
Set,
=
is
~
of small indexing-types, and where
consists of (the units of) all the ¢-Com[A,BJ
A
(Joyal suggests calling the latter a
cartesian theory; in that finite limits may be said to go back to Descartes, {(x,y)
I
0
A p-Alg
who introduced both the product
f(x,y) = g(x,y) }.) (F
R x R
and the equalizer
This terminology moreover allows
being understood) as a useful abbreviation for
0
F-Cts[A P, VJ. 0
CA P,~)
Consider now a sketch
where
~
is given by (6.7); let
F be a set of small indexing-types containing each O·
'
and let
and
B
be a small
L: B--+ 8°p~Alg
=
F-cocomplete category. 0
F-Cts[B P,V]
observing by Theorem 6.11 since
L
is also an
that
0
a
-y
Write
occurring in K: A--+
~-Alg
for the respective dense functors, is fully faithful.
Note that,
L-comodel by (5.51), we have:
Proposition 6.13 For a small L: B--+ Bop_Alg
L
F
F-Cts[B P,V]
F-cocomplete
B, the dense inclusion
preserves and reflects
F-colimits.
0
(6.13)-(6.16)
221
Consider a
~-comodel
G: A
~B.
F-cocontinuous functor, the composite Taking
0
=Vp
V
here,
If QG
B - - 7 V is any
Q:
is clearly another
0
we see that
$-comodel.
0
[G P,l]: [8°P,VJ--+ [A P,VJ
restricts to a functor (6.14) Such a functor between the categories of algebras, induced by a 0
realization (that is, a model) often said to be algebraic: F-cocomplete and
Gp
of one theory in the other, is
especially in the case where
~
K: $-Alg --+ [A 0 p, VJ
and 0
fully faithful, since the left adjoint adjoint
-
* L,
A too is
0
0
[c P,l]: [B P,V]--+ [A P,VJ
LanGop•
and since
L
are
has by Theorem 4.50
has by Theorem 4.51 the left
it follows that the algebraic functor
G
has the
left adjoint (-* L).
The value of this at is also
(KP)
*
P
(LG);
E
K
LanG 0 P. 0
B p-Alg
is
(Lan
so that by (4.17)
G0 P
(KP))
* L,
which by (4.65)
we have (6.15)
Lan (LG). K
In fact
G is recoverable from
G*.
First observe that
Proposition 6.13 gives:
Proposition 6.16
In the circumstances above,
-comodel. 0
of '!>-ComlA,B P-Alg]
Thus
given by_ the
6.3 222 Using this and (6.15), we have:
Theorem 6.17
Let the small
B be
F-cocompLete, wher•e the set
(A 0 P,~);
respective dense functors.
y
0
K: A~ $-Alg
and let
occurring in the sketch
F
small indexing-types contains aLl the
F of
and L: B ~ B P-Alg be the
Then the composite of the full inclusion sending
~-Com[A,BJ
G to
LG,
and the
equivalence
of Theorem 5.56• is isomorphic to a functor ( ) : ~-Com[A,B] __,. Ladj [)-Alg,B P-Alg] 0
(6 .18)
* sending
..
G to the left adjoint
G K
*
and the functor
( )*
of (6.18)
L as
According~y
(6.19)
is fuZZy faithful, ita image consisting
SK ~
LG
for which
SK
factors
for some (tssentiaZZy
D
We may consider this theorem in the case where F-cocomplete, and
=
0
(A P, F).
functors between these, and the the latter, form a form more; for
we have
LG
0
through the fully-faithful G.
=
S: -Alg ~ B P -Alg
of those left-adjoint
unique)
of c*.
G
F-theories
V-Cat
the
F-continuous
V-natural transformations between
2-category - that is,. a
F-CoctsrA,B]
We saw in 2.3 that
The
A too is
Cat-category.
is not just a category but a
In fact they V-category,
is symmetric monoidal closed; and what the
F-theories actually constitute is a
(V-Cat)-category.
There is a
(6.17)-(6.20)
223
( V-Cat) -functor into
V-CAT
sending the
and defined on hom-objects by (6.18).
A0 p
F-theory
A0 P-Alg
to
It is locally fully faithful,
in the sense that (6.18) is fully faithful.
Theorem 6.17 above
determines, in a certain sense, its local image; not as absolutely as 0
S: A p-Alg ~ B0 P-Alg
we should like, since the criterlon for
in this local image refers back to the inclusions of
to be
B.
A and
The
rem.aining step in determining globally the image of this
(V-Cat)-functor
is that of characterizing the
0
V-categories of the form
A p-Alg.
For this we can get something from Theorem 5.60; in the absence of any particularly simple density presentation of
* K
can just use the canonical one
KC
Proposition 6.20
A is
0
A P-Alg
be an
If the small
~
0
K: A--+ A p-Alg,
C from Theorem 5.19.
we
We have:
F-cocomplete and K: A--+
is the fully-faithfUl dense functor as above, let
G: A--+ V
F-cocontinuous functor, and hence a K-comodel; and define
T: V--+ A0 P-Alg
by
G~
KT.
In order that
T be an equivalence,
the following conditions are necessary and sufficient: (i)
V is cocomplete.
(ii)
G is fully faithful and strongly generating.
(iii)
The canonical map
0
0
A P-Alg(KA,C) --+ V(GA,A P-Alg(K-,C)
*
G)
is an isomorphism. Proof
The conditions are clearly necessary.
refer not to Theorem 5.60 but to its proof. G admits a left Kan extension a left adjoint to
T.
For
n
S and
along ~
K,
For their sufficiency we Since
V
is cocomplete,
which by Theorem 5.56 is
to be isomorphisms, we need
6.3
224 that
G
is fully faithful and strongly generating (which is (ii)) KC * SK
and that the colimit
last requirement is that and as
G
givin!-'
(iii).
is
G-absolute.
*
V(GA,KC
G)
SK ~ G,
Since
be isomorphic to
is fully faithful the latter is
KC * A(A,-)
this
*
KC or
V(GA,G-);
(KC)A,
II
Again this recognition theorem is not as absolute as we should
A0 p-Alg.
like, in that condition (iii) refers in detail to 0
when both
V and
0
A p ~ A p-Alg
better description of the image of
A far
is often available
F are suitably restricted - see for example
[45].
The fact is that we are coming to the end of what can usefully be said in the present generality.
6.4 One last series of importaPt observations can however be made. Call a sketch If all the
FY
(A P,~) 0
small if the set
~
-types, the smallness of
of cylinders is small.
lie in a small set
~
occurring in
¢
F of indexing-
is automatic; for the small
A admits
but a small set of cylinders with any given indexing-type.
Let
Proposition 6.21
0
(A P,~)
indexing-tyFes cnZy fPom the
be a small sketch b'hich 1"nvC'!.ves
smaZ~
set
be the corresponding dense functor. F-colimits in
J:
V--> C;
dense, so that in particular
--+
C = 4>-Alg
V be
it is small by 3.5.
Z: A--+ V
by TheoPem 5.13 both
J: C--+ [V0 P,VJ is
assert that the r~pZete image of
K: A
Let V be the closure under
C of the fuZZ image of K;
the factorization of K through fuZZ inclusion
and Zet
J is
fol~owed
z and
J
Let
by the are
fuZ~y faithful.
F-Cts[V0 P,V].
We
(6. 21)
225
Proof
One direction is immediate.
V,
constructon of and hence
JC
so that
is
C(J-,C)
pop: vop -+V
-comodel by (5.51),
is
F-continuous.
and since the fully-faithful
p
-comodel.
Since
too is a
-comodel.
By Theorem 5. 56, we have
Vop
Theorem 4.47, ~
Lan Pz 2
SJ,
1: PZ--+ PZ
gives a map SJ
preserve
~:
SJ
since
K
=
JZ
with
PZ =
s
-
JZ
c
is
=
SK
t.;here the
LanKPZ,
By
fully faithful, we have
J
A an isomorphism.
with unit
Applying Theorem 4.43 to
as in
~:
SJ
--~
P
with
~Z
an isomorphism.
F-colimits, and since
--+
P
we have
Z
V
Since both
is the closure under
(which is the full image of
K),
P
and
F-colimits
we conclude
is an isomorphism.
The right-adjoint C(-,C),
v
of this left Kan extension being an isomorphism.
of the full image of that
J:
K
PZ: A__,. vop
F-cocontinuous,
is a left-adjoint functor given by
PZ __,. SK
unit
is
Since
Z: A-+V
F-colimits,
itself a
c __,.
V,
sends them to limits in
not only preserves but also reflects
S:
F-colimits by the
F-continuous.
Suppose now that is a
J preserves
S0 p: C0 p--+ V being necessarily a representable
p 0 P ~ S0 pJop ~ C(J-,C)
Now Theorem 6.11 gives:
= JC,
as required.
0
6.4
226 Corollary 6.22
In thene cirewnstanccs the functor
to the inclusion V ~ V0 P-Alg th.at for any
B
?..'e
of the sketch
¢,
F
V,
so
0
here is bounded only below by the knowledge 0
we cannot expect the comodels of the sketches
to "coincide" in eve:ry
and
F-cocomplete smaZZ
J-Com[V,B] = F-CoctsiV,BJ.
haVI?
Since the size of
of the
ts isomm-phic
J
B·
B
that they do so when
'
(A P,¢)
is
F-cocomplete is an example of the "sufficient completeness" referred to in the penultimate paragraph of 5.13.
The precise result is:
e~ery
Theorem 6.23
In the cir>cwnstances of Proposition 6.21,
~-comodel
A --+ B admits a left Kan extension alonJ Z: A --+ V
whenever
G:
B is Lan
F-cocomplete; and we have an equivalence
2
--1
[Z,l]: F-Cocts[V,B] ~ ¢-Com[A,BJ
whose unit and counit are the canonical maps.
Proof By Corollary 6.22 and TI1eorem 5.52, we have only to show that every
-comodel G: A-+ B has the form
HZ
for some
F-cocontinuous
H: V--+ B. We suppose first that
L: B--+ 6°p-Alg
B is small, and consider the inclusion
of Proposition 6.13.
LG,
Then
being itself a
-comodel as in Proposition 6.16, is by Theorem 5.56 isomorphic to for some left-adjoint of (6.19).
B c:
8°P-Alg
The set
S: -Alg--+ 8°p-Alg;
H of those objects
left-adjoint
.c (
c
certainly contains all the objects
and it is closed under S
s
in fact
is the
G*
sc
lies in
for which KA,
since
SK
-
F-colimits by Proposition 6.13, since the
preserves colimits; hence
H
contains
SK
V
by the
LG;
(6.22)-(6.23)
227
definition of this latter, is clearly and
(L
SJ ~ LH
Thus
F-cocontinuous since SJ
H: V--+ B,
for some
is so.
LG ~ SK
Now
being fully faithful) we have the desired result
Passing to the case where the let
B'
be the closure under
the
~-comodel
A--+ B;
G:
F-colimits,
G'
Now
G-;: HZ, 0
We may say that
(A P,~), 0
where
is the
V p
(A P,~) 0
or that
G'
= H'Z H
B.
Since
~-comodel;
is itself a
small by 3.5, we have as above H': V--+ B',
N: B' --+
=
is
G':
N
A--+
B'
preserves and
and since
for some NH'
G-;: HZ.
of the full image of
this latter factorizing as
followed by the full inclusion reflects
B
SJZ -;: LHZ;
=
B need not be small,
F-cocomplete
F-colimits in
which
B'
is
F-cocontinuous
0
F-cocontinuous.
F-theory generated by the sketch
is a sketch of the
0
F-theory
V P.
The
latter form of words comes closer to explicating Ehresmann's choice of the word "sketch". small category
V =Set),
As he used the word (in the case
A
the
was not in general explicitly given, but presented
by generators and relations; often this presentation was finite, and ~
was a finite set of finite cones (the colimits involved in
classically being conical ones), (A p .~) 0
(the presentation of)
In such cases, one can literally see as a finitary way of ''sketching" the or the still more
generally infinite and complicated structure of complicated structure of
When
V =Set
ar.d
for finite
L,
the sketch
(A P,~)
the 0
of finite cones. that are the
F
0
V p-Alg.
F
consists of the functors
61:
L ~Set
F-theories are the cartesian theories of 6.3 above; gives rise to such a theory if
It is exactly the categories
~-Alg
locally finitely presentable categories;
¢
is a small set for such a
V c ¢-Alg
Q
is
6.4
228 a small dense subcategory composed of objects which (since finite limits commute with filtered colimits in
Set)
V
all the examples of categories
0
are finitely presentable.
that we declared locally finitely
presentable in 6.1, it is easy to see that ~.
sketch
V
0
= ~-Alg
than
for such a
For further information on the relation of locally presentable
categories to reguli and sketches, see the classical newer
In
[45]
[31J,
which extends the ideas to certain important
or the
V
other
Set.
V include
These
Cat
and
Gpd,
which are the
appropria~e
base
categories for the study of categories with essentially-algebraic structure.
At this level, as is well known, equivalence becomes more
central than isomorphism, and the naturally-occurring "functors" and "transformations" are more general than the
V-functors and the
V-natural transformations; which leads to various problems of coherence. The study of essentially-algebraic theories in this context must take account of these more general notions; this is not touched on in but a beginning is made in
6.5
[45],
[46].
Before ending, we give a final application of Theorem 6.23.
consider the where
F
(V-Cat)-category of small
We
F-cocomplete categories
is a small set of indexing-types.
Since
A,
F-CoctsfA,BJ
denotes the
(V-Cat)-valued hom here, an appropriate name for this
category is
F-Cocts.
If
B and
C are
F-cocomplete, so of course is
F-colimits formed pointwise. this is again
The full subcategory
[B,CJ,
with
F-Cocts[B,C]
F-cocomple te, since colimi ts commute with colimi ts.
of
(6.24)
229
Q: A--+ F-Cocts[B,C]
The functors P: A~
B--+
correspond to those functors
C for which each partial functor
F-cocontinuous.
If
A
too is
B--+
P(A,-):
Q is itself
F-cocomplete, the functor
F-cocontinuous precisely when the other partial functors are also
F-cocontinuous.
P: A ~ B --+ C which is Such a
P
T: L --+A,
F-cocontinuous in each variable separately. 0
((A~ B) P,~).
is a cylinder in
we can consider for
A, B
E
F: L0 p
where B
L
to
(TL,B),
and called
If
--+
V and
the functor
--,T,---~-=-B--+ A ~
sending
P(-,B): A--+ C
We are thus led to the notion of a
is a comodel for a sketch
A: F--+ A(T-,M)
C is
T ®B.
B
Then we can consider the
cylinder F --+ A(T- ,M) ;;;-ACT- ,M) ~I ~1 . A(T-,M) ~ B(B ,B)= (A® B) ( (T-,B) '(M,B))'
A
~J
and call this if
A is one in
colimits. A ®
A ®B.
~.
A;
Note that this is a colimit-cylinder in essentially because
If we take
where
~
A is an
F-colimit-cylinder in precisely those
P
- ® Y: V
to consist of all the F-colimit-cylinder in
B,
~-comodels
the
that are
--+
A® B
V preserves
A ® B and all the A and
P: A® E
--+
~
is an C are
F-cocontinuous in each variable.
In fact
more than this is true; it is easy to see that ~-Com[A ~
B,CJ
-
for the
Write ((A® B) 0 P,~).
F-Cocts[A,F-cocts[B,C]]. F-theory generated by the sketch
In view of Theorem 6.23, we get
F-Cocts[A atFB,CJ
::::
F-cocts[A,F-Cocts[B,CJJ •
(6.24)
6.5
230 The symmetry in
B,
A,
C
of
F-Cocts[A,F-Cocts[B,F-Cocts[C,VJJJ
now
easily gives (6.25)
and (6.26)
If
A
is the free
F-cocompletion of
clear that (for any small
A
and
A
as in Theorem 5.35, it is
B) (6.27)
it is also clear that, for any small
A
F-cocontinuous functors
correspond to the functors
P:
A ® B --~
C
A®FB--+ C
for which each
P(A,-)
and for
is
F-cocomplete
F-cocontinuous.
B,
the
It follows
that
(6.28)
where
1
is the free
is the closure of
I
F-cocompletion of in
V under
I;
which by Theorem 5.35
F-colimits.
The coherence, in the appropriate sense, of the maps (6.25), (6.26), and (6.28), follows from the universal property (V-Cat)-category
(6.24).
Thus the
F-Cocts is endowed with something like a symmetric
monoidal closed structure - the difference being that we have equivalences in place of isomorphisms.
(b.~5)-(b.28)
2 31
Bibliography l 1,
C. Auderset, Adjonctions et monades au niveau des
Cahiers de Top. et atom. Diff. [2]
H. Bass, AZgebraie
2-categories,
15(1974), 3-20.
K-theory, W.A. Benjamin Inc., New York and
Amsterdam, 1968. [3J
A. Bastiani and C. Ehresmann, Categories of sketched structures,
Cahiers de Top. et ~4
13(1972), 103-214.
J. Benabou, Categories avec multiplication, C.R. Acad. Sci.
Paris [5]
G~om. Diff.
256(1963), 1887-1890.
J. Benabou, Categories relatives, C.R. Acad. Sci. Paris 260(1965), 3824-3827.
_o_
J. Benabou, Introduction to bicategories, Lecture Notes in Math.
47(1967)' 1-77. -7
J. Benabou, Structures algebriques dans les categories, Cahiers
de Top. et Geom. Diff. 10(1968), 1-126. [8]
J. Benabou, Les distributeurs, Univ. Cath. de Louvain, Seminaires
de Math. Pure, Rapport No. 33(1973). [9:
F. Borceux and G.M. Kelly, A notion of limit for enriched categories, Bu~l.
[10]
Austra~.
Math. Soc. 12(1975), 49-72.
M. Bunge, Relative functor categories and categories of algebras,
J. Algebra
11(1969), 64-101.
Bibliography
2 32
[ 11]
E. Brown, Cohomology theories, Ann. Math. 75(1962), 467-484.
[ 12J
B.J. Day, On closed categories of functors,Lecture Notes in tJ,,LI ..
[13
1 l7( 1970J,
1-'Jtl.
B.J. Day, Construction of biclosed categories
(Ph.D. Thesis,
University of New South Wales, 1970).
[14]
B.J. Day, A reflection theorem for closed categories, J. Pure
AppZ. Algebm [ 15]
2(1972), 1-ll.
B.J. Day, On adjoint-functor factorization, Lecture f,'otes i"l Math. 420(1974), 1-19.
[16]
B.J. Day, On closed categories of functors II, Lecture l.'otes
in [17]
Math. 420(1974), 20-54.
B.J. Day, An embedding theorem for closed categories, Lzcture Notes
[18]
in Math. 420(1974), 55-64.
B.J. Day, An adjoint-functor theorem over topoi, P•~i.
15(1976), 381-394.
B.J. Day and G.M. Kelly, On topological quotient by pullbacks or products, PY'oc. ('rqr>broi?;;" p;.,n.
~aps E~n.
preserved
67( 1970),
S S l- S'i R.
[20]
B.J. Day and G.M. Kelly, Enriched functor categories, L~~turr rJotes {n Math.
[21]
106(1969), 178-191..
Y. Diers, Type de densit~ d'une sous-cat~gorie pleine, A;;n. S(le.
Scirnt. Bruxelles
90(1976), 25-47.
Index [22]
233 E.J. Dubuc, Kan extensions in enriched category theory,
Lectu:t'e
Notes in Math. 145(1970). [23]
E.J. Dubuc and H. Porta, Convenient categories of topological algebras, and their duality theory, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 3(1971)' 281-316.
[24]
C. Ehresmann, Esquisses et types de structures algebriques,
Bul. Inst. Polit. [25:
Ia~i
S. Eilenberg and G.M. Kelly, A generalization of the functorial calculus, J. Algebra
[26]
14(1968), 1-14.
3(1966), 366-375.
S. Eilenberg and G.M. Kelly, Closed categories, Proc. Conf. on
Categorical Algebra
(La Jolla, 1965), Springer-Verlag, Berlin-
-Heidelberg-New York, 1966; 421-562. [27]
J. Fisher-Palmquist and P.H. Palmquist, Morita contexts of enriched categories, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 50(1975), 55-60.
[28]
P.J. Freyd, Abelian categories:
an introduction to the theory
of functors, Harper and Row, New York, Evanston, and London, 1964. [29]
P.J. Freyd, Several new concepts:
lucid and concordant functors,
pre-limits, pre-completeness, the continuous and concordant completions of categories, Lectu:t'e Notes in Math. 99(1969), 196-241. [30]
P.J. Freyd and G.M. Kelly, Categories of continuous functors I,
J. Pure Appl. Algebra Algebra
4(1974), 121.
2(1972), 169-191; Erratum, J. Pu:t'e Appl.
Bibliography
234 [31J
P. Gabriel and F. Ulmer,
Lecture Notes in Math. [32J
Kategorien~
221(1971).
J.W. Gray, Closed categories, lax limits and homotopy limits,
J. Pure Appl. Algebra [33]
Lokal prasentierbare
19(1980), 127-158.
M.F. Gouzou and R. Grunig, U-distributeurs et
cat~gories
de
modules, Manuscript, Univ. de Paris 7, 1975. [34]
A. Grothendieck,
Cat~gories
geometrie algebrique de [35]
fibr~es
l'I.H.E.S.~
et descente, Seminaire de Paris, 1961.
J.R. Isbell, Adequate subcategories, Illinois J. !42th. 4(1960), 541-552.
[36]
J.R. Isbell, Structure of categories, Bull. Amer. !'2th. Soc. 72(1966), 619-655.
[37]
J.R. Isbell, General functorial semantics I, Amer. J. Uath. 94(1972), 535-596.
[38J
D.N. Kan, Adjoint functors, Trans. Amer. ~ath. Soc. 87(1958), 294-329.
[39]
G.M. Kelly, On Mac Lane's conditions for coherence of natural associativities, cornmutativities, etc., J. Algebra
1(1964),
397-402.
[40]
G.M. Kelly, Tensor products in categories, J. AlJ~bra
2(1965),
l 5- \7.
[41]
G.M. Kelly, Monornorphisms, epimorphisrns, and pull-backs,
J. Austral. Math. Soc. 9(1969), 124-142.
Index [42]
235 G.M. Kelly, Adjunction for enriched categories, Lecture Notes
in Math. 420(1969), 166-177. [43]
G.M. Kelly, Doctrinal adjunction, Lecture Notes in Math. 420(1974), 257-280.
[44]
G.M. Kelly, A unified treatment of transfinite constructions for free algebras, free monoids, colimits, associated sheaves, and so on,
:45~
Bu~~.
AustraZ. Math. Soc. 22(1980), 1-83.
G.M. Kelly, Structures defined by finite limits in the enriched context, Cahiers de Top. et
[46]
G~om.
Diff. 1981, to appear.
G.M. Kelly, Categories with structure- biadjoints for algebraic functors, to appear.
[47~
G.M. Kelly and S. Mac Lane,
J. Pure AppZ. AZgebra A~gebra
[48]
Coherence in closed categories,
1(1971), 97-140; Erratum, J. Pure
App~.
1(1971), 219.
G.M. Kelly and S. Mac Lane, Closed coherence for a natural transformation, Lecture Notes in Math. 281(1972), 1-28.
[49J
G.M. Kelly and R.H. Street, Review of the elements of
2-categories,
Lecture Notes in Math. 420(1974), 75-103. I50J
J.F. Kennison, On limit-preserving functors, IZZinois J. Math. 12(1968), 616-619.
[51]
A. Kock, Closed categories generated by commutative monads,
J. AustraZ. Math. Soc. 12(1971), 405-424.
Bibliography i
'>~
I
F .lv. Lawvere, Functorial semantics of algebraic theories,
PY.oc. Nat. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. [53]
50(1963), 869-872.
F.W. Lawvere, Teoria delle categorie sopra un topos di base, Mimeographed notes, Perugia 1972/1973.
[54]
F. \v. Lawvere, Metric spaces, generalized logic, and closed
categories, Rend. del Sem. Mat. e Fis. di Milano
43(1973),
135-166. [55 I
H. Lindner, Morita equivalences of enriched categories,
Cahiers de Top. et [56]
Diff. 15(1974), 377-397.
F.E.J. Linton, Autonomous categories and duality of functors,
J. Algebra [57]
G~om.
2(1965), 315-349; Erratum, J. Algebra
4(1966), 172.
F.E.J. Linton, Relative functorial semantics: adjointness results,
Lecture Notes in Math. 99(1969), 384-418. [58]
S. Mac Lane, Natural associativity and commutativity, Rice
Univ. Studies [59]
49(1963), 28-46.
S. Mac Lane, Categorical algebra, Bull. Amer.
~2th.
Soc.
71(1965), 40-106. [60]
S. Mac Lane, Categories for the Working Mathematician, Springer-Verlag, New York-Heidelberg-Berlin, 1971.
[61]
J.P. May, The geometry of iterated loor sr~ces,
in Math. 271( 1972).
Lecture Notes
Index [62]
237 J.P. May, Pairings of categories and spectra, J. Pure Appl.
Algebra [63]
19(1980), 299-346.
B. Mitchell, Low dimensional group cohomology as monoidal structures, to appear.
[64]
Ju. A. Mitropol'skii and L.A. Nazorova, editors:
Matrix Problems,
Akad.Nauk Ukrain. SSR Inst. Mat., Kiev, 1977. (in Russian) [65]
K.
~~rita,
Duality for modules and its application to the
theory of rings with minimum condition, Sci. Rep. Tokyo Kyoiku
Daigaku, Sect. A, 6(1958), 83-142. [66]
D. Newell, Morita theorems for functor categories, Trans. Amer.
Math. Soc. 168(1972), 423-434. [67]
J. Wick Pelletier, Dual functors and the Radon-Nikodym property in the category of Banach spaces, J. Austral. Math. Soc.
(Series AJ [68]
27(1979), 479-494.
S.V. Polin, Morita equivalence and the Jacobson-Rees theorems for rings and monoids in closed categories, Soviet Math.
Doklady
15(1974), 1248-1251.
[69J
E. Spanier, Quasi-topologies, Duke Math. J. 30(1963), 1-14.
[70]
R.H. Street, The formal theory of monads, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 2(1972), 149-168.
[71]
R.H. Street, Fibrations and Yoneda's lemma in a
Lecture Notes in Math. 420( 1974), 104-133.
2-category,
238 [72]
Bibliography R.H. Street, Elementary cosmoi I, Lecture Notes in Math. 420(1974), 134-180.
[73]
R.H. Street, extract from a letter to F. Foltz; to appear in
Diagrammes. [74]
R.H. Street and R.F.C. Walters, The comprehensive factorization of a functor, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 79(1973), 936-941.
[75]
R.F.C. Walters, Sheaves and Cauchy-complete categories,
Cahiers de Top. et [76]
G~om.
Diff.,
to appear.
R.F.C. Walters, Sheaves on sites as Cauchy-complete categories,
J. Pure Appl. Algebra, to appear.
239
Index Absolute colirnit, 187 K-absolute colirnit, 170 Accessible functor, 144 weakly accessible functor, 147 Adequate, 158 Adjoint, left, 49 partial, 50 right, 49 Adjoint functor theorem, general, 147 special, 150 Adjunction, 49 Algebra, 202 for a regulus, 218 for a sketch, 218 Algebraic functor, 221 Atom, 149 Bicategory, 34 Biclosed bicategory, 34 monoidal category, 34 Boolean algebra, 35 Cartesian closed category, 33 Cartesian rnonoidal category, 21 Cartesian theory, 220 Category, cartesian closed 33 cartesian monoidal, 21 enriched over V, 23 functor -, 59 monoidal, 21 monoidal biclosed, 34 monoidal closed, 33 of elements of F, 48 symmetric monoidal, 30 symmetric monoidal closed, 35 underlying, 26 2-category, 24 Cauchy complete, 176 Cauchy completion, 176 Closed monoidal category, 33 Closure under a family of colimits, 86 under a family of cylinders, 154 Co complete, 74 F-cocomplete, 183 Cocompletion, free, 126 Cocontinuous, 75 F-cocontinuous, 183 Codense, 158 Coend, 101
240 Cogenerator, strong, 88 Coherence axioms, 21, 28, 29 Cointersection, 209 Co limit, 7l absolute, 187 classical, 81 conical, 81, 96, 99 F-colimit, 183 filtered, 134 K-absolute, 170 iterated, 98 pointwise, 77 Comodel, 198 for a regulus, 218 for a sketch, 218 Complete, 74 finitely, 132 Completion, Cauchy, 176 idempotent-splitting, 186 under F-colimi ts, 185 under finite colimits, 188 Component, connected, 84 of a V-natural transformation, 25 Composition law, 23 Comprehensive factorization system, 136 Cone, 81 canonical inductive, 82 projective, 81 Conical limit or colimit, classical, 81 in a V-category, 94, 96, 99 Connected component, 84 Conservative, 23, 87 Continuous, 75 Continuity of a limit in its index, 80 Contravariant functor, 31 respresentable, 37 Copower, 92 Cotensor product, 91 Cotensored, 92 Counit, of a general end, 100 of a limit, 72 of an adjunction, 49 of an end in V, 54 of a representation, 47 of a right Kan extension, 113 Cowellpoweredness, weak, 91 Cylinder, 73 K-cylinder, 152
Index
241
Index Dense, 158 Density presentation, 172 Diagonal fill-in, 208 Diagram, 71 Directed, 133 Discrete Grothendieck construction, Discrete op-fibration, 136 Distributor, 176 Dual V-category, 30
139
(E,~I)-generator, 209 Element, of X E V, 23 of a set-valued functor, 48 End, in V, 54 in any V-category, 100 Epimorphism, extremal, 84 Equivalence, 51 Essentially algebraic theory, 198, 202 finitary, 220 Essentially surjective, 51 Evaluation, 33, 59 Extremal epimorphism, 84 Extraordinary V-naturality, 40
F-colirni t, 183 F-cocomplete, 183 F-cocontinuous, 183 F-theory, 220 Factorization system, 138 comprehensive, 136 proper, 208 Filtered category, 133 a-filtered, 136 Filtered colimit, 134 Final diagram, 130 Final functor, 130 Finitary, 220 Finite-colimit completion, 188 Finitely complete, 132 Finitely presentable, 155 Flat, 190 Free cocompletion, 126 Free V-category, 68 Fubini theorem, for ends in V, general, 78 Full image, 53 Full subcategory, 25
Fully faithful, 25 locally, 221
57
Index
242 Functor, algebraic, 221 conservative, 23 contravariant, 31 contravariant representable, enriched over V, 24 flat, 190 fully faithful, 25 generating, 88 of two variables, 31 partial, 31 representable, 36, 47 underlying, 2 7 2-functor, 25 Functor category, 59
37
General adjoint functor theorem, 147 Generating functor, 88 Generator, 88 (E,M)-generator, 209 regular, 152 strong, 88 Generic model, 202 Grothendieck construction, discrete, 139 Heyting algebra, 35 Hom, internal, 33 Idempotent, split, 186 Idempotent monad, 53 Idempotent-splitting completion, Identity element, 23 Image, full, 53 replete, 53 Indexed colimit, 73 Indexed limit, 72 Indexing type, 71 Inductive cone, canonical, 82 Initial diagram, 129 Initial functor, 130 Interchange, of ends in V, 57 of limits in general, 80 Internal hom, 33 Intersection of subobjects, 149 of M-subobjects, 208 Iterated colimit, 98 K-absolute colimit, 170 K-comodel, 198 K-cylinder, 152 K-model, 198 Kan adjoint, 125 Kan extension, 113' 115 pointwise, 123 weak, 122
186
Index
243
Left adequate, 158 Left adjoint, 49 Left exact, 132 Left Kan extension, 115 weak, 122 Limit, conical, 81, 94, 99 indexed, 72 pain twise, 77 Limit cone, 81, 94 Locally bounded, 209, 210 Locally finitely presentable, Locally fully faithful, 223 Locally presentable, 211 Locally small, 23
211
~~subobject,
208 52 M-wellpowered, 209 Model, 198 for a regulus, 218 for a sketch, 218 generic, 202 Monad, idempotent, 53 Monoidal category, 21 biclosed, 34 cartesian, 21 strict, 22 symmetric, 30 Monoidal closed category, Morita equivalence, 176 M~tes,
Opposite V-category, Orthogonal, 215
33
30
Partial adjoint, SO Partial functor, 31 Pointwise limit or colimit, 77 Pointwise Kan extension, 123 Power, 92 Presentation of density, 172 Preservation, of a limit, 75 of a right-Kan extension, 114 Profunctor, 176 Projective cone, 81 Proper factorization system, 208 Realization, 221 Reflect limits, 85 Reflective full subcategory, 53 Regular generator, 152 Regulus, 218 Replete full subcategory, 53
Index
244 Replete image, 53 Repletion, 53 Representable V-functor, Representation, 47 Right adequate, 158 Right adjoint, 49 Right exact, 132 Right Kan extension, 113
36' 4 7
Sketch, 218 of an F-theory, 2Z 7 small, 224 Small limit, 74 Cl-small, 136 Small-projective, 174 Small sketch, 224 Small V-ca tegory, 24, 55 Solution-set condition, 148 Special adjoint functor theorem, 150 Split coequalizer diagram, 151 Split idempotent, 186 Strict monoidal category, 22 Strong cogenerator, strongly cogenerating, Strong generator, strongly generating, 58 Subobject, 149 M-subobject, 208 Surjective, essentially, (on objects), 51 Symmetric monoidal category, 30 Symmetric monoidal closed category, 35 Symmetry, 28 Tensor product, 23, 92 of F-theories, 229 of V-categories, 30 Tensored, 92 Theory, essentially algebraic, 198, 202 F-theory, 220 finitary, 220 Transformation, V-natural, 25 Triangular equations, 49 Underlying category, 26 Underlying functor, 27 Union, of M-subo~jects, 208 Unit, of a colimit, 73 of a left Kan extension, I IS of an adjunction, 49 of a representation, 47 Unitobject, 23 Unit V-category, 26 Universal V-natural family, 54
88
Index
245
V-ca tegory,
23 cocomplete, 74 complete, 74 dual, 30 free, 68 opposite, 30 small, 24, 55 unit,
2b
V-functor, 24 accessible, 144 cocontinuous, 75 conservative, 87 continuous, 75 dense, 158 representable, 36, 47 strongly generating, 88 V-natural family, extraordinary, universal, 54 V-natural transformation, 25 Weak Kan extension, 122 Weakly accessible, 147 Weakly cowellpowered, 91 Wellpowered: M-wellpowered, Yoneda embedding, 67 Yoneda lemma, weak, 45 strong, 65 Yoneda isomorphism, 65, 74
209
40