190 76 11MB
English Pages [220] Year 1978
STOILE
EVEFSkw DiFHClJIT
THOUOfT JW\DEE4SY Mortimer Adier I.
OTHER BOOKS
BY THE
AUTHOR
Dialectic
What Man Has Made
How
How
to
to
Read a Book
Think About
War and
Peace
O. Kelso)
(with Louis
The
of Man
Capitalist Manifesto
The Idea of Freedom The Conditions of Philosophy The Difference of Man and
the Difference It
The Time of Our Lives
The
Common
Sense of Politics
(with William Gorman) The American Testament
Some Questions About Language Philosopher at Large
Reforming Education (with Charles
Van Doren)
Creat Treasury of Western Thought
Makes
7IRIST0TLE
FOR EVERYBODY DIFFICULT
THOUGHT
MADE EASY BY
Mortimer J. Adler Macmillan Publishing Co.,
Inc.
NEW YORK Collier
Macmillan Publishers
LONDON
Copyright All nghts merved.
© 1978 by Mortimer
No
part of thu book
/
may
Adler be reproduced or
transmitted in any form or by any mearu, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage retrieval system, without permission in writing
Macmillan Publishing Co. 866 ThinI Avenue.
New
York.
,
from the Publisher.
Inc.
NY
Canada.
Collier hAacmillan
and
10022
Ltd.
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Adler, Mortimer }erome. 1902Aristotle for everybody.
Includes bibliographical references.
I.
Aristoteles
B481 A3
185
I
Title.
78-853
ISBN 0-02-503100-7
Printed in the United States of AmerKa
I
CONTENTS
PREFACE Vll INTRODUCTION :
Part
Man
I
2. 3.
4.
The Great Divide
11
Man
Aristotle's
the
7.
10
:
The Four Causes
Productive Ideas and
to
16
:
Maker
Crusoe
To Be and Not
Animal
3
:
:
23
Change and Permanence 6.
8.
Games
Man's Three Dimensions
Part
5.
the Philosophical
Philosophical
1.
ix
:
:
Be
:
30
39 :
49
Know-How
:
57
VI
;
Contents
Man
Part HI
Living and Living Well
10.
Good,
11. 12.
What
How
Good
13.
Better, Best
Habits and
What
We
Have
What Goes
into the 17.
Man
IV
Part
Part
69
:
76
83
to Pursue Happiness
92
:
Good Luck
100
:
109
:
a Right to Expect
from Others and from the
18.
:
:
Others Have a Right to Expect from Us
15.
16.
Doer
Thinking about Ends and Means
9.
14.
the
State
118
:
Knower
the
Mind and What Comes Words
Logic's Little
out of
It
Telling the Truth and Thinking
It
Reasonable Doubt
Beyond
V
Difficult Philosophical Questions
22.
The
20.
Infinity
21.
Eternity
God
:
:
160
171
:
:
175
Immateriality of 23.
129
151
:
19.
a
:
139
:
Mind
:
179
185
EPILOGUE For Those
Who
Have Read totle
:
or
191
Who
Wish
to
Read
Aris-
^
PREFACE
When
the idea for this book
entithng those
it
titles
whom
The Children's
occurred to me,
I
thought of
But
Aristotle or Aristotle for Children.
would not have accurately conveyed the audience
this simple,
easy-to-read exposition of Aristotle's
mon-sense philosophy everybody
first
is
intended.
The
audience,
I
for
com-
felt,
was
—
of any age, from twelve or fourteen years old up-
Hence the title chosen, and the subtitle "Difficult Thought Made Easy," together with the statement that this book is an introduction to common sense.
ward.
When
I
say "everybody,"
I
mean everybody
except profes-
sional philosophers; in other words, everybody of ordinary expe-
rience and intelligence unspoiled by the sophistication cialization of
academic thought. Nevertheless,
have added an
who come upon
this
find useful as a guide to the reading of Aristotle's
own
Epilogue which students of philosophy
book may
I
and spe-
works on the subjects covered in
this
book.
i
via
Preface
:
My
two sons, Douglas and Philip
spectively), read portions of the
typewriter last
summer
in
Aspen.
I
and eleven,
(thirteen
manuscript
am
as
re-
came from my to them for their
it
grateful
enthusiasm and their suggestions. I
wish also to express
my
gratitude to
Rosemary Barnes, who
read and criticized the whole manuscript at that time, as well as to
my
colleagues at the Institute for Philosophical Research
gave
me
Bird,
and Charles Van Doren. At
the benefit of their advice
manuscript went into type, of
it
and made suggestions
my for
—
a later date, just before the
wife, Caroline, read the
its
who
John Van Doren, Otto
improvement,
for
whole
which
I
am
grateful.
As always, Marlys Allen,
I
am much
for
her
in
debt to
tireless efforts at
my
editorial
secretary,
every stage in the produc-
tion of this book.
Mortimer Chicago, December 28, 1977
/.
Adler
INTRODUCTION
Why Why
Aristotle? for
everybody?
And why troduction to
is
an exposition of Aristotle
common
evenbody an
for
can answer these three questions better
I
swered one other.
how
Why
in-
sense?
philosophy?
to think philosophically
— how
Why
after
have an-
I
should everyone learn
to ask the kind of searching
questions that children and philosophers ask and that philoso-
phers sometimes answer? I
have long been of the opinion that philosophy
business
—but not
in order to get
is
everybody's
more information about the it would be
world, our societ\% and ourselves. For that purpose, better to turn to the natural tory.
It is
in another
to understand things
way
we
and the
social sciences
that philosophy
is
useful
already know, understand
now understand them. That is why should learn how to think philosophically.
than we
I
and
to his-
—
to help us
them
better
think everyone
X
:
Introduction
For that purpose, there
do not hesitate
The only
to
is
other teacher that
my judgment
he
no
better teacher than Aristotle.
recommend him is
second
I
as the teacher to
might have chosen
best. Plato raised
in addition, gave us clearer answers to totle
how
to think philosophically,
son so well that he
we
Since
is
who he was
what
or
thought
when and how he
his life
and the I
how
to think the
way
more important than
is
lived appear strange to us;
do not make either the
will try to explain, they
les-
of us.
all
The centuries and the may make the conditions of
which he
society in
them too and,
lived.
changes that separate him from us
but, as
the ques-
but Aristotle learned the
the better teacher for
Aristotle
all
them. Plato taught Aris-
are concerned with learning
Aristotle did,
Plato, but in
is
almost
tions that everyone should face; Aristotle raised
I
begin with.
style or
the content of his thinking strange to us.
was born in 384 B.C. in the Macedonian town of Stagira on the north coast of the Aegean Sea. His father was a Aristotle
physician in the court of the King of Macedonia.
grandson became Alexander the Great,
became both
tutor
and
to
whom
The
King's
Aristotle later
friend.
At the age of eighteen, Aristotle took up residence in Athens
and enrolled
in Plato's
Academy
was not long before Plato found
who
as a student of philosophy.
Aristotle a
It
troublesome student
questioned what he taught and openly disagreed with him.
When
Plato died,
Aristotle
opened
and Alexander became the
own
his
school, the
ruler of Greece,
Lyceum. That was
in
335
B.C.
The Lyceum had maps, and a zoo
mal
life.
It
in
a fine library,
which
an extensive collection of
Aristotle collected
has been said that
specimens of ani-
some of these were
Alexander from the countries he conquered.
sent to
When
him by
Alexander
died in 323 B.C., Aristotle exiled himself from Athens to one
Introduction
of the Aegean islands.
He
Aristotle lived in a society in
in
which
women
and
to
which the
citizens
had
free
because they had slaves
do menial work.
It
was
time
to take
also a society
occupied an inferior position. Plato, in pro-
jecting the institutions of cal offices,
an ideal
state,
proposed that
all politi-
except that of military leader, should be open to
women, because he
regarded
men and women
essentially
as
equal; but Aristotle accepted the
more conventional view of
day concerning the
women.
I
shall
inferiority of
have more
to say in a later chapter
views with regard to slavery and to
once that
my
and not
just for the
no way an indication
On
that
about
women. Here
use of the words *'man,"
in their generic sense to stand for ders,
xi
died there a year later at the age of 63.
to enjoy the pursuits of leisure
care of their estates
:
I
Aristotle's
want
to say at
"men," and "mankind"
human
beings of both gen-
male portion of the population, I
his
share Aristotle's view about
the contrary, with regard to this point,
am
I
There may be some persons who regard
is
in
women.
a Platonist.
Aristotle's antiquity
They may feel that it would be much better to select as a teacher someone alive today someone acquainted with the world in which we live, someone who knows what modern science has discovered about that world. I do not agree as a disadvantage.
—
with them.
Though
was
Aristotle
a
Greek who
lived twenty-five centuries
ago, he was sufficiently acquainted with the
the world in which today. totle
As an aid
to
would not be
we
live to talk
about
main
as if
it
outlines of
he were
alive
our being able to think philosophically, Arisa better teacher
even
if
he were acquainted
with everything that modern scientists know. In an effort to understand nature, society,
began where everyone should begin
knew
in the light of his ordinary,
and man,
—with
Aristotle
what he already
commonplace
experience.
xii
Introduction
:
Beginning there, his thinking used notions that not because
we were taught them
common
are the
human
stock of
all
of us possess,
but because they
in school,
thought about anything and
everything.
We
sometimes
refer to these notions as
our
common
about things. They are notions that we have formed of the lives
common
we have
experience
we
part, experiences
as a result
in the course of
—experiences we have without any
sense
our daily
effort of inquiry
on our
have simply because we are awake and
all
common notions are common words we employ
we
conscious. In addition, these
notions
are able to express in the
in everyday
speech.
Forgive I
me
because what erything
is
word ''common"
for repeating the
cannot avoid doing
so,
means
it
and
are
but there are other things that ours.
We
them with
share
friends have read or a
or a house that live in
The
it
the
all
my
many on
times.
that
word
argument. Not ev-
many things we call our own, we recognize as not exclusively
others,
such
as a
book
that our
motion picture some of us have enjoyed,
members
of the family share
when
they
together.
things
we
share are
common. There
that different groups of people share.
we
all
all
human.
share and are It
common
are
many
that
notions, or
common
I
refer to
common
sense, as
Our common-sense
things
There are fewer things
that
simply because we are
to all of us,
in this last, all-embracing sense of the
is
"common"
''thing,"
so
to lay stress
the heart of
lies at
common. There
have
I
experiences and
word
common
common.
notions are expressed by such words as
"body," "mind," "change," "cause," "part," "whole,"
"one," "many," and so on. Most of us have been using these
words and notions
for a long
We
them
started to use
time
—
since
in order to talk
we were
quite young.
about experiences that
Introduction
of US have had
all
of things
moving or remaining
xiii
at rest,
of
of animals being born and dying, of sitting
plants growing,
down and
—
:
getting up, of aches
and
pains, of going to sleep,
dreaming, and waking up, of feeding and exercising our bodies,
and of making up our minds. I
could enlarge
this
could enlarge the
common
notions
could be made,
and notions
I
of the
list
we
it
common experiences, common words we use
of our
list
I
and the
have. But even without the additions that
should be clear that the words, experiences,
have mentioned are
yours, or mine, or
just as
anyone
all
common
—not
exclusively
else's.
In contrast, the things that scientists observe in their laboratories or that explorers observe
special experiences.
We
on
their expeditions are very
them from their we do not experience them ourselves.
ports, but, as a rule,
Human
may
learn about
re-
beings have learned a great deal since Aristotle's day,
mainly through the discoveries of modern science. Applied science has created a world and a his
world and his way of
life.
way of
He
life
very different from
did not have an automobile,
could not talk on the telephone, never saw what can be seen
through a microscope or a telescope, did not have a close view of the surface of the surface by
mon
men
moon, and never heard
a description of
its
Aristotle had the same comwe have in ours. The kind of about them enabled him to understand them
walking on
it.
But
experiences in his day that
thinking he did better than
That and stand these
most of us do. that alone
common
is
the reason he can help us to under-
experiences better and help us to under-
stand ourselves and our lives, as well as the world and the society in
which we
and our
live,
even though our way of
society are different
Aristotle's thinking
from
began with
life,
our world,
his.
common
sense, but
it
did not
XIV
:
end
Introduction
there.
common common
It
went much
further.
That try to
is
added
to
and surrounded
sense with insights and understandings that are not at all.
His understanding of things goes deeper than
ours and sometimes soars higher.
common
It
It
is,
in a word,
uncommon
sense. his great contribution to all of us.
do in
this
book
is
easier to understand. If
even become
less
it
What I am
going to
make his uncommon common sense becomes easier to understand, it might
to
uncommon.
t
PAR J
J
MAN THE PHILOSOPHICAL
ANIMAL
I
Philosophical
Many
Games
of us have played two games without reahzing
on the way
to
becoming philosophical. One
is
we were
called ''Animal,
Vegetable, Mineral"; the other, 'Twenty Questions."
Both games consist
in asking questions.
what makes them philosophical games; questions
—
a set of categories, a
sifying things, placing
process.
when
them
Everyone does
it
scheme of
lies
at
is
on
they
not
behind the
—
is
a familiar
shopkeepers
their shelves, librarians
when
is
classification. Clas-
one time or another
they catalogue books, secretaries
when
what
it is
in this or that category,
they take stock of what
ments. But
However, that
file letters
when
or docu-
the objects to be classified are the contents of
the physical world, or the even-larger universe that includes the physical world, then philosophy enters the picture.
The two games Questions"
—
are
—"Animal, Vegetable, Mineral" and "Twenty sometimes played
game. That occurs when the
^q
first
as
if
they were the
same
of the twenty questions to be
4
Aristotle for
:
asked
is
Everybody
"Animal, vegetable, or mineral?"
in order to find
out
whether the object being thought of falls into one of these three But only some of
large categories, or classes, of physical things.
the objects
we can
think about are physical things.
ample, the object decided on was a geometrical circle, or a it
number, such
happened
as the square root of
to be one of the Greek gods, such
If,
for ex-
such
figure,
as a
minus one, or as
if
Zeus, Apollo,
or Athena, asking whether the object in question was animal, vegetable, or mineral
—
would not
—
should not
or, at least,
get
an answer.
The game
of twenty questions,
when
''Animal, vegetable, or mineral?"
is
not begun by asking
it is
concerned with discovering
any object that can be thought about by anybody. ited to objects that are physical things.
the
more
likely to
Of
It is
not lim-
the two games,
it
is
engage us in philosophical thought without
our being aware of
To become aware
it.
of
it,
we need
Aris-
totle's help.
Classifying was one of the
Another was
skills in
which
Aristotle excelled.
his skill in asking questions. Philosophical
began with the asking of questions
—questions
that
thought
can be an-
swered on the basis of our ordinary, everyday experience and with some reflection about that experience that results in a
sharpening and refinement of our
Animal, vegetable, and mineral fold division of things
we
fall
is
when we
on one
gold or silver that
a rough-and-ready, three-
use
it
to stand for all the
— rosebushes
mice from
or
inanimate things are not minerals, such
we
dig from deposits in the earth.
rock formations found on the earth's surface or in
some
But we use
side of the line that divides liv-
ing organisms from inanimate things sticks or stones. All
sense.
find in the physical world.
the word "mineral" loosely physical things that
common
Some
its
as
are
interior;
are other forms of matter in liquid or gaseous state.
Man In
the Philosophical
loosely covered by the term "mineral," Aristotle
between elementary and
mentary body, according
—
single kind of matter contrast, a
more
gold, for
composite body
is
one
is
one that
What
ele-
that consists in a
composed of two
is
of copper and zinc. But, for Aristotle, the is
An
example, or copper or zinc. In
different kinds of matter, such as brass, which
tinction
is
would have us
composite bodies.
to Aristotle,
5
:
inanimate bodies that
the category of nonliving or
distinguish
Animal
a
is
or
mixture
more important
dis-
the one that divides living from nonliving things.
differentiates
all
organisms from inert bodies,
living
whether they are elementary or composite bodies? From our dinary experience of living organisms,
have certain
common
characteristics.
or-
we know that they all They take nourishment;
they grow; they reproduce.
Among
living organisms,
what
mals? Again, from our ordinary experience,
mals have certain
common
from ani-
differentiates plants
we know
that ani-
characteristics that plants lack.
They
are not rooted in the earth like plants; they have the ability to
move from place to place by their own means of locomotion. They do not draw their nourishment from the air and from the soil as plants do.
The
line
that
In addition,
divides
most animals have sense organs.
inert
bodies from
sometimes leaves us wondering on which ticular thing belongs.
This
is
living
organisms
side of the line a par-
also true of the line that divides
plants from animals. For example,
some
plants appear to have
sensitivity
even though they do not have sense organs
and
Some
ears.
like eyes
animals, such as shellfish, seem to lack the
power of locomotion;
like plants
they appear to be rooted in one
spot.
In classifying physical things as inanimate bodies, plants,
animals, Aristotle was aware that his division of
all
and
physical
6
Aristotle for
:
Everybody
things into these three large classes did not exclude borderline cases
—
things that in a certain respect appear to belong
side of the dividing line
belong on the other
and
He
side.
on one
another respect, appear
that, in
bodies, the transition from things lifeless to living things
from plant or-none
life is
Nevertheless,
gradual and not a clear-cut,
persisted
Aristotle
between
and animals separated them
we
in
did not, in the
thinking that the
first
was
as follows.
and understand the
place, recognize
and
mouse, we would
a
never find ourselves puzzled by whether something
was a
dif-
into quite different kinds of
clear-cut distinction between a stone
classify
all-
and nonliving bodies and between
living
things. His reason for holding this view If
and
affair.
ferences plants
animal
life to
to
recognized that in the world of
living or a nonliving thing.
difficult to
Similarly,
if
we
did
not recognize the clear-cut distinction between a rosebush and a horse,
we would never wonder whether
living
organism was a plant or an animal.
a given
Just as animals are a special kind of living
specimen of
organism because
they perform functions that plants do not, so for a similar reason are
human
beings a special kind of animal.
tain functions that
no other animals perform, such
general questions and seeking answers to
and by thought. That
—
is
why
engage
in philosophical thought.
questioning
There may be animals
zees,
it
engage
as asking
human
beings
and thinking animals,
animals
cer-
them by observation
Aristotle called
tional
that divides
They perform
able
ra-
to
that appear to straddle the borderline
humans from nonhumans.
Porpoises and chimpan-
has recently been learned, have enough intelligence to in
rudimentary forms of communication. But they do
not appear to ask themselves or one another questions about the nature of things, and they do not appear to
try,
by one means or
Man
the Philosophical
Animal
:
7
We may speak human, but we do not include them
another, to discover the answers for themselves. of such animals as almost as
members of Each
the
human
race.
distinct kind of thing, Aristotle thought, has a nature
that distinguishes class of things
it
from
all
What
the others.
from everything
differentiates
else defines the nature possessed
by every individual thing that belongs to that
human nature, human beings have
speak of all
characteristics
for
Aristotle's
differentiate
scheme of
is
and that these
them from other animals, from things.
arranged the
He
an ascending order.
mentary and composite bodies
istics
When we
example, we are simply saying that
classification
classes of physical things in
of the higher classes
class.
certain characteristics
and from inanimate
plants,
one
main
five
placed ele-
Each
the bottom of the scale.
at
higher because
it
possesses the character-
of the class below and, in addition, has certain distin-
guishing characteristics that the class below does not have. In the scale of natural things, the animate
is
a higher
form of
existence than the inanimate; animals are a higher form of
than plants; and
human
life is
All living organisms, like
and have weight, but
the highest form of
all
life
on
life
earth.
inanimate bodies, occupy space
in addition, as
we have
noted, they eat,
grow, and reproduce. Because they are living organisms, animals, like plants, perform these vital functions, but they also
perform certain functions that plants do not. At the top of the scale are
human
beings
who perform
formed by other animals and who, to seek
all
the vital functions per-
in addition,
have the
ability
knowledge by asking and answering questions and the
ability to think philosophically.
Of think,
course,
it
can be said that
many
of the higher animals
and even that computers think. Nor
is
it
true that only
8
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
humans have
intelligence. Intelligence in varying degrees
be found throughout the animal world, in varying degrees
in
members
just as
it
human
of the
special kind of thinking that gives rise to asking
philosophical questions distinguishes mals.
No
is
to
to
be found
race.
But the
is
and answering
humans from
other ani-
other animal plays philosophical games.
In the world of physical things that Aristotle divides into five large classes, the class.
There
subclass.
word "body" names the one, all-embracing
no more inclusive
is
Every thing
which bodies
class of
in the physical
world
is
a
are a
body of one kind
or another.
Can we go
to the opposite
bodies at which
we must
extreme and find a subclass of
stop because
any further into smaller subclasses?
we
are unable to divide
the
Is
human
it
species such
a subclass of animals?
Faced with that question, most of us probably think of different races or varieties of mankind color, by facial characteristics, by
do not such characteristics divide
—
head shape, and
human
at
once
differentiated by skin so on.
Why
beings into different
kinds or subclasses? In this connection, Aristotle
Not
all
made an important
distinction.
the characteristics of a thing, he said, define
or essence.
As we have already seen,
should be defined as a
Being able
rational
to ask questions
wherefore of things
is
—
or
its
nature
Aristotle thought
philosophical
man
—animal.
about the what, the why, and the
what makes anyone
a
human
being, not
the skin color, the snub nose, the straight hair, or the shape of the head.
We
can, of course, divide
ety of subclasses
—
tall
human
or short,
fat
beings into an endless varior thin,
white or black,
strong or weak, and so on. But although such differences
may
Man
the Philosophical
be used to distinguish one subgroup of
human
Animal
:
g
beings from
another, they cannot be used, according to Aristotle, to exclude
any of these subgroups from the
more important,
it
In
other words,
race.
What
is
even
cannot be said that the members of one
subgroup are more or
human
human
less
the
human
than the members of another.
differences
between one subclass of
beings and another are superficial or minor, as
pared with the basic or major differences that separate
com-
human
beings from other animals. Aristotle called the superficial or
minor differences accidental; the basic or major differences he regarded as essential.
Human human
beings and brute animals are essentially different;
beings and short ones,
are accidentally different.
being
differs
from another.
It is
fat
human
only in this way that one
We are all
tall
beings and thin- ones,
human
animals of the same kind,
may have more and another individual less human characteristic. Such individual differences are much less important than the one thing that unites all men and women their common humanity, which is the one respect in which all human beings are equal.
but one individual of this or that
—
The Great Divide
Aristotle's division of physical things into
living
and
organisms,
his
division
inanimate bodies and
of living organisms
and human beings, do not exhaust
plants, animals,
his
into
scheme
of classification or his set of categories.
Think,
example, of Wellington's horse
for
at the Battle
of
Waterloo or of Julius Caesar crossing the Rubicon. Think of Shakespeare's Hamlet, the Gabriel.
ripe tomato,
None
Loch Ness monster,
Think of the odor of
roses in full
isted in the past,
is
a physical thing that exists
but they
exist
Ness monster
is
now
as
animal,
and Julius Caesar
ex-
no longer. Shakespeare's Hamlet
a fictitious person, not a real one.
full
a
Newton's theory of gravitation, or God.
of these
vegetable, or mineral. Wellington's horse
is
or the angel
bloom, the color of
The
existence of the
Loch
highly questionable. As for the odor of roses in
bloom, the angel Gabriel, Newton's theory of
and God, none of these
fall
gravitation,
under any of the headings that
Man
the Philosophical
Animal
:
ii
cover bodies that either exist or have existed in the physical world.
The
universe of objects that can be thought of
than the physical world
—the world of
have existed in the
the world of bodies, but
also includes
it
from everything
we can
It
now
includes
else besides.
else
the great divide.
What is left when we put the whole What belongs to the other half of
verse of objects that
past.
much is
The
physical world to one
the all-embracing uni-
side?
give
larger
bodies, either those
in existence or those that
line that divides bodies
much
is
think about?
I
am
not going to
try to
an exhaustive enumeration of the kinds of objects that are
not bodies, but here
—mathematical — imaginary or or
some of the
at least are
objects,
such
and square
as triangles
fictitious characters,
possible kinds:
such
roots
as Shakespeare's
Hamlet
Mark Twain's Huckleberry Finn
—disembodied
or
unembodied
spirits
of
all sorts,
including ghosts
and angels
—gods
God when
or
divine beings are thought of as not having
bodies
— mythological —minds
and mermaids
beings, such as centaurs
that are able to think
up the kind of questions we have
been asking
— I
ideas or theories that
am
thought
fully
aware that
raises
many
sense of that word?
minds think with
this
enumeration of possible objects of
questions. If
bilities?
bodies?
If
such objects
exist,
in
any
how does their existence differ What does it mean to call them
they do,
from the existence of bodies? possibilities?
Do
Are there any objects of thought that are impossi-
minds
are not bodies,
what
is
their relationship to
12
Aristotle for
Everybody
will try to
answer some of these questions
:
I
help
—
—with
sophical questions that the
Some
in later chapters of this book.
moment,
asking
will
I
them
to the larger universe of
Aristotle's
are difficult philo-
postpone until the very end. For
serves the purpose of calling attention
which the physical world
even though the world of bodies
may
is
but a part,
be the only one that really
exists.
we must
Staying with that world,
made by
Aristotle.
odor of roses in
and tomatoes
We
full
On
it
handle the question about the
to
or the color of a ripe tomato. Roses
Considering the physical world, Aristotle
a line that divides
its
constituents into two major kinds.
In our everyday speech,
We
do not speak of the
were a body. weight, for to feel
We
we
I
know
its
that
make
the
and weight of
size
hand me the
to
you must hand
me
same
distinc-
a stone as
if it
stone's size or
the stone in order for
size or weight.
can think of the stone's
the stone,
ordinarily
would not ask you
I
side,
such as their odors or colors.
their characteristics or attributes,
me
on the other
the one side of the line, he placed bodies;
tion.
and
are bodies, they are plants, but their odor
their color are not.
drew
need
bloom
consider another distinction
but
size or
we cannot change
without changing the stone.
If
weight without thinking of the stone's size or weight
the stone
is
lying in a pile of
we can take it from the pile and leave the other stones behind, but we cannot take the stone's size or weight away from stones,
it
and leave the stone behind.
What
belongs to a body in the way in which the stone's size
or weight belongs to
has
its
it is,
according to Aristotle, something that
existence in a thing (as the stone's weight exists in the
stone), but does not exist in
A
physical thing, a body,
from which
it
and of
may
can be removed
—
itself (as
the stone
exists).
belong to a collection of things as
one stone can be taken from
Man a pile of stones.
of
But each of the stones
e\en when
itself,
and of themselves. They are always the
physical things,
and they cease
they exist cease to
A A
and
is
sizes
when
:
13
and not exist
and weights of
the bodies in which
exist.
Another way of grasping cal things
to exist
That
and weights do not
true of the stone's size or weight. Sizes in
in the pile exists in
exists in a collection of stones.
it
Animal
the Philosophical
this basic distinction
between physi-
how
things change.
their attributes
is
to consider
made smooth. made perfectly attributes, we are deal-
stone w ith a rough surface can be polished and stone that
round. While
is
almost round in shape can be
we
same stone If
it
changing
are
ing with one and the
same
It is
not another stone, but the
altered.
same stone while becoming
did not remain the
in this or that respect,
being rough
to
it
could not be said
understand
this,
is
it
(this
have changed from
we understand
reason for saying that a physical thing
what
to
different
being smooth or from being larger to being
When we
smaller.
a stone's
stone.
that
is
individual stone) while at the
Aristotle's
which remains
same time being
subject to change in one respect or another (in size or weight,
shape, color, or texture).
The
attributes of bodies, unlike bodies themselves, are never
subject to change.
Roughness never becomes smoothness; green
never becomes red.
the green tomato that things,
in
short,
the rough stone that
It is
are
changeable; they are
becomes red when changeable. the
it
becomes smooth; ripens.
Physical
Physical attributes are not
respects
in
which physical things
change.
Aristotle attempted to
make
a
complete enumeration of the
attributes that physical things have.
questioned, but the attributes he
Its
completeness
names
are ones
we
may
be
are
all
Everybody
Aristotle for
14
common
acquainted with in
— — — A it
when
in quantity,
when
in quality,
experience, especially those that
which things change:
are the principal respects in
they increase or decrease in weight or size
they alter in shape, color, or texture
in place or position,
when
move from
they
here to there
thing has other attributes, such as the relationships in which stands to other things, the actions
being acted on, the time of tion of
its
Of all
existence,
its
it
performs, the results of
coming
and the time of
its
into existence, the dura-
ceasing to
its
exist.
the attributes that a physical thing has, the most impor-
tant are those that
spect to
which
manent
attributes
it
it
has throughout
its
existence and with re-
does not change as long as
make
the kind of thing
it
it
exists.
These per-
For example,
it is.
it
a permanent attribute of salt that it dissolves in water; a permanent attribute of certain metals that they are conductors of is
electricity;
a
permanent
birth to living offspring
Such thing
it
attribute of
and suckle
attributes not only is,
make
mammals
a thing the special kind of
they also differentiate one kind of thing from an-
other. Being able to ask questions of the sort
ing
a
is
tiates us
We call
permanent
beings persons.
sharks or birds persons. a
person,
we
to this point, the
We
When we
treat
human. Objects that we in the same manner.
Up
ask-
are, of course,
are physical things, but not only physical things.
recognize this fact in our use of the word "person."
human
were
we have been
attribute of rational animals that differen-
from other mammals. Rational animals
They
bodies.
that they give
their young.
it
as
do not treat
if
regard as
it
call
spiders,
our pet cat or dog
were
mere
human
things,
We
snakes, as if
it
—
or almost
we do
word "thing" has been used
not treat
to refer to
Man physical things
—
to
bodies.
Now
the Philosophical
Its
meaning
is
It is
sometimes so broad that
object of thought
—not only
to their attributes as well,
it
a
15
troublesome word.
refers to
any possible
to existent physical things,
and
:
word "thing" has been
the
used in contrast to the word "person."
Animal
to objects that
do not
but also
exist,
ob-
may
never have existed, and even objects that cannot
possibly exist.
Sometimes the word "thing" narrowly applies
jects that
now
only to bodies that
have existed there
exist in the physical world, bodies that
in the past, or bodies that
can
exist there in
the future.
Using the same word in a variety of senses able. In the case of the
words we use ble not to
do
word. also
most important words we
in ordinary everyday speech, so. Aristotle
ferent senses in
When we
often unavoid-
is
it
is
use, especially
almost impossi-
frequently called attention to the dif-
which he found
it
necessary to use the same
Human and not
we must we use.
think about our experience as he did,
pay attention to the different senses of the words
beings are physical things in one sense of that word
in another
when we
call
them
persons, not things. As
physical things, as bodies, they have the three dimensions with
which we
are
all
acquainted. As persons, they also have three
dimensions, which are quite different.
Mans Three Dimensions
Regarding ourselves simply things
—
would
I
as
bodies
—
merely
or
as
physical
say that our three dimensions, like the three
dimensions of any other body, are length, breadth, and height.
That
is
the way in which any body occupies space.
While,
we
as bodies,
we have
are, as
kind of thing
mensions
—
we
are physical things like
just seen,
that
is
my hand
down. Like
also directions
human
What
called a person.
In space, a dimension
to
—the only
are our three di-
as persons, not just as bodies?
can move
up
other bodies,
all
the special kind of thing
being.
— I
spatial
which our
is
a direction in
left to right,
which
from front
which
am
we have only
sure that I
as active activities
I
can move.
to back,
I
from
dimensions, personal dimensions are
directions in
physical bodies, but
dimensions
from
cannot be
human
can take
as a person,
— only
can act as a
three dimensions as
as sure that
beings us.
I,
we have only
three
three directions in
Man However,
I
think that the three dimensions
There may be
portant as these. In the
the
first
The
doubt
I
rep-
activity
can
there are any as im-
if
three are making, doing, and knowing.
we have man
of these three dimensions, making,
or artisan
artist
ships,
others, but
ly
:
name
shall
I
human
resent three very important directions that take.
Animal
the Philosophical
—the producer of
all sorts
of things: shoes,
and houses, books, music, and paintings.
It
not just
is
when human beings produce statues or paintings that we should call them artists. That is much too restricted a use of the word art.
a
Anything in the world that
work of
artificial rather
is
In the second of these dimensions, doing,
—
moral and social being
achieves happiness or
fails to
achieve
human
acquiring knowledge of
sorts
all
human
it,
someone who
the
wrong,
finds
it
beings in order to do
we have man
— not
beings are a part, not
nature, but also about knowledge
three of these dimensions,
kind of thinking he does in order to
as learner,
only about nature, not
human
only about the society of which only about
right or
being, he or she feels impelled to do.
In the third dimension, knowing,
all
is
or does not do, either
human
necessary to associate with other
what, as a
we have man
someone who can do
someone who, by what he or she does
In
than natural
—something man-made.
art
man make
is
itself.
a thinker, but the
things differs from the
kind of thinking he does in order to act morally and socially.
Both kinds of thinking being does in order
differ
just to
from the kind of thinking
—
know
to
know
a
human
just for the sake
of
knowing.
Aristotle
was very
much concerned
with the differences that
distinguish these three kinds of thinking.
He
used the term
''productive thinking" to describe the kind of thinking that
man
engages in as a maker; "practical thinking" to describe the kind
i8
:
Aristotle for
Everybody
and "speculative" or "theoretical
that he engages in as a doer;
thinking" to describe the kind he engages in as a knower.
This threefold division of the kinds of thinking can be found
Some
in Aristotle's books.
and
of them, such as his books on moral
concerned with practical thinking
political philosophy, are
and with man and trying
to
doer
as a
make
it
as
—
an individual living
as
good
as possible,
of society, associated with other
with them.
Some
human
and
his
also as a
own life member
beings and cooperating
of these books, such as the ones on natural
philosophy, are concerned with theoretical thinking about the
man
whole physical world, including
and man's mind and knowledge
He
wrote a treatise about
man
only with
man
entitled
Poetics because the
it
maker of
as a
the word "poetry"
as a part of that world,
as well. as a
maker, but that book deals
and paintings. He
poetry, music,
Greek word from which we
— making
means making
get
anything, not just
the kind of objects that entertain us and that give us pleasure
when we
enjoy them.
Men
women
and
produce an extraordi-
we use in our daily lives, such as the clothes we wear, the houses we live in, the furniture in those houses, and the implements needed to make such nary variety of useful things, things
things.
The more
man
as a
general treatment of
maker of
man
as a
useful physical things,
that Aristotle wrote about nature
—
phy. In his effort to understand the totle frequently resorted to
his
maker, particularly
we
find in the books
books of natural philoso-
phenomena
of nature, Aris-
comparisons between the way
men
produce things and the way nature works. His understanding of
what
is
help us
involved in
—
That
making
is
to
helped him
— and
it
will
understand the workings of nature.
why
as a
human making
I
am
going to begin, in Part
dimension of
human
II
of this book, with
activity. After that, in Part
III,
Man I
am
going to deal with the dimension of
which man I
will
come
is
to
a
the
man
as a
knower, postponing
we have
human mind and knowledge
The most words that
And
moral and social being.
difficult questions that
Animal
the Philosophical
human
activity in
—
questions about
itself.
name
the universal values that
elicit
respect
—
and
or the
good, and the beautiful. These three values pertain to
human
In the sphere of making,
we
activity.
are
concerned with beauty
say the least, with trying to produce things that are well
In the sphere of doing, as individuals
we
most
to the last the
to consider
challenging words in anyone's vocabulary are three
the three dimensions of
ety,
19
finally, in Part IV,
evoke wonder. They are truth, goodness, and beauty true, the
:
are
concerned with good and
the sphere of knowing,
we
are
and
as
members
evil, right
concerned with
or, to
made.
of soci-
and wrong. In
truth.
PJJIT
JJ
MAN THE MAKER
s
Aristotle's
If Aristotle
had written the
of the tale
would have been
The
story
storv'
Crusoe
of Robinson Crusoe, the moral
different.
most of us have read celebrates Crusoe's ingenuity
in solving the
problem of how
on the
island
where he found himself
wreck.
It
sight.
also celebrates his virtues
It is
a story of
control over
For
—
and comfortably
a castaway after a ship-
his
courage and his fore-
man's conquest of nature,
his
mastery and
it.
Aristotle, the island
ture with a capital
of nature
to live securely
would have represented Nature, na-
N, nature untouched by humans. The works
—the seeding of
trees
and bushes, the growth of plants,
the birth and death of animals, the shifting of sands, the wear-
ing away of rocks, the formation of caves
long before Crusoe's
arrival.
Aristotle
changes that Crusoe brought about
— had been going on
would have viewed the
as a
way of understanding
the changes that had taken place without him.
For him, the
24
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
would not have been
story
account of
man
When we
a stor>' of
man
against nature, but an
working with nature. understand something that
try to
derstand, a good
common-sense
rule
the difficulties. light
What
on what
that helps us over-
more understandable may throw
is
Human
understandable.
less
is
if
un-
out with some-
to start
is
thing easier to understand in order to see
come some
difficult to
is
beings
should be able to understand what goes on when they make
something or change something. That stand than what goes on in nature
when human
Understanding works of
in the picture.
less difficult to
is
art
under-
beings are not
may, therefore, help
us to understand the workings of nature. suggested,
I
the preceding chapter, that in
in
meaning the phrase "work of art" covers everything made.
Let's reconsider that.
beings
artificial,
Is
I
think you should, then
drawing the
rectly
is
man-
human
parents produce children,
are the children artificial? Are they works of art? If as
that
everything produced by
When
not natural?
broadest
its
we have not
you
say no,
yet succeeded in cor-
line that divides the artificial
from the natu-
ral.
Suppose that lightning tree
split in half;
is
them
sets
off a
changes that
branches are cut
forest
result
strikes a tree in a
fire.
The
off.
forest
dense
forest.
The burning fire
and
of
all
from the lightning's stroke are
The
some of
the other
all
natural,
are they not?
But
away
on
a person,
walking through the woods, carelessly throws
a lighted cigarette.
fire,
and the woods
was caused by lightning.
The
work of man
a
It
are
human
first
sets
consumed
in flames.
being, as the
one was
— something
the dry leaves of the underbrush
a
first
That
forest fire
one was caused by
work of nature. Was the second
artificial,
a
not natural?
Suppose, however, that the individual in the woods had not
Man dropped a lighted
cigarette.
mound
in a
that he surrounded
with small stones. Then, lighting a match, he
not, that
of
he had built
unlike the
art,
We
would
Would
a fire.
fire set
25
:
Suppose he had gathered dry twigs
and leaves and heaped them order to cook his lunch.
Maker
the
the
them
set fire to
in
would we
ordinarily say,
he built be a work
fire
dropping of a lighted
off by the careless
cigarette?
Before you answer that question too quickly, fire itself is
to
make
it
something natural. happen. In
what does he make to
happen
at
—the
fire itself
through the woods caused
it
to
does
or does
and place,
a certain time
human
does not need a
It
when man
fact,
remember
happen
make
that
being
happen,
it
he merely cause
man
as the
at the spot
it
walking
where he de-
cided to cook lunch?
One more example cut off
some of
to consider: lightning split the tree
branches.
its
Men
can do
that, too,
and
with axes
it when they engage in lumbering in wood they need to build houses, or to make You understand that the houses men build
and saws; and they do order to obtain the chairs
and
tables.
are products of art, not of nature
ing a house, then,
is
you cannot be quite tificial,
—
not natural. Build-
artificial,
not quite the same as building a so sure that the fire a
man
fire,
builds
is
for ar-
not natural.
—
What is the difference between the man-made house or the man-made chair or table and the man-made fire? Or between
—
the tree's branches that are cut off by lightning and the tree's
branches that are cut built
down by lumberjacks? Or between
the
fire
by the picnicker in order to cook his lunch and the
fire
caused by the
man
tramping through the woods
who
carelessly
fire
caused by
dropped a lighted cigarette? Let's start with the easiest question
first.
The
26
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
the lighted cigarette was accidental rather than intentional.
was not
for a
resulted
from
purpose that some
human
human
carelessness
being had in mind.
—even
than from careful planning and foresight.
human It
thing that a
human
as lightning
behavior
is
a
being did, but
human
Now, what
man
Not everything
is.
man-made
fire,
some-
a part of nature just as
from
human
art.
deliberately built for the
house, deliber-
purpose of providing shelter? Here neither
humanly-brought-about
result
is
accidental. Purpose
ning are certainly involved in both. So artificial side
artificial.
artificial.
that results
man-made
purpose of cooking lunch, and the
on the
is
of any
resulted from
production or a work of
of the
ately built for the
It
It
rather
on the natural
it
from the
was man-caused but not man-made.
much
The absence
purpose, planning, or foresight puts
side of the line that divides the natural
—
mindlessness
It
far, at least,
and plan-
both belong
of the line that divides the natural from the
What, then,
is
the difference between them?
One difference is clear immediately. Fires happen in nature when men are not present, but houses do not. Men can help nature produce
fires
by lighting matches and setting dry leaves
and twigs aflame. But when than
one
make
we
fires
said before,
happen
men do
at a certain
not
tools
built after
and place. Except
just
for his
but they
he had rescued
made happen
at a cer-
being on the island, no
houses would have ever happened, as
pened
fire itself,
from the shipwreck was something that he and he
alone produced, not something he tain time
make
time and place. In the other case,
men do make houses. The house that Robinson Crusoe some
beings build houses rather
they are not helping nature produce them. In the
fires,
case,
human
fires
might have hap-
as a result of bolts of lightning.
One more
question remains.
We
have so
far
decided that
Man
Maker
the
Crusoe's house, planned and produced for a purpose, of
not of nature, something
art,
entirely artificial
that before
God
—wholly
a
a
not natural. But
artificial,
human
is
creation?
The
Bible
:
27
work is
tells
it
us
created the world there was nothing, and that
God's creation of the world brought something out of nothing.
Did Crusoe bring something out of nothing when he
built his
house? Hardly.
He
built
chopping down
it
saw, and smoothing
out of the
wood he had obtained from
with his ax, cutting off branches with his
trees
them with
into the building of the
The wood
his plane.
house came from nature.
It
that
went
was there
to
begin with. So, too, was the iron out of which nails had been
formed, nails that Crusoe recovered along with tools in the carpenter's
house,
chest
that
made out
floated
of
soe, not by nature, but
That
is
ashore
wood and it
nails,
the
after
The made by Cru-
shipwreck.
was indeed
was made out of natural materials.
also true of all the tools that
Crusoe had the good luck
to be able to use. Let's not forget the children that parents produce.
already tificial
decided that children are
— not works of
art. Is
natural
products,
that because they are
We
have
not ar-
sometimes ac-
cidental products rather than intentional ones?
Sometimes, we know, children are the or thoughtlessness, for.
and are
as
unexpected
result of carelessness
as they are
unplanned
But even when children are wanted and planned
when some thought when, with some a certain time
is
for,
even
involved in begetting them, and even
luck, parents help nature
and place, they are not
like
produce children the
fire
at
that the pic-
nicker helped nature to produce or the house that Crusoe built
out of materials provided by nature.
Why
not? For the time being,
swer suggested above. Children,
let
us be satisfied with the an-
like the offspring
of other ani-
28
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
mals, can certainly happen without any thought, planning, or
purpose. That
not true of anything
is
we would
call a
work of
But just as human beings can make fires happen by knowing something about how fires happen in nature, so, too, can human beings make children happen by knowing something about how the procreation of offspring happens in
art or artificial.
nature.
When
they are totally ignorant of that, then their offspring
are entirely accidental.
the having of offspring
But when they have such knowledge, is,
partly at least, the result of planning
lot
of happenings and productions, and
and purpose.
We
have surveyed a
we have compared the differences between them in order to see if we can place each on one or the other side of the line that divides the natural and the artificial. Before we go on, it might be a good idea to summarize what we have learned. First, we decided that fire itself is something entirely natural. The particular fire a man purposely builds at a certain time and place
is
an
artificial
—something
happening
that
happened had not some human being caused and
would not have to
happen then
there.
Second, the to
it
artificiality
make lunch
Crusoe
differs
of the
fire
from the
the picnicker built in order
artificiality
human
both spring from occur in nature
purposes, houses, unlike
when human
refer to the picnicker's
Crusoe's house as an
fire
as
artificial
beings are not
an
artificial
artificial.
not out of nothing.
It
It is,
at
Though
fires,
never
work. Let us
happening and
to
product.
Third, Crusoe's house, though an
something wholly rials,
of the house that
built in order to provide himself with shelter.
artificial
product,
is
not
was made out of natural matetherefore, unlike the world itself
Man
the
Maker
:
29
God created out of nothing. Let us men make out of natural materials their
according to the Bible,
that,
call things that
always
productions rather than their creations.
we considered human children and the offspring of other animals. Do we ordinarily call them either productions or creations? No, the language we use for describing their coming Fourth,
to
be involves such words as ''reproduction" and "procreation."
The
Let us take that fact as significant.
results
reproduction or procreation are not like the
—
ning
a natural event;
tificial
happening; nor
artificial product;
nor
nor
house that
the world that
caused by
fire
light-
—an Crusoe erected — an
like the fire built
like the like
of biological
by
God
man
ar-
created out of
nothing.
However, understanding how to
understand
Understanding derstand
how
build houses will help us
how animals reproduce or procreate how men make fires happen will help
fires
happen
difference between will
men
as natural events.
making
fires
offspring.
us to un-
Understanding the
happen and building houses
help us to understand the difference between
fires
happen-
ing in nature and animals reproducing their kind.
Do
now whether understanding all this will also help how God created the world. That question until we see whether our understanding of the works
not ask
us to understand
must wait
of nature and of art leads us back to the Bible's story of creation
—
a story that Aristotle never read.
Change and Permanence
Aristotle took a sensible attitude
ceded him.
He
what they had
said he thought
toward the thinkers it
was wise
to say in order to discover
false,
Two
who
pre-
pay attention
to
which of their opinions
were correct and which were incorrect. By the
to
from
sifting the true
some advance might be made.
earlier thinkers
— Heraclitus and Parmenides —held
very
extreme views about the world. Heraclitus declared that everything, absolutely everything,
was constantly changing. Nothing,
absolutely nothing, ever remained the same. lowers, Cratylus, even
went so
possible to use language to stantly is
One
far as to say that this
communicate,
made
it
fol-
im-
words are con-
for
changing their meanings. The only way
of his
to
communicate
by wiggling your finger.
At the other extreme, Parmenides declared that permanence reigns supreme.
ever
comes
Whatever
is,
is;
whatever
is
not,
is
into existence or perishes; nothing at
nothing moves.
The appearance
nothing
not; all
changes,
of change and motion, which
Man
the
Maker
Parmenides acknowledged as part of our daily experience,
We
illusion.
31
:
an
is
are being deceived by our senses. In reality, every-
thing always remains the same.
You may wonder how Parmenides could persuade anyone
to
accept so extreme a view, and one so contrary to our everyday experience.
One
of his followers, a
man named Zeno,
ceived things
per-
moving about, we were being deceived.
We
were suffering an
One
illusion.
of these arguments ran somewhat
hit a ball
to get there, the ball first has to
on
it first
go through half the distance.
soning,
Aristotle
His
—
at least to the service box. In order
followed the direction of Zeno's reato the
—could never
conclusion that the ball could
leave your racket.
was acquainted with these opinions and arguments.
common
sense as well as his
they were wrong.
If
common
experience told
him
words are always changing their meanings,
how could
Heraclitus
erything
changing and suppose,
is
and
his followers repeatedly say that evas
they obviously did, that
they were saying the same thing each time, not the opposite? the motion of the heavenly bodies
change from day perishes,
It
has to go
has to go through half the distance; and so
From this, if we we would be led
never get started
first
it
by a continual halving of the distances that
indefinitely,
remain.
to
to another. In order
has to reach the net. In order to get there,
through half the distance
You want
like this:
from one end of the tennis court
to get there,
tried to
when we
invent arguments that would persuade us that
no one
to night.
dies,
If
is
an
illusion,
then so
is
If
the
nothing comes into existence or
but where are Parmenides and his friend
Zeno now? Heraclitus and Parmenides were wrong, but not fact,
each was partly
right,
and the whole
all
truth,
thought, consisted in combining two partial truths.
wrong. In Aristotle
32
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
On
the one hand, motion and change,
passing away, occur throughout the
human
occurring long before
from being grasps the
be
full
beings
of illusions, our
coming
wodd of nature and were came on the scene. Far
common
experience of nature
of change. Things are the
realit)'
be and
to
way they seem
to
— changing. On
the other hand,
not everything
always changing in
is
every respect. In every change, there must be something perma-
nent
—something
coming
that persists or remains the
different in
one respect or another. That tennis
example, which you
one place baseline,
when
but
was the same tennis
direction. If
it
had been
reached your opponent's
it
you propelled
ball that
a different tennis ball,
magician standing on the sidelines,
ball, for
move from
tried to hit across the court, did
another,
to
it
same while be-
conjured up by a
would have been
it
in that
called a
foul.
Motion from here tion or
(which Aristotle called local mo-
to there
change of place)
is
the most obvious of the changes in
which something remains the same. The moving thing
is
the
unchanging subject of the change that
it
was
when
''your tennis ball"
it
ball"
when your opponent
ball,
not another
While we
When
fell
is
hits
it
back
—
it
is
a tennis ball,
heavy (you and
another word for heavy).
naturally.
That was
You
a natural, not
hit the tennis ball
man-made motion,
me mention
makes between two kinds of
you accidentally drop
But when you
''your tennis
it is still
the selfsame, identical
are talking about local motion, let
ground because
which
local motion.
is
your racket,
ball.
distinction that Aristotle tion.
left
If
not a natural one.
it
on
mothe
say because of gravity,
did not throw
an
artificial,
it
down.
The it
is
a
force of your stroke
ball to fall
a path
It
motion.
with your racket, that
overcomes the natural tendency of the weight, and this force sends
I
local
falls to
it
a
because of
would not have
its
fol-
—
Man you had not propelled
lowed
if
stroke.
The same
thing
it
propel a rocket to the
moon. That is not a natural motion for rocket. Without the propelling force we naturally leave the
From there
is
a
heavy body
give
it
it,
like a
would not
of gravity.
earth's field
tennis balls to rockets, from elevators to cannonballs, a
wide variety of bodies
be moving as they do were ture.
33
:
by your
in that direction
when we
true
is
Maker
the
it
in local
motion
would not
not for man's interference with na-
we
call these
motions
for
they
motions
Since they are not natural, should
That word might be used,
artificial?
that
are
brought about by men. Aristotle called them violent motions violent in the sense that they violate the natural tendency of the
bodies in question.
What
changes that occur naturally also occur
other
or through man's having a
tificially,
the sun ripens a tomato and turns
it
hand
in
ar-
them? The heat of
from green
not a change in place, but a change in color.
to red.
It
is
That
is
not a local
motion, but the alteration of an attribute of the tomato.
From being
green at one time, the tomato has
become
red at
another, just as the tennis ball, from being here at one time, there at another.
not space.
No
What
is
common
to these
change of place occurred
two changes
is
in the ripening of the
tomato, only a change in quality; but neither change
change a
in place
change
and the change
in quality
—the
—took place without
in time.
People paint green things red, or red things green
The
tables, chairs,
and
ral alteration;
the painting of things
them. The house, did not
is
time,
become
so on.
ripening of the tomato
table, or chair,
is
an
—houses, is
a natu-
artificial alteration
which was
at
red at another time without
of
one time green,
human
interven-
tion.
In addition to local motion (or change in place) ation (or change in quality), there
is still
and
a third kind of
alter-
change
34
•
Everybody
Aristotle for
that
both natural and
is
the artificial form of
Take
This time
artificial.
it.
rubber balloon and blow
a
changes in
size as well as in shape.
tinue to do so as you blow air into
of
it,
it
table by
itself,
balloon will not decrease in
panied by a change in shape, artificial
changes
occur
to
its
size. is
and
gets larger,
And when you its
also
make
at the
same time
occur naturally
They
—
and
ing things.
many
—
more there
You
logs.
of course,
we do
build a If
build. If
you feed
in
For
in the
world of
liv-
but
among them
to
changes in
body
a living
in quantity,
it
is
cer-
has a peculiar
not find in the increase of inanimate
and you can make
fire
are
and weight.
more and more
would appear
but no matter
change
The action of waves may More familiar experiences of
—occur
an increase or a change
bodies.
a
size).
and animals grow. Their growth involves
increases in size
characteristic that
in
as they are continually
Although one aspect of the growth of tainly
change
as well as artificially.
and weight
in size
Plants
changes,
quantity
—
a
get smaller.
seacoast caves larger.
natural increase
in-
end twisted and bound, the
example, rocks on a seacoast wear away battered by waves.
out
The change in size, accomyour doing. You have caused
quantity (the increase or decrease in the balloon's in quantity
it
con-
will
let air
would not have
quality (the alteration of the balloon's shape)
Changes
so,
original shape.
the balloon
Blown up, with
creased in size.
two
It it.
As you do
up.
it
decreases in size and returns to
on the
Left
us begin with
let
it
larger
by adding
logs are available to pile
be no limit to the size of the
fire
on
it,
you can
carrots to a rabbit, the rabbit grows in size,
how many
carrots
you feed the
rabbit, there
is
a
limit to the rabbit's increase in size.
You can
and human
labor,
that has ever
been
stones
amid
build smaller or larger pyramids and, given
you can make one built.
larger
enough
than any pyr-
But no matter what you do
in the
Man
the
make them grow You cannot make a house cat
Maker
35
:
feeding of animals, you cannot
to
than a certain
the size of a
size.
be larger
lion or a tiger.
The
reverse
in size as
you
let
The
also true.
is
the air out of
the point where the balloon
animals cease
to
is
balloon you blew up decreases
and the decrease can go on
it,
completely collapsed. But
may
grow, they
to
when
cease to increase in size, but
they do not decrease in size to the vanishing point so long as
they remain alive.
But animals and plants cease to be balloons
This brings us tificial
—
separates
that it
is
So, too, do balloons burst and
die.
when you blow
to a fourth
kind of change
so different
sharply from the
much
them.
—both natural and
ar-
rest.
we have seen, move from here
shape, get larger or smaller.
take time to happen. to
there,
bursts,
it
That change would ap-
peai to take no time, certainly no appreciable
occurs in an instant; or perhaps
Time
in color or
alter
But when the balloon
ceases to be a balloon instantaneously.
It
air into
from the other three that Aristotle
All the others, as
elapses as bodies
too
we should
amount
say: at
the balloon exists, and at the very next instant
of time.
one instant
no longer
it
ex-
we have left are shreds or fragments of rubber, not balloon we can blow up. The same is true of the rabbit that dies. In one instant it ists.
All
alive; at the next,
it
is
no more.
All
we have
left is
a
is
the carcass,
which, in the course of further time, will progressively decay
and
disintegrate.
This special kind of change (which Aristotle ing to be and passing away)
instantaneous.
is
special in other
is
so special that
In every change,
we have been
It
it
refers to as
com-
ways than being problems
for
something
re-
raises serious
us.
saying so
far,
36
Everybody
Aristotle for
;
mains permanent and unchanging. The body or thing that changes in place, in color, or
when
moves from one place or another, when
it
when
color,
when
it
The
What remains
same when the
the
decaying, disintegrating carcass
fed carrots to.
The
in
alters
it
But what remains the same
increases in size.
the balloon bursts?
bit dies?
we
remains the same body
in size
rab-
not the rabbit
is
shreds of rubber are not the balloon
we
blew up. Nevertheless, there
kind of change.
It is
destruction of things by plants
something permanent
is
men
than
Pieces of wood, nails,
make
a chair.
in this special
in the production or
in the birth
and death of
and glue do not come together natu-
Men make
after that
istence as
You
happens,
at
chairs by putting these mate-
They
together in a certain way.
the instant
something you can
sit
when
materials
into a chair as they are
comes
the chair
into ex-
on.
find the chair uncomfortable or
and want
same
are the
and shaped
before they were put together
all
it is
it is
and animals.
rally to rials
what
easier to see
a table instead of this one.
You
you have other chairs probably cannot reuse
the nails or the glue, but you can take the chair apart and,
using the pieces of
wood and some
of the nails, you can build a
small table with most of the same materials. glue in the
first
place,
and
if
If
you had not used
you had been able
to extract all the
nails in usable form, the materials in the chair that has ceased
to be
and
tical.
They would
in the table that has differ
come
into being
only in respect to
would be iden-
how
they are put
together. It
would, therefore, appear
to
be the case that in
artificial
productions and destructions, what persists or remains the same
throughout the change
is
not the thing that was produced and
destroyed, but only the materials that a person used in putting
together and the materials that are
left
when
it
is
taken apart.
it
—
a
Man Something
like that
is
makeup. And
is
may
37
:
after all, a material thing, just
a material thing.
it
dies, decays, disintegrates.
a chair
is,
There
that matter remains, not in the
course, but nevertheless
Maker
also the case in the death of the rabbit.
Being a living body, the rabbit as the chair or table
the
remains,
And
when
is
matter in
its
same form, of
the rabbit breaks
up
just as the inorganic materials
of
enter into the composition of a table, so the organic
may
materials of a rabbit
enter into the composition of another
living thing.
may have been killed by a jackal and devoured for nourishment. To the extent that the jackal is able to assimilate The
what
rabbit
the organic materials of the rabbit enter into the
eats,
it
bone,
flesh,
and muscle of the
jackal.
—
Modern science has a name for what is going on here name that Aristotle did not use. We call it the conservation of matter. However it is referred to, the point is that something persists in the special kind of change that is coming to be and passing away. That something, in the case of artificial things
such
as tables
and
chairs, consists of the materials out of
which
they are made.
man-made
In
materials are nails.
It
is
—
productions,
what these
these particular pieces of wood, these particular
living things die.
stances of
usually identify
not always as easy to identify the particular unit or
units of matter that persist
when
we can
coming
when one animal
eats
another or
But there can be no doubt that
in all in-
be and passing away, both natural and
to
ar-
either matter itself or materials of a certain kind un-
tificial,
dergo transformation.
What
is
meant by "matter
of a certain kind"? tificial
rials
things, never
Human
itself" as
beings, in
work with matter
contrasted with "materials
making or destroying itself,
of a certain kind. Does nature, unlike
ter itself? If so,
then that which
ar-
but only with mate-
man, work with mat-
persists or
remains the subject
38
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
of change in
same
as that
natural
artificial
which
coming
production and destruction
persists or
to be
human
not the
remains the subject of change in
and passing away.
Similar, but not the same.
materials in
is
The
transformation of identifiable
production and destruction
is
only
like
but
not identical with the transformation of matter in natural coming to be and passing away. Nevertheless, the similarity or like-
may help us to understand what happens when, things come to be and pass away. We will look into ness
closely in the following chapters.
in nature, this
more
The Four Causes
The
"four causes" are the answers that Aristotle gives to four
questions that can and should be asked about the changes with
which we
are acquainted in our
common-sense
questions,
and
common
by considering them as they apply
human That
beings,
They
experience.
are
so are the answers. Let us begin to
changes brought about by
especially the things they produce or
make.
will help us to consider the four causes as they operate in
the workings of nature.
The
first
going to be at
question about any
made
of? If
human
you asked
this
production
What
is it
question of a shoemaker
work, the answer would be ''leather."
eler,
is:
If
you asked
it
of a jew-
fashioning bracelets or rings out of precious metals, the an-
swer might be ''gold" or "silver."
producing a steel."
The
rifle,
the answer
kind of material
If
you asked
it
of a gunsmith
would probably be "wood and
named
in
craftsman works and out of which he
each case, on which the is
producing a particular
— 40
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
product,
the material cause of the production.
is
four indispensable factors tion
—
It
one of
is
without which the produc-
factors
would not and could not occur.
The second
question
human
productions.
Who made
is:
be the easiest question of
may
It
That would appear
it?
to
when we are dealing with easy when we come to the
all, at least
not be so
changes that take place in nature and
produced by
to the things
human
nature rather than by men. So far as
productions are
concerned, the question has already been answered in what was said in
answer
shoemaker
to the first question: the
the
is
maker
of the shoe, the jeweler of the bracelets or rings, the gunsmith
The maker
of the gun.
each case
in
the efficient cause of the
is
production.
The
third question
face of
it,
tient to
have
is
is:
that question to consider
What
is
it.
It is
and so
that
is
is
being made?
that Aristotle called the answer
formal cause of the change or production,
as
you
will
''material," the
first
of the four causes.
it is,
the
a shoe, by the jeweler a ring,
you may be puzzled by the introduction of though
On
may make you impayou may say, that what
it
obvious,
made by the shoemaker on. But when I tell you
being
to this question the
it
so easy that
is
nation of "formal" after
soon
that
see, the precise I
word
word
''formal,"
to pair
with
will return to the expla-
we have considered
the
last
of the four
made
for?
What
causes.
The pose
fourth question
is
it
intended to
maker have the question
in is:
mind
Why
What
is:
fulfill?
as the is
quickly.
We
all
being
What
end
we have been
know what
And
its
simplest form,
the answer, with
talking about,
shoes and rings
and guns
what function they perform or what purpose they This fourth factor in
human
pur-
objective or use did the
to serve? In
being made?
it
regard to the productions
is it
comes
are for
serve.
productions Aristotle called the
Man final cause, calling
mind
in
had I
is
in
you or
I
make
we can put
before
it
41
:
it
last
or finally.
to use for the
is
we have
anything, the end
We
must
purpose we
mind.
said earlier that the four causes are indispensable factors that
must be present and operative whenever
To
Maker
that because the factor being referred to
something that we achieve
making
finish
it
When
an end in view.
the
men
produce anything.
them indispensable is to say that, taken together, they are that without which the production could not have taken place. Each of the four factors, taken by itself, is necessary, but none by itself is sufficient. call
All four
must be present together and operate
one another to
in a certain
way.
The workman must have
work on and must actually work on
transform
made to the
to
it
into
By doing
something that the materials
person making
In other words,
it.
it,
have expended the
effort to
You may
for
question the
wonder whether the for
it.
in
material
he must
so,
hand can be
become. And what has been made must be of some use
reason for making
thing
in relation to
final
—must always be
someone
to
he must have had
make
cause
it.
of these statements.
last
—the reason
for
You may
making some-
present and operating. Isn't
it
possible
produce something without having a reason
—without
doing so
a
without that, he would probably not
for
having in mind, in advance, a deliberate
purpose that he wishes to serve?
That question
you must admit
is
not easy to answer with certainty, though
that, for the
most
part,
human
beings do
the effort to produce things because they need or things they are engaged in producing. Yet they casion, fiddle
around with materials and,
something unexpected
When
this
—
aimlessly or, shall
may
also,
as a result,
we
make
want the
on oc-
produce
say, playfully.
happens, there would appear to be no final cause.
42
Aristotle for
:
no end
result
Everybody
being aimed
duced, a function for production
mind
in
to
perform,
purpose
may
for the object pro-
be thought up
completed, but the producer of
is
advance.
in
it
A
at.
It
it
after the
did not have
it
could, therefore, hardly have been an
indispensable factor, or a cause, of what occurred.
When we
turn from
human
productions to the workings of
nature, the question about the presence
and operation of
final
more insistent. We cannot avoid facing it we should certainly be uneasy about saying that nature has this or that in mind as the end result that it aims at. Perhaps, when I am able to explain why Aristotle calls the third
causes becomes squarely, for
of the four causes the formal cause,
will also
I
be able to answer
the question about the operation of final causes in the workings
of nature.
Before
them
ing
I
do
so, let
me summarize
in the simplest
the four causes by describ-
terms possible. Because these
state-
ments about the four causes are so very simple, they may be
difficult to
understand.
We
must pay close attention
also
to the
key words that are italicized in each statement.
is
made.
1.
Material cause: that out of which something
2.
Efficient cause: that by which
something
3.
Formal
something
4.
Final cause: that for the sake of which something
cause: that into which
is
is
is
made. made. is
made.
What do we mean when we say ''that into which something made"? The leather out of which the shoe was made by the
shoemaker was not
on
into
shoemaker went
to
work
became a shoe or got turned into a shoe by the work he which transformed it from being merely a piece of leather being a shoe made out of leather. That, which at an earlier
it.
did,
a shoe before the
It
time was leather not having the form of a shoe,
time leather formed into
a
shoe. That
is
is
why
now
at a later
Aristode says
Man that "shoeness"
The
the
Maker
:
43
the formal cause in the production of shoes.
is
introduction of that word ''shoeness" will help us to
we can make
avoid the worst error
We
causes.
form of
might be tempted, very naturally,
a thing as
its
shape
—something we come
a piece of paper. But shoes
well as colors and sizes.
dow with
dealing with formal
in
If
you
in a
would
common
is
wide variety of shapes,
on as
stood in front of a shoestore win-
sketch pad in hand, you
impossible to draw what
to think of the
are able to sketch
find
very difficult or
it
to the various shapes of the
shoes in the window.
You can draw
think of what
When
it.
is
common
shoes, of every shape, size,
and
a form, shoes could never be are
When
—
they are not
on
—
you
word
A
them
into
you have grasped
made; the raw materials out of
''transform."
leather into shoes,
them
a
to all
Without there being such into shoes.
contains the word
It
you transform raw materials
are giving
have.
common
is
made could never be transformed
Please notice that
"form."
them, but you cannot
color, then
the form that Aristotle calls shoeness.
which shoes
to
you do have an idea of what
into
something that
gold into bracelets, and so
form that they did not previously
shoemaker, by working on raw materials, transforms
something they can become but which, before he
worked on them, they were
We can get further away formal cause
is
not.
from the mistake of thinking that the
the shape a thing takes by considering other
we
kinds of change that
discussed before
—changes
other than
the production of things such as shoes, rings, and guns.
The
tennis ball
you
set in
motion moves from your racket
across the court to your opponent's baseline. ficient
your
You
are the ef-
cause of that motion, propelling the ball by the force of
stroke.
The
ball
acted on. But what
is
is
the material cause
the formal cause?
—
It
that
which
is
being
must be some place
44
Everybody
Aristotle for
'
when you
other than the place from which the ball started out hit
Let us suppose that the ball lands on the other side of the
it.
net,
missed by your opponent, and comes to
is
back fence. The place where
comes
it
to rest
on your
side of the net,
The size.
,
against the back fence.
green chair that you paint red
Redness
is
similarly transformed in
you blew up;
So, too, the balloon
color.
position or place has been
its
transformed into being over there
is
it
transformed in
the formal cause of the change
is
about by painting the chair,
the
rest against
the formal cause
From having been
of the particular motion that ended there. here,
is
just as overthereness
you brought is
the formal
cause of the change you brought about by hitting the tennis ball.
In each of these changes,
you are the
one of them, the green chair
is
you acted on
red.
balloon
you blew
The rally,
in painting
it
it
up.
man
without
occurrence,
natural
more
difficult,
will
be of some help to
said about
rays of the
red,
cause of redness
color, that final
sun are the
itself,
is
is
it.
person
it
from green
to red.
and
efficient cause of this alteration,
the subject undergoing the change,
is
the
ma-
Here, as in a person's painting a green chair
the formal cause.
From having been
green in
what the tomato becomes. But here there
cause distinct from the formal cause
The
arise.
humanly caused
us.
Sunshine ripens the tomato and turns the tomato
four
the
identifying
and some new problems
However, what has already been changes
When
entering the picture as efficient cause.
their
causes becomes
terial
you acted on when
three kinds of change just considered also occur natu-
we examine
The
which
In the other, the collapsed
the material cause, that which
is
efficient cause. In
the material cause, that
who
just
painted the green chair red
so for the sake of having
it
match
is
no
named.
may have done
a set of chairs in a certain
room. The purpose or end the individual had
in
mind was
dis-
Man from the redness that was the formal cause
tinct
mation of the
that
had
it
on the tomato, wished
at last
become
ripening, so far as
being red.
Its
its
edible.
is
to
45
:
in the transfor-
make
The end
surface color
being red
Maker
But we would hardly say that the
chair's color.
sun, in shining
the
is
it
red as a sign
result of the tomato's
concerned, consists in
both the formal and the
its
cause of
final
the change.
Much
the
same can be
about the rock that wears away
said
under the battering of the waves, becoming smaller in result of that process.
This process
moment,
but at any given
both the formal and the
The account
just
for a
size as a
long time,
the size of the rock at that time
final
occurred so
in size that has
may go on
cause of the change
—
is
the decrease
far.
given of a natural alteration in color and a
natural decrease in size applies as well to a natural change of
The
place.
tennis ball that
is
ground and eventually comes
comes
to
that place If,
an end is
at
accidentally dropped to rest there.
the place where the ball
force of gravity
fact
tween an
one were
to ask
upon
it
a
and
—an answer
that
would have puzzled
most
Aristotle.
does not affect our understanding of the difference beefficient cause,
is
on the one hand, and other.
However
it is
material, final,
named
or desig-
always that which, in any process of change, acts
changeable subject or exerts an influence upon
results in that
tain respect
been
motion
to rest,
about the efficient cause, the
would probably be named
and formal causes, on the nated,
local
comes
the
the formal as well as the final cause of the motion.
in this case,
of us learned in school, but that
That
That
falls to
—
it
that
changeable subject's becoming different in a cerred,
larger; there,
from having been green; smaller, from having from having been here.
Let us consider one other kind of change living thing that,
though
it
—
the growth of a
involves increase in size, involves
46
:
Aristotle for
much more acorn that
Everybody
than
uses the famihar example of the
this. Aristotle
falls to
the ground from an oak, takes root there,
nurtured by sunshine, rain, and nutrients in the
and even-
in the process of
becoming.
tually develops into another full-grown
The
What
acorn, he
it is
be oak
to
an oak
tells us, is is
both the
reaches
it
oak
tree.
and the formal cause of the
The form
acorn's turning into an oak.
when, through growth,
final
is
soil,
that the acorn
assumes
development
the end
its full
is
that the acorn was destined to reach simply by virtue of
its
being
an acorn. If,
instead of being an acorn, the seedling
taken from an ear of corn, our planting
would have
resulted in a different
with ears on
it.
According
achieved and the form that
is
that,
a kernel
and nurturing
end product
—
a stalk of
the end that
to Aristotle,
growth are somehow present
had been
it
is
it
corn
to
be
be developed in the process of
to
at the very
beginning
—
in the seed
with proper nurturing, grows into the fully developed
plant.
They
are not present actually,
he would acknowledge,
then the acorn would already be an oak, and the kernel a of corn. But they are present potentially, which opposite of their being present actually.
tween the
potentiality that
is
It
is
is
is
simply the
the difference be-
present in the acorn,
hand, and the potentiality that
for
stalk
on the one
on one way and
present in the corn kernel,
the other, which causes the one seed to develop in the other seed to develop in another.
Today we have
a different
way of saying the same
thing. Aris-
totle said that the ''entelechy"
of one seed differed from the
''entelechy" of the other. All he
meant by
that each seed
had
in
it
that
through growth and development, a different result.
We
say,
when we
that the genetic code in
Greek word was
a potentiality that destined
use the language of
one seed
gives
it
final
it
to reach,
form or end
modern
science,
a set of directions for
i
Man growth and development that
from the
different
Maker
set
:
47
of direc-
by the genetic code in the other seed.
tions given
We
is
the
think of the genetic code as programming a hving thing
moment when
growth and development from the very cess starts. Aristotle
thought of a living thing's inherent potenti-
guiding and controlling what
alities as
of growth and development. descriptions of
s
that pro-
what happens
Up
becomes
it
in
a certain point,
to
process
its
the two
The
are almost interchangeable.
observable facts to be accounted for remain the same. Acorns
never turn into cornstalks.
That
this
so
is
must be because there
is
something
different in the matter that constitutes the acorn,
hand, and
on the
in the
matter that constitutes the kernel of table corn,
other. Calling
what
is
there genes that program growth
and development or calling them control growth
potentialities that guide
and
much
dif-
and development does not make
ference to our understanding of what
of us know,
do
it
initially
on the one
does
make
is
a difference to
going on. But, as most
what human beings can
to interfere with natural processes.
Our
scientific
knowledge of
in biochemistry) enables us to
DNA
experiment with the genetic code
of an organism and, perhaps, to directions
it
(an abbreviation for a term
make
significant
gives. Aristotle's philosophical
understanding of the
enable him, nor does
role that potentialities play did not
able us, to interfere in the slightest
changes in the
it
en-
way with the workings of na-
ture.
I
ities
shall
have more
and
actualities,
damental tificial.
factors in
These four
to say in the next chapter
and
also about matter
changes of
factors,
all
sorts,
about potential-
and form,
as fun-
both natural and
ar-
although not identical with the four
causes, are closely related to them.
To whet
your appetite for what
is
coming
next, let
me
ask
48
:
you
Aristotle for
Everybody
one more change
to consider again
mentioned
coming
—
the special kind of change that Aristotle called
I
am
going
down to dinner and, in the course of it, we eat a piece The apple on our plate, when taken from the tree, had
finished growing. But
is
it
still
that can be planted to sprout
of decay or rotting.
has
We
eat
a living thing, with seeds in
more apple it,
all
it
shows no signs
trees. It
What
but the core.
has be-
of the apple?
We also
most
is
life.
sit
fruit.
come
an occurrence that
to take
familiar to us in our everyday
We
aheady been
be and passing away. As an example of that special
to
kind of change,
of
that has
have not only eaten
it,
chewed
up, digested
it
have drawn some nourishment from
somehow become
part of us. Before
but
it,
we
it,
which means
that
we
started eating
it,
it
the
organic matter of that piece of fruit had the form of an apple. After
we
from
it,
finished eating, digesting,
the matter,
and drawing nourishment
which once had the form of an apple, has
somehow become
fused or merged with our
has the form of a
human
The
apple has not
appear,
matter
form of an apple
itself
to
own
which
matter,
being.
become
a
human
being. Rather,
it
would
has been transformed, from having the
having the form of a
human
being.
It
ceased
be apple matter and became human matter. What is meant by ''matter itself" as opposed to ''apple matter" and "human matter"? Can we say that matter itself is that which to
remains the permanent underlying subject of change in
this re-
markable kind of change that happens every day when we eat the food that nourishes us? I
hope
chapter.
I
can throw some
light
on these "matters"
in the next
To Be and Not to Be
We
ordinarily think of the birth of a Hving organism as the
coming
we
into being of
something that did not
And
exist before.
often refer to the death of a person as his or her passing
away. In Aristotle's thought about the changes that occur in the
world of nature and the changes that by their to
effort,
human
beings bring about
the special kind of change that he calls
be and passing away
is
distinguished from
all
coming
other kinds of
change, such as change of place, alteration in quality, and increase or decrease in quantity.
This special kind of change in nature derstand than other kinds of change.
begin with what
is
When
people
human
move
more
Why? To
easier to understand
struction of things by
is
—
difficult to
un-
find out, let us
the production or de-
beings.
things fi:om
one place
to another,
when
they alter or enlarge them, the individual thing that they move.
so
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
or enlarge remains the selfsame thing.
alter,
with respect to
attributes
its
—
its
place,
color,
its
only remains the same kind of thing that
changed;
after
it
has been changed,
changes only
It
its
size.
It
not
was before
it
it
also persists as this one,
it
unique, individual thing.
The enduring sameness
or
permanence of the individual
thing that undergoes these changes that
its
identity
is
clear to us
from the
can be named in the same way before and
the change occurs: this ball, that chair.
another chair, but
When someone
this
after
not another ball or
one or that one.
takes
raw materials, such
and transforms those raw materials
—something
It is
fact
as pieces of
into a chair,
—
an
wood,
artificial
comes wood have now become this particular chair. Pieces of wood becoming a chair is certainly not the same as this green chair becoming red. The reason is that when the chair has come into being, the several separate pieces of wood no longer remain, at least not as several
thing
tence.
What
that did not exist before
into exis-
before were several pieces of
separate pieces of
wood, though
this chair
remains precisely
this
when it changes in color. Before we go from artificial production to natural generation (which is just another name for the process of coming to be), it will be helpful to us if we look a little more closely at what is
chair
happening duction.
in the easier-to-understand process of artificial pro-
The
help will
come from
getting
some
grasp of the
meaning of four words that were used in the preceding chapter. They are ''matter," "form," "potentiality," and "actuality." Though what they mean can be understood in the light of com-
mon
experience and in common-sense terms, the words them-
selves are not
Pieces of
words we use frequently
wood
that are a chair.
that are not a chair
When
the pieces of
in everyday speech.
become
wood
pieces of
wood
are not a chair, their
Man not being a chair lack
—they
are deprived of
word "privation" There
—the
form of
:
51
They
their part.
a chair. Let's use the
for this lack of a certain form.
more
is
on
lack of chairness
a
is
Maker
the
chairness. If that
wood than
in these pieces of
was
there was to
all
the privation of
wood
these pieces of
it,
could never be made into a chair. In addition to lacking chairness, these pieces of
wood must
quire chairness. Their capacity their privation, for
of a chair, they
wood
did not lack the form
acquiring that
for
they would already have
it,
for
it.
Only
wood, lack a certain
certain materials, such as pieces of
form can they have the capacity
to ac-
inseparably connected with
would not have the capacity
form, since not lacking
when
is
these pieces of
if
have the capacity
also
acquiring
it.
Let us call that capacity a potentiality of the materials in question. Another
word
for potentiality
chair or can be a chair. These pieces of
but they can be a chair. As
However,
it is
makes
wood
moment
is
a a
are not a chair,
ago,
if
they were a
a chair.
when
certain materials lack
have the potentiality
air lack the
form of
air are materials that
for acquiring
a chair,
it.
but unlike
do not have the potential-
acquiring the form of a chair. Although the potentiality
for acquiring a certain
unless that form
is
lack or privation of rials
said a
not true to say that
For example, water and
ity for
I
become
a certain form, they always
wood, water and
It
whether you say that something
great deal of difference
chair, they could not
''can be."
is
form
is
absent, the it
—does not
have the potentiality
never present in the materials
mere absence of the form necessarily
for acquiring
it.
mean
Men
—the
that the mate-
can make chairs
out of wood, but not out of air or water.
When also
form
the pieces of
wood
have the potentiality
for
that lack the
form of
a chair
and
acquiring that form take on that
as a result of a carpenter's skill
and
effort,
we
say that the
^2
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
pieces of
become
wood
pieces of
actually
Throughout the whole process of becoming,
a chair.
until the very
now
that were potentially a chair have
moment when
the chair
is
finally finished, the
wood, undergoing transformation, were
Not
tentially a chair.
only po-
still
been com-
until their transformation has
pleted do they actually have the form of a chair.
When
becoming
ity for it
the pieces of
wood have acquired
We
can
lack of that it
how
see
or lack a certain form. Lacking
it,
it
which
it,
form
in the
wood but
these four important words
—
form. But
the pieces of
is
matter
its
may
also
—
compared with wood.
we saw
When
it
matter,
may have
are related. Matter
have the ca-
potentiality for having that
does not always have such a potentiality
lacks a certain form, as
did not
in water or air.
form, potentiality, and actuality
pacity for acquiring
so, of course,
The form
the actuality that removes the potentiality
is
lack of
now
been actualized; and
as a potentiality.
accompanied the
accompany the
are actually a chair, their potential-
a chair has
no longer remains
that
wood
in the case of water
when
and
it
air as
acquires the form for which
it
has a potentiality, that potentiality has been actualized. Having the acquired form has transformed the matter fi-om being a potential chair into I
being an actual chair.
have been using the words "matter" and "materials"
terchangeably. But
when we
are referring to
in-
wood, on the one
hand, and water, on the other, we are speaking of different kinds of matter.
— matter
matter
Wood
is
not just matter;
it
is
a certain kind of
having the form of wood, which
is
different
from matter having the form of water.
One terials
kind of matter, wood, provides
human
beings with
ma-
out of which they can make chairs; another kind, water,
does not.
The form
the matter has, which makes
kind of matter (wood), also gives
it
it
a certain
a certain potentiality (for
Man becoming
Maker
the
53
.
Matter in the form of water does not have
a chair).
that potentiaht)-.
When we
understand
this
simple point, a simple step of rea-
soning enables us to grasp another important point.
Wood
can become a chair, but
can become
light bulb; water
it
cannot become an but
a fountain,
electric
cannot become
it
a chair.
Matter ha\ing a certain form has a limited quiring other forms. This
is
true of ever\' kind of matter, all the
different kinds of materials that people
things
—
Now ter.
But
it
lacking
form.
all
would
ut-
would not actually be any kind of mat-
forms,
it
would have the capacity
be quite right
if,
to
acquire any
potentiality for forms.
thinking about
this,
you were
to
"Hold on, matter without any form might have an unlim-
lacking
an unlimited
all
forms,
nothing does not
it
would be
exist.
capacit)-, for
to talk
about something that cannot
ask,
did
I
bother to mention
point in thinking about Aristotle
would
acquiring forms, but
actually nothing.
Hence
talk
it
What
Why,
exist."
in the
first
then, you
one way, you
formless matter,
other words,
is
You
it is
to
may
is
although formless matter
also potentially ever\'thing.
It is
are right
not actually
are, therefore, also
right in thinking that formless matter does not exist. that,
is
it?
say that, looked at in
nothing.
would add
actually
place? What's the
in thinking that pure matter, or, in
is
about formless matter
anything
ing,
—
also be potentially ever>- kind of matter; since,
ited potentialit)',
totle
produce
to
deprived of form
totally
would have an unlimited
It
You would say:
It
can work on
and fountains.
chairs, electric light bulbs,
suppose there was matter
terly formless matter.
potentialit\- for ac-
is
But Aris-
actually noth-
potentially ever>' possi-
ble kind of thing that can be. Still,
you
persist in asking, if formless
matter does not exist
S4
••
Aristotle for
and cannot about
it?
mention
Everybody
exist,
what
Aristotle's it
the point in mentioning
is
answer
or think about
understand
artificial
it
if
we confined
or thinking to
ourselves to trying to
productions and destructions
and unmaking of such things
it
would be no need
that there
is
—the making
But the birth and death
as chairs.
of animals are not so easy to understand.
an animal's death
Let's take
Our
first.
pet rabbit dies
and eventually disappears. The matter
disintegrates,
the form of a rabbit
no longer has
that form.
quired another form, as would happen
and devoured by a wolf.
When
this
if
—
decays,
now
It
had
that
has ac-
the rabbit were killed
happens, matter that was
the matter of one kind of thing (rabbit) has
now become
the
matter of another kind of thing (wolf). If
you think about
has occurred here
which
is
chair,
it
ter of a
is
this for a
different
moment, you becomes
does not cease to be wood.
throughout
this
change.
A It
what
from what occurred when wood,
a certain kind of matter,
certain kind.
will see that
It
a chair.
Becoming
a
does not cease to be mat-
certain kind of matter has persisted
can be identified
as,
the subject of the
change. These pieces of wood that at one time were not actually a chair
But
have
now become
actually a chair.
in the transformation that occurred
and devoured the
rabbit, a certain
when
the wolf killed
kind of matter did not persist
throughout the change. The matter of (matter having the form of a rabbit)
a certain
became
kind of thing
the matter of an-
other kind of thing (matter having the form of a wolf). identifiable subject of this
change
is
— not
matter
The
only
matter of a
certain kind, since matter of a particular kind does not persist
throughout the change.
Let us
came
now
turn from death to birth. That pet rabbit of yours
into being as a result of sexual reproduction. Aristotle
was
Man acquainted with the
as well
facts
of
life
process that results in the birth of a living rabbit
ovum
55
:
The began when an
you and
as
Maker
the
are.
I
of a female rabbit was fertilized by the sperm of a male
rabbit.
From
moment
the
of fertilization, a
though while
to develop,
it
is
new organism
has begun
being carried in the female
still
not a separate living thing.
The
birth of the
rabbit's uterus,
it
rabbit
phase in the rabbit's process of development.
just a
is
is
It
has been developing within the mother rabbit before being born, and full
it
goes on developing after
it
is
born until
it
reaches
growth.
Birth
is
another
—
aration
is
nothing but the separation of one living body from the baby rabbit from the a local
motion, a
mother
movement
being in one place to being in another
mother
rabbit.
that sep-
of the baby rabbit from
— from being
mother
rabbit to being outside the
And
inside the
rabbit.
—
now go back to the beginning of the baby rabbit the moment when it first came to be. Before that moment, there was the female rabbit's ovum and the male rabbit's sperm. Neither the ovum nor the sperm was actually a rabbit, though both together had the potentiality' for becoming a rabbit. The actualization of that potentialit}' took place at the moment of fertilization, when the matter of the sperm was merged or frised Let us
with the matter of ovum.
Do
the matter of the
ovum and
the matter of the sperm in
separation from each other stand in the
same
relation to the
matter of the baby rabbit after fertilization occurs, as the matter of the rabbit stands to the matter of the wolf after the rabbit has
and devoured by the wolf?
been
killed
what
Aristotle
formless matter
had is
in
then something
mind when he asked
enduring in
It is
this special
that
like
us to think about
coming to be and which we identify as
the subject of change in the
passing away of living organisms. persisting or
If so,
kind of change.
56
This
is
thought
it
for in the
me
near as
as
ask
far
—
same way you
is
that "nature proceeds
things in such a
way
living
it
by is
little
from things
He
said
lifeless to living
impossible to determine the exact
He was
quite capable of imagining the
be of the
to
identify the matter that as
so,
living being crossed
when
organisms on earth emerged from nonliving mat-
coming
In that
you do think
one more example.
little
that
demarcation."
first
ter.
can be accounted
that Aristotle himself considered.
between the nonliving and the
line
the
that natural generation
one
why Aristotle You may think
to explaining
as artificial production. If
to consider
The example
line of
can come
I
necessary to mention formless matter.
went too
that he
let
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
is
first
living organisms,
can we
the subject of this remarkable change
being matter of a certain kind? Does
of matter both before and after the
it
first
remain the same kind living
organisms came
into being?
You may But,
not want to go so
far as to call
on the other hand, you may
find
matter of a certain kind, which would tained a certain form.
derstand
why
to explain
Aristotle
than
why he thought
If this is
it
formless matter.
difficult to identify
mean
state of
that
it
it
had and
as re-
mind, then you un-
thought natural generation more
artificial it
your
it
difficult
production; and you also understand
necessary to mention and ask you to think
about pure or formless matter, which, of course, does not
exist.
8
Productive Ideas and
Know-How
The a
individual
bed or
a
who
house
first
wood and made it had some idea
took
— must have
into a chair
of
—
or
what he was
going to make or build before setting to work. Such an individual
had
have
to
to
understand the form that the pieces of
acquire in order to
that idea
become
a chair.
wood would
He could
isted before
he made
this one. Perhaps,
we may
guess, he got
from experiences with rock formations that provided with support for sitting down. tion of
not get
from an experience with chairs because no chairs ex-
something
its
The
first
his
it
body
chair was thus an imita-
inventor had found in nature, as the
first
house was, perhaps, an imitation of natural cave formations that provided shelter.
Wherever or however the chair, the idea itself lier
first
chairmaker got the idea of a
was not enough. As we observed in an
chapter, the form of a chair
chairs of every size, shape,
—chaimess—
and configuration of
is
ear-
common
to
parts. If all that
— 58
the
Everybody
Aristotle for
••
carpenter had in his
first
eral,
mind was an
idea of chairs in gen-
he could not have produced an individual chair, particular
in every respect in
which one individual chair can
wood
others. In order to transform the
from
differ
materials he worked on,
by giving those materials the form of a chair, he also had to
have some idea of the particular chair he was about Productive thinking involves having what
to
produce.
we may be tempted
Since no Greek equivalent of the word
to call creative ideas.
we should
"creative" was in Aristotle's vocabulary,
resist that
temptation, and speak instead of productive ideas. Productive ideas are based
can
take,
on some understanding of the forms
that matter
supplemented by imaginative thinking about such de-
tails as sizes,
Without
shapes, and configurations.
a productive
idea in this full sense, the craftsman cannot transform raw terials into this
or anything else that can be
—be
ma-
it
a chair, a bed, a house,
made out
of materials provided by
individual thing
nature.
There are two ways pressed.
draw up duce.
The
first
in
which
a productive idea
a plan or blueprint of the thing
With
mind, he
a productive idea in
materialization
of
that
idea
—
its
in
mind
before he
he was about to projust
produced
embodiment
expressed the productive idea he had.
what idea he had
can be ex-
chairmaker or housebuilder probably did not
If
made
house, he might not have been able to
in
it.
The
matter
you had asked him the chair or built the tell
you
many
in so
words. But once he had brought the chair or house into existence, he could have pointed to I
had
in
Much became became
it
and
said,
'There, that
is
what
mind." later in the history
able to draw
of mankind, craftsmen of
up plans
for the
making of
all sorts
things.
They
able to express their productive ideas before actually
materializing
them by transforming
matter.
But even
at later
Man stages in the history of
human
always proceed to work by
first
down on paper in some idea in their mind and
it
work
had
:
59
putting their productive ideas
They
sometimes hold the
still
guide them in every step of the
until the finished product
presses the idea they
Maker
productivity, craftsmen do not
fashion. let
the
comes
into existence
and ex-
in the first place.
This distinction between two ways in which productive ideas
can be expressed
calls
our attention to two phases in the making
of things, phases that can be separated.
One
the idea of a particular house to be built
plans for the building of that house.
individual can have
and can draw up the
Another individual, or
Nowadays to the mak-
other individuals, can execute or carry out that plan.
we
differentiate
between these different contributors
ing of a house by calling one an architect and the other a
builder
(or,
if
the builder employs other persons to engage in
we call the builder a contractor). The individual who draws up the plans in the first place one who has the productive idea. Those who execute the building the house,
must have know-how. In the making of anything, whether a chair or a house, productive ideas are not
them
out,
terials in
it is
necessary to
know how
to deal
such a way that their potentiality
or a house
is
actualized. Unless that
end
for
enough.
To
is
the
plans it
be
carry
with the raw ma-
becoming
result
productive idea will not be expressed in matter.
is
a chair
reached, the
It
will not be
materialized.
Of
course, one and the
same
indiviual
may have both
the
know-how needed for making a chair or The only thing we must remember is that productive and know-how are distinct factors in the making of things.
productive idea and the a house.
ideas
What
enters into the craftsman's
First of all,
he must know
know-how?
how
to
choose the appropriate raw
6o
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
materials for
making the kind of thing he has
whatever tools he has only his bare hands.
mer and
at his disposal, or
for
If,
And
house out of stones.
what
gardless of
mind, with at all,
but
example, his only tools are a ham-
make
saw, he cannot
in
with none
a chair out of iron or steel or a
should go without saying
it
tools are available, the artisan
that, re-
cannot make a
chair or a house out of air or water.
Beyond knowing how work on with the
know how by
to
choose the appropriate materials
tools at his disposal, the craftsman
to use those tools efficiently
step, in the construction
and how
must
to
also
to proceed, step
of the thing he wishes to make. In
the building of a house, laying the foundations precedes getting the frame up, as that precedes putting the roof on.
The mind, all
the hands,
and the
tools of the craftsman, taken
together, are the efficient cause of the thing that
They
act
upon
is
produced.
the raw materials to actualize the potentialities
that such materials have for being transformed into the product that the
Of
maker had
mind.
in
these three factors (which together constitute the efficient
cause), the
mind
is
the principal factor.
that has the productive idea
tools are
the maker's
mind
and the know-how, without which
neither hands nor tools could ever
hands and his
It is
make
anything.
merely the instruments his
The maker's mind uses to
put his productive idea and his know-how into the actions required to act on the raw materials and actualize their potentialities.
The human mind
is
Everything else
is
tion.
To know how
the principal factor in
human
produc-
instrumental.
make something is to have skill. Even in the simplest performances, which we sometimes call unskilled labor, there is some know-how and, therefore, some skill. From to
Man complex
the simplest to the most
beings engage
—from
are the levels of
who
person
has the
for ''skill"
which
know-how
The combining form
comes from the Greek English
An
art.
know-how
or
the levels of
know-
word ''technique."
required for making someit.
Aristotle used in talking
some men may have and
that
mention
I
because
this
about the acquired
may
others
not have for making
means
techno- which
techne. In Latin, this
art or skill,
becomes
ars
and
person
who
has the technique,
making
things.
We
would
if,
in addition to
tech-
ability
artist is a
for
creative artists
61
which human
word "technique" comes from the Greek word
the English
things.
—
the
is
thing has the technique for making
nikos,
:
skill.
Another English word
The
Maker
the building of toy models by children to
the building of bridges, dams, and schools
how
in
activities
the
in
skill,
such persons
call
having the know-how, they also
have the productive idea that
is
the
primary
indispensable
source from which comes the thing to be made.
We an
sometimes use the word
artist.
works of the
We
first
produced by
cannot be produced unless someone has acquired
art
know-how
must
"art" for the things
use that word as short for "works of art." But since
to
produce them,
exist in a
dent in a work of
human
art in the
being before
it
know-how can make itself evisense of
art.
Although you would readily
refer to cooks, dressmakers, car-
penters, or shoemakers as artists or craftsmen because
ognized that they had the that,
skill
you would probably not
teachers as
artists. Aristotle,
of a certain artists.
skill
or
or
know-how
for
refer to farmers,
you
making
rec-
this or
physicians, or
however, recognized their possession
know-how
But he also pointed out
that
would
how
justify calling
different their art
is
them from
the art of cooks, carpenters, and shoemakers.
The
latter
produce things
—
cakes,
chairs,
and shoes
—
that
62
:
Aristotle for
Everybody
would never come
They
things.
effort.
productive
Nature does not produce such
always works of
are
human
into existence without
know-how, and
ideas,
But nature, without
art.
human know-how and effort, does produce fruits and grains. Why, then, should we refer to farmers, who raise such things as apples or corn, as artists? What have they produced? By themselves, nothing. Farmers have merely helped nature to
produce the apples and the corn that nature would have
produced anyway. They have the
or
skill
know-how
to
cooper-
ate with nature in the production of fruit or grain; and, by so
doing, they
may be
able to obtain a better supply of nature's
products than would have fallen to their hands
if
they had not
cooperated with nature in producing them.
As farmers, having the know-how or cooperate with
culture, grains, skills
nature
in
that belong to agri-
skills
the
production of
fruits,
and vegetables, so physicians, having the know-how or
that belong to medicine, cooperate with nature in preserv-
ing or restoring the health of a living organism. Since health, like
apples and corn,
something that would
is
exist
even
if
there
were no physicians, physicians, as well as farmers, are merely cooperative
artists,
not productive ones
like
the shoemakers and
the carpenters. So, too, are teachers.
Human
without the aid of teachers,
beings can acquire knowledge
just as apples
the aid of farmers. But teachers can help
knowledge,
just as
desired qualities
healing,
The
is
human
beings acquire
farmers can help apples and corn to grow in
and
quantities.
Teaching,
like
farming and
a cooperative, not a productive art.
productive
arts
differ
in
many
turns out a wide variety of products
houses
and corn grow without
to paintings, statues,
ways.
—from
Human making
chairs, shoes,
and
poems, and songs. Paintings and
Man and chairs
statues are like shoes rials that
somehow
the maker
chairs, paintings
and
the
Maker
made
in that they are
of mate-
and
transforms. Also, like shoes
statues exist at a given place
and
63
:
given
at a
time.
On
the other hand, a piece of music
over and over again time.
—does not
can be sung
It
at
many
ferent times. In addition,
piece of music, as
The song and
it
different places
song that
and
poem
takes time to recite a
it
a
is
one place and at
sung
at
one
many
dif-
takes time to sing a song or play a
or
the story have a beginning, a middle,
sequence of times, which
in a
—
exist just at
is
tell
a story.
and an end
not true of a statue or a
painting.
There
is
one further difference between
a painting or a statue.
Stories
down
songs can be written
in
a
song or a story and
can be written down in words; musical notations.
The words
of
speech and the notations of music are symbols that can be read.
The
who
person
is
able to read
them can
get the story that
being told by them, sing the song or hear
and the
statue
must be seen
painter or sculptor,
To
directly.
you must go
it.
is
But the painting
enjoy the work of a
to the material
product that he
has made.
Though
the painting or the statue
is
a material product like
the shoe or the chair,
it is
story or the song, not
something to be used,
chair.
on the
Of
course,
wall, as
stead of sitting
it
it
is
is
also
something
to
be enjoyed, like the
like the
shoe or the
possible to use a painting to cover a spot
possible to enjoy a chair by looking at
down on
it
in-
it.
Nevertheless, using and enjoying are different ways that
men
art. They use them when they employ them some purpose. They enjoy them when they are satisfied
approach works of to serve
with the pleasure they get from perceiving them in one way or
another
—by
seeing, hearing, or reading.
64
Everybody
Aristotle for
•
The
we
pleasure
get
when we enjoy
that
not
is
there
all
to
is
It
it.
a
work of
we enjoy
thing to do with our calHng the thing
house beautiful simply because
being well
made
human we
one
is
it
it
is
make good
The
sense.
statue or the house,
somehow connected
well made.
is
it
The
a chair or a statue.
another
Aristotle's suggestion that these
to
We
all
much know
by a skilled or soups shirt
two
pleasure
pleasure
factors are related appears
we
get
from looking
with
its
being well made.
A
pleasure.
tailor,
made by
or a soup
made by
persons with very
—than poorly made
is
skilled
a skilled cook,
little skill.
and
well made.
We
—
give us
more
would expect
We
skilled
cooks or
would be very
shirt or
tailors to
surprised
if
one
cook thought a soup was well made and another, having skill,
thought
We would
to
shirts
The well-made
the art of cooking or tailoring
it
was poorly made.
not be so surprised
liked
it
and the other
we found
if
looking at a painting that skilled
one
made
ones.
who have
agree in their judgments.
equal
is
would not
the difference between a piece of clothing
In addition, those
soup
the
made
poorly
have the know-how by which they can judge whether a a
at
or listening to the story or the song,
and the well-made soup are more enjoyable
pleasure
Its
factor.
statue, a poorly constructed house, a poorly told story
give us as
But
beautiful.
factor that enters into the beauty of a
product, whether
from beholding
get
has some-
also possible to call a chair, a
is
table, or a
is
art
didn't.
artists
We
that,
of two persons
agreed was well made,
do not expect individuals
enjoy the same things or enjoy them to the same extent.
What
gives
one person pleasure may not give pleasure
to an-
other. Just as
one person may have more
another, so one person
may have
skill
or
know-how than
better taste than another.
It
Man would be wiser
Maker
not
know anything about how such
might be wiser
enjoyability of a taste to like a
person
to ask a
work of
art that
65
who
did
things should be made. So
who had
We would
work of art.
:
person whether a certain work of
was well made than to ask that question of a person
art
it
to ask a skilled
the
better taste about the
expect a person of better
— not only
was better
better
made
but more enjoyable.
The
whether we should a
work of
art
some reasons answering
it
be expected to agree, about the beauty of
all
anwering
for
in
We
well
to
to answer.
produce
made
Where
it
by saying no.
be easier
needed
its
by saying yes, and some reasons for there were to the beauty of a
If all
being well made, the question would
expect those
work of that
a
who have
sort to
the
know-how
be able to agree that
it
or poorly made.
does this
does the person of
all skill
important know-how acquire
come from? How
it?
There are two answers. In the duction, the
be able to agree, or
all
has never been satisfactorily answered. There are
work of art consisted
is
we should
question whether
earlier stages of
human
pro-
know-how needed was based on common-sense
knowledge of nature nature provided the
—knowledge about the
human
raw materials that
producer to work on and knowledge
about the use of the tools to be worked with. In later stages,
and
especially in
needed has been based on
now
consists of
scientific
name
modern
scientific
what we have come
knowledge gives
for scientific
us.
know-how
as
times, the
know-how
knowledge of nature, and to call the
'Technology"
it
technology that is
just
another
compared with common-sense
know-how.
Does
Aristotle's
uncommon common
know-how? Does philosophical thought
sense give us any useful
—the understanding of
66
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
we have been
natural processes that
ing chapters
No,
considering in the preced-
us to produce things?
does not. Scientific knowledge can be applied produc-
it
Scientific
tively. skill
— help
and power
knowledge, through technology, gives us the
to
produce things. But the philosophical
tion or understanding that improves our
the physical world in which
we
reflec-
common-sense grasp of
live gives us neither the skill
nor
the power to produce anything.
Remember, ter.
for
example, something said in an earlier chap-
Aristotle's philosophical
understanding of
why
acorns de-
velop into oaks and kernels of corn develop into stalks of corn
does not enable us to interfere with these natural processes in
any way. But our
scientific
knowledge about
DNA
and the
genetic code does enable us to alter the pattern of development
by splicing the genes. Is
Yes,
philosophy it is,
if
totally useless, then, as
we confine
compared with science?
ourselves to the use of knowledge or un-
derstanding for the sake of producing things. Philosophy bakes
no cakes and builds no But there the use
a use of
is
we put
it
when we engage
to
and manage our
worse
knowledge or understanding other than in
the production of
Knowledge and understanding can be used
things. lives
bridges.
lives
That
is
and
to direct
societies so that they are better rather
our
than
better rather than worse societies.
a practical rather than a productive use of
and understanding
—
knowledge
a use for the sake of doing rather than a
use for the sake of making. In useful
that
dimension
— more
of
human
useful than science.
life,
philosophy
is
highly
PAX J
m
MAN THE DOER
Thinking about Ends and Means
I
do not have an automobile and
want
me a
more money than
costs
money needed
to get the
number
of ways in which
tional
money;
In this
the
same
ting the is
I
number
How
or
I
—
can borrow
—
I
necessary for
it,
can
to
be
needed without
is
by not spending try to
earn addi-
it.
getting the automobile
buy the car which there
to
an end to
is is
the end in view. Geta
are,
means to that end; as we have seen,
it
a
of means.
do
I
others; going
choose
among them? One may be
one way may
going the other ways. tain the
can save else; or
I
there might have been countless others of
money needed
also itself
I
It is
There appear
car.
can get what
have on something
example sort
buy the
to I
want one. The automobile
have available.
For example,
violating the law.
what money
I
I
end
in view,
Of
get
me my
goal
easier than the
more quickly than
the several means, each serving to at-
one would normally choose the means
-JO
Aristotle for
:
Everybody
I seems better by virtue of being
that
easier, quicker,
When we
we
act this way,
act purposefully.
purpose in what we do
have
a
some
goal that
we have
Sometimes we
in
is
we
that guides our acting in
aimlessly requires no thinking part,
we
have
are
—
boat just drifting on the
like a
achieve
aiming
it.
We
at
have
When we
it.
We
act in
have nothing in
one direction or another. To
on our
act
part.
We
first.
—the end we
have
to
to think
about the
are trying to achieve.
means think about which
think about the various
to
we
however, we act purposefully, and then we
cannot act without thinking goal
say that
are acting for
mind.
act aimlessly
are also acting thoughtlessly.
For the most
To
we
to say that
current with no one at the wheel to steer
mind
likely
and so on.
to succeed,
that way,
more
that is
we can
We
use to
the better of alter-
means and why one is better than another. And if the particular means that we choose to employ is a means we cannative
not use without doing something else
hands on
it,
means
the
to
then
it
Thinking of the ing.
It
is
sort
itself
It
is
in order to lay
our
an end, and we must think about
it. I
have
just described
thinking about ends and
means
is
practical think-
—thinking about
the
reach and thinking about what must be done
goal you wish to get there.
is
achieving
first
the kind of thinking that
is
to
necessary for pur-
poseful action.
Productive thinking, as to
we have
seen,
is
thinking about things
be made. Practical thinking, in contrast,
what
is
thing,
to
be done.
you have
to
To
is
thinking about
think well for the sake of making some-
have what we called productive ideas and
know-how. To think well
for the sake of getting
what you do, you have
have an idea of a goal to be reached
to
somewhere by
Man and ideas about ways of reaching about the reasons
why one way
And you
it.
also
Doer
the
have
:
yi
to think
of pursuing your goal
is
better
than another. Productive thinking, or thinking in order to produce something, does not actually
produce
Such thinking may
it.
lead to
actual production, but production does not actually begin until
the producer goes to work and acts
form them
had
in
in a
way
on the raw materials
to trans-
that will materialize the productive idea
he
mind.
So, too, practical thinking, or thinking in order to act purposefully or to do falls is
what
necessary to achieve
is
short of actual doing.
Doing begins when
put into practice. Productive thinking
production
actually going on.
is
some end
or goal,
practical thinking
may continue while may con-
Practical thinking
tinue during the course of purposeful action. But until
making
and doing actually begin, productive thinking and practical thinking bear no
fruit.
Aristotle tells us that, except for the exceptional instances of
aimless behavior, view.
The
human
beings always act with
some end
thinking they do in order to act purposefully begins
with thinking about the goal to be achieved, but
when
begin to do anything to achieve that goal, they have to the
means
for
first
in
do
at
but the means
human
to
accomplish their purposes.
beings always
for
—
or usually
—
in view, Aristotle also says that they act for
with a good that
In his view,
it
with
in order to act purposefully,
they wish to obtain and possess.
aimed
start
in the thinking
it.
what they do
In saying that
some end
The end comes
they
first
achieving
that individuals
come
in
is
as
identifies
an end being
desired.
makes no sense
an end that we regard
He
act with
some good
bad
at all to say that
for us.
we
are acting
That amounts
to saying
72
;
that
Everybody
Aristotle for
what we
are
plain
common
thing
we
aiming
at
something we do not
is
we
sense that what
desire to avoid, not
desire.
regard as bad for us
something we desire
is
It is
some-
to possess.
What about the means we need to achieve the end we have in mind? To aim at an end is to seek a good that we desire. Are the
means we must and no.
desire? Yes
desire
them
for their
for the sake of
we The means are good, but not because we own sake, but only because we desire them
use to achieve the end also goods that
something
else.
Must we always regard means as good because they provide us with a way of getting the end we want to achieve? Certainly, means are good only if they do help us succeed in reaching our goal.
But
they have other consequences, too, then they
if
be undesirable
we have
would
we
I
would wish
seek
where we want
do not want
To sum
money
get the
that
I
need
buy an au-
me
into serious
use to attain
must not only be good because they
to go, but they
to be
up:
to avoid.
to
The means we
want, but stealing might also get
I
trouble that
the end
may
from achieving the end
mind.
in
Stealing
tomobile
for reasons quite apart
—
in
must
also not land us
get us
where we
jail.
means may be an end
other means, and an end
may
that
also be a
we have to achieve by means to some further
end. These two observations lead to two questions that Aristotle thinks
we cannot
avoid.
One
is:
Are there any means that are
purely or merely means, never ends?
The
other
—what
ends that are ends and never means
timate or final ends because they are not
is:
Are there any
Aristotle calls ul-
means
to
any ends
beyond themselves? Another way of asking the there are any things that
we
first
question
is
to ask
whether
desire only for the sake of
some-
Man
own
thing else, never for their the second question
we
own
desire only for their
something
sake.
73
:
another way of asking
sake
and never
for the sake of
else.
maintained that there are means that are merely or
Aristotle
means
purely means, ends that are also
and ends
selves,
And
Doer
whether there are any things that
to ask
is
the
we pursue
that
to goals
own
for their
beyond them-
sake
the sake of any further good to be obtained.
and not
for
His reasons for
thinking so are as follows. If
we
there were nothing that
something
for the sake of
We
begin.
desired for
its
own
sake
our practical thinking could not
else,
have already seen that practical thinking must begin
with thinking about an end to be sought or pursued.
we thought about were
every end
and self,
that further
if
and
We
so
on
end were
view.
means
start
achieving
for
poseful action, with
means other
So
that
is
means far
I
me
when
is.
means
To
it.
put into prac-
to
find
our doing, or pur-
we must
start
with a
it.
have told you only why there must be ends that are
why
there
what
If practical
I
must be means
have told you so
would not
how you have
knowing what your
something beyond
else,
far
that are not ends. surprise
ever done any
final or ultimate
thinking cannot begin with an end that
any end that you seek anything
start
doing,
start
consisted in wondering
to
is
an end that requires us
we cannot
then
it,
practical thinking without
end
to
practical thinking
itself
is
achieve
reaction to
if it
means
some further end, some end beyond it-
to
purely a means, and not also an end that requires to
not means and
Your
a
means
if
with some means to whatever end we have in
means
that
If
still
a
Now
endlessly, practical thinking could never begin.
have seen that
we must
tice,
and not
for
its
itself,
own
how could you
and sake
if
is
a
you do not know of
and not
for the sake of
ever begin to think practically?
Everybody
Aristotle for
74
Since you have undoubtedly done a the course of your
Aristotle
life,
lot
of practical thinking in
must be wrong when he
that practical thinking cannot begin until
end
or final
So
it
says
you have an ultimate
mind.
in
A
would certainly seem.
between two ways
distinction
in
which you can have an ultimate or a final end in mind will open the door to a solution of this problem. To get some understanding of the required distinction, learned in school about geometry
start
let's
we
with what
—the same kind of geometry
with which Aristotle was acquainted.
What
are called the
first
principles of geometry are the start-
ing points with which you must begin in order to demonstrate the geometrical propositions that have to be proved. In Euclid's
geometry, the
gles,
first
The
postulates.
principles consist of definitions, axioms,
and so on are needed, and so are such axioms
whole
greater than
is
same thing
and
definitions of points, lines, straight lines, trian-
any of
parts"
its
and
"the
as
''things equal to the
are equal to each other." In addition, there are
—assumptions
the postulates
that Euclid
makes
in order to prove
the propositions that need proof.
The
difference between the axioms and the postulates
is
that
you cannot deny the axioms. You cannot avoid affirming them. For example,
which
it
try to
think that a part
belongs. But
can draw
when Euclid
a straight line
is
greater than the
asks
from any point
you
to
whole
assume that you
any point, you may
to
be willing to make that assumption, but you do not have so.
There
is
nothing compelling about
axiom concerning wholes and
it
to
as there
is
to
do
about the
parts.
As axioms and postulates are
different kinds of starting points
in geometrical thinking, so are there different kinds of starting
points in practical thinking. Just as you can
assume what Euclid
— Man asks
you
your
a certain goal or it,
even
if
own
end
is
you can assume
practical thinking,
ultimate,
most of us get
is
view can be taken goal about
our practical thinking
we have
—
for the
time being
as if
at least
it
in
were a
which no further questions need be asked.
example we have been considering, we may take being
able to drive to school or to work as the
automobile, being able to buy
and
so on, are the
it,
you came
to that question
to
end
which having an
for
money neded
getting the
means. Of course, you
you could be asked why you want
and your answer until
that
absolutely our final or ul-
timate goal, but rather by assuming that the end
it,
75
and ask no further questions
started in
not by having in mind that which
buy
:
they can be asked.
In other words,
In the
Doer
to take for granted in order to get his geometrical proofs
started, "so in
about
the
realize that
to drive to school or to
might lead
to
work,
to a further
why
an answer about which no further why could
be asked.
That answer,
if
you ever reached
it,
the ultimate or final end, for the sake of a
means. But you do not have
to
would be your grasp of which evervthing
else
is
have such an end in view in
order to begin practical thinking or purposeful doing because
you can provisionally assume is,
for the
own
that
time being, ultimate
some end you have in mind you want for its
—something
sake.
When yourself
you do what needs
why you wanted
it,
to
be done to get
means
order to do what needs to be done to use
That question can be postponed
not forever, not, at purposeful
life.
least,
if
you may ask
but you do not ha\e to ask that
question in order to think about the
pose.
it,
—
you want
for getting
means
for the
it
or in
for that pur-
time being, but
to lead a well-planned,
10
Living and Living ^)^I1
The younger we
more
are, the
acting aimlessly
and acting
we do
things
aimlessly, then at least playfully.
There
playfully.
We
aimlessly. If not
a difference between
is
act aimlessly
when we
have no end in view, no purpose. But when we behave playfully,
game
—
we do have an aim pleasure, the fun we get out of the it is we are playing. The pleasure we get from
or whatever
the activity is
itself is
our goal.
We
have no ulterior purpose; that
purpose enough. Serious activity, as contrasted with playful activity, always has
some some
We
ulterior purpose.
goal, for
which doing
engage in the this or that
not having an ulterior purpose
and
play,
about which
ognize that work
is
I
will
is
one
is
a
activity to achieve
means. Having and
distinction
have more to say
a serious activity
and
between work
later.
that
it
is
We
all rec-
seldom
as
pleasant as play.
The younger we
are, the less likely
it
is
that
we
will
have a
r Man well-worked-out plan for are likely to be
When we
living.
—
immediate ones
are young, our goals
whole. One's
life
week
as a
whole
most.
at the
hardly a plan for living one's
is
77
:
things to do, things to get,
things to be enjoyed today, tomorrow, or next
Having such goals
Doer
the
life
as
a
a very difficult thing to think
is
when one is young. As we get older, we become more and more purposeful. We also become more serious and less playful. That is generally true, but not true of everyone. There are exceptions. Some older persons live only for pleasure and enjoyment, and when we say that about them, we are not complimenting them. On the contrary, we are criticizing them for devoting too much of about
their time
We
tivities.
way
and energies
to playing
are saying that the
and not enough
grown-up person who
not really grown-up but childish.
is
to serious ac-
is all
It
lives this
right for chil-
dren to play a large part of the time, but not for mature
men
and women. As we grow older and more purposeful,
we
serious,
try to
fit
all
herent scheme for living.
We
us.
should
less playful
and more
our various purposes together into a co-
we
If
don't,
we
should, Aristotle
develop a plan for living in order to
try to
tells
live as
well as possible. Socrates,
who was
that
an unexamined
ther
and
said that
an unplanned trying to
we is
Plato's teacher as Plato
one
in
are trying to get or
how
life is
not worth examining, for
which we do not know what we
do or why, and one
certainly not worth
in
to get there.
examining
not worth living because
one's
life is
to
it
are
which we do not know where It is
a jumble, a mess.
It
closely.
In addition to not being worth examining, an is
Aristotle's, said
not worth living. Aristotle went fur-
life is
an unplanned
life is
was
unplanned
cannot be lived well.
be thoughtful about
it,
and
that
To
life
plan
means thinking
y8
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
about ends
be pursued and the means for achieving them.
to
Living thoughtlessly
acting aimlessly.
like
is
It
you no-
gets
where.
But
Aristotle does not think
you must have
enough
it is
to
persuade you that
He
a plan for living in order to live well.
wishes to persuade you that you must have the right plan. plan
not as good as another. There are
is
but only one right plan.
you
will
end up,
If
a
good
One
of wrong plans,
you adopt one of the wrong plans, having had a good
Aristotle thinks, not
end up having had
lots
also
you must have
life,
lived
it
life.
To
according
to the right plan.
The right plan? It may be easy for that we ought to have a plan for living fully
and purposefully. That's
totle
to persuade us that there
we ought that,
it
adopt
to
just
common
sense. But for Aris-
only one right plan that
is
not so easy.
is
Aristotle to persuade us
in order to live thought-
he can succeed
If
will be another indication of his
in
doing
uncommon common
sense.
What can
make one plan
possibly
for living right
and
all
To that question, Aristotle thinks there can be only one answer. The right plan is the one that aims at the right ultimate end the end that all of us ought to aim at. That may others wrong?
—
be the answer to the question, but
unanswered.
What
us ought to
aim
end
is
try to
a part, so
one we ought achieve
it.
Granted, you
—the end
that all of
You can see at once that if there were a we ought to aim at it. Just as we find it im-
possible to think that part of a it is
leaves a further question
at?
right ultimate end,
which
it
the right ultimate end
is
we to
Only
may
find
aim if
it
say,
whole it
at. is
is
greater than the
whole of
impossible to think that a wrong If a
right,
goal
is
wrong, we ought not
ought we
but that
still
to try.
leaves the important
Man
What
question unanswered.
one goal that
the
You may
Aristotle doesn't. Perhaps is
79
:
What
the right ultimate end?
is
is
a hard question to answer, but
is
should say that one of his answers
I
him
very easy for
But
to give.
complete answer. The complete answer
and
Doer
of us ought to seek?
all
think that that
that question
the
is
much
to
not the
is
it
harder to
state
with the easier, though incomplete, an-
to grasp. Let's start
swer.
The
end
right
reasoning on this point
Aristotle's
me summarize
vincing. Let
There
are certain things
things as nourishing
money we need
There
to
we do for
we do
certainly
makes
and
we
We
make
alive,
life.
at least,
as
We
but having
which we have is
itself a
means
to find to liv-
impossible to live well without staying alive
is
long as possible or,
do
earn
to
think that knowing
keep
for
the means. But living, or keeping alive, It
work
better.
Both living and living well are ends
ing well.
to
in order to live well.
in order to
richer
life
—such
shelter.
necessary just to keep alive enriches our
is
life.
think, con-
in order just to live
which most of us have
do not need certain pleasures
them
I
good
our bodies and keeping them
buy food, clothing, and
are other things
a
is
simple and,
is
the effort to get an education because
more than
pursue
to
it.
and caring
healthy, for the sake of
the
ought
that all of us
long as
it
—
seems desirable
as
to
so.
Living,
I
have
living well a
just said,
means
to?
tion, Aristotle tells us,
end we seek else or for
for
any
Anything
its
is
a
means
to living well.
There can be no answer
because living well
own
sake
and not
is
But what
is
to that ques-
an end in
for the sake of
itself,
an
anything
ulterior purpose.
else that
good or desirable,
is
we can think of, anything else a means either to living or to
that
we
call
living well.
8o
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
We
can think of living
means to living means to anything
as a
think of living well as a
should be obvious
Aristotle thinks that that
in fact, agree
common
our
also thinks that
about
The word he
well, but
we cannot
else.
to all of us.
experience shows that
all
He
of us do,
it.
uses for living well (or for a good
has
life)
usually been translated into English by the word "happiness."
Happiness, Aristotle says, if
that
is
which everyone
seeks.
No
asked whether he wants happiness, would say, "No,
I
one,
want
misery instead."
no one,
In addition,
would have
to
There
is
it.
be some more ultimate end,
of which happiness ists.
why he wants The only reason
asked
if
give a reason for wanting
is
a
is
I
good
achievement
life,
for
life."
What if
as
interchangeable with
has been said about happithe word
is
used with any
can avoid using the word "happiness" with
any other meaning, but
many
it
serve as a means.
not as plain and obvious
other meaning.
with
for the
wanting
means. But no more ultimate end ex-
have used the word "happiness"
"living well" or "a
ness
for
nothing beyond happiness, or a good
which happiness can I
happiness, can
different
I
cannot avoid using the word "happy"
meanings, meanings that are related
to hap-
piness in different ways.
We ask
ask
one another "Did you have
one another "Do you
feel
a
happy childhood?"
We
We
one
happy now?"
another "Have a happy vacation" or "Have a happy
When we
use the word "happy" in these ways,
we
say to
New
Year."
are talking
about the pleasure or satisfaction that we experience when we get
what we
People feel
desire.
who
happy.
A
feel
contented because they have what they want
happy time
is
one
filled
with pleasures rather than
Man pains, with satisfactions rather than dissatisfactions.
Doer
the
That being
We
we can be happy today and unhappy tomorrow.
so,
81
:
can
have a happy time on one occasion and an unhappy time on another. Different
human
beings want different things for themselves.
Their desires are not ahke.
may wish
to avoid.
What one
That amounts
person desires, another
to saying that
sons regard as good for themselves, others
We
differ in
regard as good for us.
do
may
our desires and, therefore, we
What makes one
what some
per-
regard as bad.
what we
differ in
person
feel
happy may
just the opposite for another.
Since different persons
happy
feel
as the result of
doing
dif-
ferent things or as the result of getting the different things they
how can
desire, life
—
is
ought
it
be said that happiness
—
living well or a
the one right goal or ultimate end that
to
all
human
good
beings
pursue?
may be able to persuade us that all of us want happiness. He may be able to persuade us that we all want happiness for its own sake and not for the sake of anything else. But how can he persuade us that all of us, wanting happiness for its own Aristotle
want exactly the same thing?
sake,
Human
beings, in seeking happiness, certainly appear to be
seeking different things. That
ence,
which
Aristotle
is
a matter of
common
acknowledged without
knew from common experience,
as
we
do, that
uals think that achieving happiness consists in great wealth; others, that
becoming famous or having If
hesitation.
some
lots
He
individ-
accumulating
consists in having great
it
experi-
power or
of fun.
happiness, like feeling happy, results from getting what you
want, and selves,
if
different persons
then the happiness
different persons.
to
want
different things for
them-
be achieved must be different for
82
Aristotle for
:
If that is so,
well?
How
Everybody
then
how can
there be one right plan for living
can there be one ultimate end that everyone ought
pursue? Happiness or living well all
of us seek, but Please
it is
I
to
the ultimate end that
not the same end for
remember something
said that there
may be
all
of us.
said earlier in this chapter.
was an easy, but incomplete, answer
I
to the ques-
What is the one right ultimate end that all of us should seek? The easy but incomplete answer is: happiness, living well, or a good life as a whole. To get at the complete answer, we must see if Aristotle can show us why living well, a good life, or
tion.
happiness
is
the
same
for all
of us.
11
Good,
Better, Best
We
know from common experience that individuals differ in We also know that in our everyday speech we use the word ''good" as a label for the things we regard as desirable. If we look upon one thing as more desirable than another, we regard it as better. And of several desirable things, the one we their desires.
most
desire
is
best in our eyes.
Reflection on these facts of
mon
common
experience and com-
speech led Aristotle to the common-sense conclusion that
the two notions
—
the good and the desirable
—
connected. As axiomatic as Euclid's "the part
whole" and desirable"
Let
me
''the
whole
is
is
less
than the
greater than the part" are "the
and "the desirable
is
remind you now of the problem we
is
We
saw
same end in view
left
unsolved
at
that differences in
difficult for Aristotle to
the
good
good."
the end of the preceding chapter.
human desires made it all human beings have
are inseparably
persuade us that
when
they aim at
84
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
living well, at a
good
or happiness.
life,
What one human
being
thinks will achieve happiness might be quite different from what
another thinks a good
uphold
Aristotle
his
life
That being
consists of.
view that there
is
so,
how can
only one right plan for
living well or for attaining happiness?
He cannot do human desires are
not
of one kind of desire
The
unless he can help us
so
of the same
all
is
sort,
understand that
and that what
is
true
not true of another kind.
kind of desires that
we have been
considering so
far are
individual desires, desires acquired in the course of an individ-
and experience. Since individuals
ual's life
differ
from one an-
other not only in their temperaments and dispositions but also in the lives they lead
and
their special experiences, they differ in
their acquired, individual desires.
While each human being unique
is
a
unique individual with
and unique experience,
life
all
members of the human species, share in The multitude and variety of individual
common
traits
For the most
human
human common
all
beings,
as
humanity.
differences overlie the
or attributes that are present in
because they are
All
a
a
all
human
beings
human.
part, these differences are differences in degree.
beings have eyes and ears, are able to see and hear,
but one individual's vision or hearing
may be more
acute than
human beings have the ability to reason, but that may be greater in one individual than in anhuman beings need food for sustenance and vitality,
another's. All
common
ability
other. All
but one individual, being of larger build than another,
may
need more nourishment than another.
That
last
example of
a
common
trait
underlying individual
differences calls attention to the other kind of desire desire that
is
natural, not acquired,
and
that
is
the
—
a kind of
same
in all
— Man
Doer
the
:
8s
human
beings, not different in different individuals, except in
degree.
When we
we need food, we are saying that we when we say that we want a new that we desire it. These two words
say that
desire food, just as
much
as
automobile, we are saying ''need"
same
and "want"
—both
indicate desires, but not desires of the
kind.
Needs
human
are inborn or innate desires
nature because
we have
have the same
all
human
common
Without
it,
do
not.
That
The
they die.
is
We
nature.
capacity for nourishment. All plants pacity; stones
desires inherent in
our
certain natural capacities or
tendencies, capacities or tendencies
we
—
why
all
to us all
have a biological
and animals have
all
because
living things
fulfillment of the capacity
that ca-
need food. is
necessary
to sustain life.
The
individual does not acquire the desire for food in the
course of his lifetime or as a result of his
He needs food whether he knows even when he does not feel the need,
ence. it
pangs of hunger. Hunger natural need that
is
is
it
as
have the same need
for
in different
and he needs
he does when he has
always present and present in
all.
and North America
food and drink, and
tain occasions, experience the pangs of
born
special experi-
merely the experience of feeling a
Individuals born in Asia, Africa, Europe, all
own
or not,
on
cer-
thirst.
But
all will,
hunger and
environments and growing up under different
circumstances, these different individuals will acquire desires for different kinds of food
(which
thirsty
want
is
and drink.
When
they feel hungry or
their awareness of a natural need), they will
different kinds of edibles
and drinkables
to satisfy their
desire.
They do not need They want them. If
different kinds of edibles
and drinkables.
the kind of food or drink they want were
not available, their need could be satisfied by food and drink
86
Aristotle for
:
Everybody
they do not want because they have not yet acquired a desire for it.
The example we have been need
common
not only to
ing things. Let us that
is
common
capacity that
is
now
considering
human
all
a biological need, a
beings but also to
consider a peculiarly
human
only to
human
beings becausje
it
all liv-
need, one
from
arises
human nature. suggested that human beings
a
a special attribute of
Earlier in this book,
I
from other animals by their capacity the
is
differ
for asking questions
with
aim of acquiring knowledge about themselves and about the
world in which they
Recognizing
live.
this fact, Aristotle begins
one of his most important books with the sentence: "Man by nature desires to desire for
know." He
knowledge
as
is
saying, in other words, that the
is
much
a natural
need
as the desire for
food.
However, there for
one
is
interesting difference
knowledge and the need
human
for food.
between the need
Deprived of food, most
beings are conscious of that deprivation
the pangs of hunger. But deprived of knowledge, the case that
human
Unfortunately,
we
feel the
we seldom experience
need
is
not true of
for food
are deprived of for
not always
the pangs of ignorance as
pangs of hunger.
have them. That
need
it is
they feel
beings are conscious of their deprivation.
All acquired desires are desires
like the
when
all
we
are conscious of
when we
Some
of them,
natural needs.
and drink, we are conscious of when we
what we need. But other natural needs,
may
may not of what we need.
knowledge, we
when we are deprived The fact that we are
or
be conscious
like the of,
even
not conscious of a natural need should
not lead us into the mistake of thinking that the need of which
we
are
unaware does not
aware of
it.
exist. It
is
there whether or not
we
are
Man have given a few examples of natural needs
I
them with acquired wants and
trast
here to
try to give
needs that
common
all
all
human
desires will help
To or
desire.
It is
common,
beings share in
human
not necessary
as they share in
him
My
nature.
persuade us that there
to
ought
present interest
between two kinds of
Aristotle's distinction
for living well that all of us
all
con-
the potentialities, capacities, and tendencies that
showing how
in
87
you an exhaustive enumeration of the natural
are inherent in their specific is
in order to
:
in order to illustrate Aris-
between two kinds of
totle's distinction
Doer
the
one
is
right plan
to adopt.
understand his argument, we must recognize what
—
most of us do recognize
we
that
often
I
think
want things we do
We even make the mistake of saying that we need them when we only want them. No one needs caviar, but many not need.
people, having acquired the taste for
even allow themselves
That
is
it,
need
to say they
not the only mistake you can
want
and they may
it;
it.
make about your
You can also want something that is not really good Some human beings want drugs or other substances harmful
to
them. They have acquired strong desires
and want them
things
They want something
them. But because they want
If
it
for
it,
it
them,
it
is
good.
When
appears good to
to
is
bad
them
at
for
the
would be
false to say that is
really
bad
nevertheless appears good to them. Their desire or
them was not
is
why
that
which appeared
really good.
In contrast to the things
time you want them but at a later
it
they desire that which
want was wrong or mistaken. That good
that
to gratify their desires.
did not appear good to them,
the desirable
that are for these
so strongly that they ignore the injury
they are doing themselves.
time they are seeking
wants.
for you.
you want, which appear good
may
at the
turn out to be the opposite of good
time, the things you need are always good for you.
88
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
Because they are
really
time and the opposite Yoij
only want
wrong
are never
is
in thinking that
—
caviar, for
at
one
you need something
example
—but your
needs
may be and often mistaken need. And anything
to
wrong or
a
something
merely appears
not good
or misdirected, as your wants
You cannot have
you need
it
for you, they are
another.
at
may be mistaken
when you are.
good
really
be good
good
for you, not
at a certain
something that
time because you desire
it.
We now
see that Aristotle's distinction
between natural and
acquired desires (or between needs and wants) to
another distinction he makes
—between
is
closely related
real
and apparent
goods.
The
satisfy
your natural needs. The things that only appear
good
things that are really good for
for you,
and may not be
really
good
you
are the things that to
be
for you, are the things
that satisfy your acquired wants.
Another way of making goods are the things we
them
sciously desire
real
is
to
say that apparent
good because we do
at the time.
want them, they appear good contrast,
point
this
call
We
con-
want them. Because we
and we
them good. In we need, whether we are con-
to us
goods are things
in fact
call
scious of the need or not. Their goodness consists in their satisfying a desire inherent in
There is
is still
human
worth considering because
Aristotle's
nature.
one other way of making the same point, and it
argument. The good
it
advances our understanding of is
the desirable and the desirable
may be desirable in two different senses of "desirable," just as it may be good in two senses of ''good." We can call something desirable because at a given time we do in fact desire it. Or we can call something desirable because we ought to desire it whether, at a given time, we actually desire it is
good. But a thing
or not.
— Man
What
desirable in
is
We
other.
may
ally
good
we need
for us
one sense may not be desirable
actually desire
in fact fail to desire
what we ought
for us to desire. it
is
to desire
is
re-
because
which
that
something that may be wrong
may be something we ought
It
will turn out to
in the
That which
to desire.
89
:
to desire, or
and we cannot have wrong needs. But
it,
only appears to be good for us
because
what we ought not
something we always ought
is
Doer
the
not to desire
be really bad for us even though,
at
we want it, it appears to be good because we want it. The one right plan for achieving happiness or a good life is,
the time
according to Aristotle, a plan that involves us in seeking and acquiring
They
the things that are really good for us to have.
all
we need not only in order to live but also in order we seek all the real goods that we ought to possess course of our lives, we will be pursuing happiness accordthe one right plan of life that we ought to adopt.
are the things
to live well. If
in the
ing to
Since natural needs, based on our
and tendencies, are the same good
any one person
for
why human sists
happiness
is
in all
common human
human
is
really
good
the
same
for all
beings,
for
capacities
what
really
is
any other. That
human
in the possession of all the things that are really
is
it
con-
good
for a
beings:
person to have, accumulated not at one time but in the course of a lifetime. is
the
same
No human on the
make
And
for all life
that
is
why
human
the one right plan for living well
beings.
can be completely deprived of
it
The
impossible to stay alive for long.
for food, drink, clothing, shelter, least to a
stay alive.
extent
real goods, for
biological level the total deprivation of basic needs
minimal
extent, in order for the living
and no more,
serves poorly as a
biological needs
and sleep must be
But when those needs are
Not only must these
satisfied, at
organism to
satisfied to that
just staying alive
means
would
minimal
—
or bare subsistence
to living well.
basic biological needs be satisfied
beyond
— go
:
Aristotle for
Everybody
minimum required to sustain life itself other human needs must be satisfied in fulfillment of all our human capacities
the level of the barest
many
but, in addition,
order to approach the
and tendencies.
If
happiness consists in such complete
ment, then one individual approaches more closely it
in proportion as
human
One that
good
aims
to achieving
able than another to satisfy his
into the possession of the things that
him.
for
plan for living well
is
better than another to the extent
more complete realization of more complete satisfaction of his needs.
guides the individual to a
it
his capacities
And
more
is
come
needs and
are really
he
fulfill-
and
to a
the best plan of at every real
we ought
the one
all,
good
addition, allows us to seek things
to adopt,
is
one
that
and measure and,
in the right order
we want but do
in
not need, so
long as getting them does not interfere with our being able to satisfy
our needs or
fulfill
Not all apparent goods
our capacities.
—
things that
turn out to be bad for us. selves;
impede or
frustrate
differ
good
from
its
our
in the sense that they
we need and
effort to get the things that
The
for us.
them-
are not injurious in
and some are not disadvantageous
that are really
may
Some
we want but do not need
man
pursuit of happiness by one
pursuit by another even
if
both are following
the one right plan for living well.
The
reason for such differences,
when
each individual may want different things above the things he needs. Though what
human
being
is
the
same
for all,
to
be good
may be
that
is
himself over and
really
good
to be
for
good
to
one
one
quite different from
another individual.
What each
indi-
may be an apparent good that is neither him nor an impediment to his pursuit of happiness.
vidual wants for himself injurious to
to
is
what appears
individual, according to his wants,
what appears
they occur, for
Man
You now have some and how
same
it
human
You and why
beings
see all
why he should
by adopting the one sound plan for doing
remain
to
What
:
gi
grasp of Aristotle's views about happiness
should be pursued.
for all
Doer
the
so.
thinks
try to
it
is
the
achieve
it
Other questions
be answered.
are the real goods that an individual should seek in
order to live well or
make
a
good
life
for himself or herself?
have mentioned some of them, but not
all.
Can
We
the enumera-
tion of real goods be completed? If
it
can be, then there
important of all
all:
in
our
the ultimate
still
should we
we
naturally need
lives?
What means
the things
have
How
is
end we have
in
a further question try to
—
all
come
happiness.
the most
into possession of
the real goods
we should
are indispensable to achieving
mind?
Only when these questions have been answered a full grasp of the plan of
—
life to
will
we have
be followed in order to achieve
12
How
to Pursue
Happiness
When Thomas
Jefferson drafted the Declaration of Indepen-
dence, did he understand Aristotle's view of happiness and
pursue
to
The
Declaration says that
happiness. Living, is
we have
we can
seen,
beings, being equal by
liberty,
means
itself a
is
and the pursuit of to living well.
—without
happiness. life is
If
we want choices we
exercise a free choice about the things
or need, and unless
our
life,
freedom.
Unless
make
human
all
nature, have an equal right to
So
how
it?
we can
freely carry
coercion or impediment
everything
is
imposed upon
about planning our
determined
cannot pursue
for us, if the pattern of
would be no sense
in talking
about adopting a plan
for living
us, there
lives or
out the
—we
well.
We
need
order to
to stay alive in order to live well.
make an
effort
—
a
planned
effort
—
We
need
to live well.
liberty in
Because
Man
we need right to to
these things in order to pursue happiness,
them. But do we need
hve well?
that
human
If not,
human
all
the
nature
The answer
what
is
to
pursue happiness?
to
93
:
we have
a
Do we need
the basis for saying, as Jefferson did,
beings have a right
—
Doer
—
a right inherent in their
pursue happiness?
number of
to that question lies in a
points that
were covered in the preceding chapters. Living well, or happi-
we
ness, life
—
saw,
that
further
is
the ultimate or final end of
which we seek
good beyond
certain things
for
its
We
it.
own
also
saw that we do
we ought
if
a
good
life
whole
as a
to
is
be so
one
—
live well is
sum
total
to achieve
really
good
happiness or a good
for us
of real goods
is
is
no
in fact desire to us.
There
at the time.
that involves having all
the things that are really good for us, then
that
this
because they are really good
to desire
whether or not they appear
Now
and
our doing in
for the sake of
and when we do, they appear good
are other things for us,
sake
all
we ought life.
Since anything
something we ought
certainly
to desire to
to desire, the
something we ought
to de-
sire.
The word "ought" tion.
do.
We
To
say that
goal of our
we ought
life is
to live well or to
To
expresses the notion of a duty or an obliga-
have a duty or an obligation to
to say that
make
a
do what we ought
to
pursue happiness as the ultimate
we have
good
to
life for
a duty or obligation to try
ourselves.
we need whatever is indispensable to making a good life for ourselves we need the real goods that, taken all together, constitute or make up happiness or a good life. That is why we have a right to them. If we did not have the obligation to try to live well and if we did not need certain things in order to do so, we would not have the right to them that Thomas Jefferson asserted all of us have. Thomas Jefferson thought that all human beings, having the fulfill
that duty or obligation,
—
94
Everybody
Aristotle for
••
same human nature, had the same natural to saying that they all
good
really
human
for
beings.
have adopted volves
same
human
being
is
Thomas
extent,
this
That amounts
—
that
what
good
really
for
is
all
Jefferson appears to
view that the pursuit of happiness
Aristotle's
human
all
set
have the same natural needs
any one
To
rights.
in-
beings in seeking and trying to obtain the
of real goods for themselves.
Before
attempt to enumerate the real goods that Aristode
I
all of us should seek, I would like to spend a moment on the difference between the question ''What should I do in
thought
order to pursue happiness?" and the
should
I
make
take in order to
"What
question
steps
a chair, a picture, or a piece of
music?" The difference between these two questions throws
on the difference between doing and making, and between
light
the kind of thinking that
is
involved in acting in order to live
well and the kind of thinking that
something that
is
involved in producing
well made.
you undertake
If
is
to
make
a chair, a picture, or a piece of
music, you must have a productive idea of the thing to be
and you must have the know-how produce
know-how
But you are under no obligation are determined to
make
Pursuing happiness ture, or piece of
no
about
it,
as there
the piece of music.
is
different
to
from producing
is
I
must do
to that end.
Only
if
you
produce
it.
a chair, pic-
You may
There
is
not wish to produce a particular
is
about
this or that."
in the case of the chair, the picture, or
why
if
means
means required
need you, but you ought
no
are the
to seek that end.
chair, nor
there
to
music because you do not begin by saying,
wish to pursue happiness,
if
made
required
skill
that particular chair, picture, or piece
of music must you employ the
I
the
well-made chair, picture, or piece of music. The
a
productive idea and the
"If
or
it.
to
pursue happiness. That
is
Man
You ought
doing so? This
is
answer consists
of us need
—
or a good
two related answers
The second answer consists all the real goods we need
whole.
as a
The
course of a lifetime. so let us start with
first
answer
in his
in the
easier than the second,
is
it.
mals. As animals,
As
we have
human
bodies that need to be cared for in
we have minds that need to Some of the real goods we need
animals,
be exercised in certain ways.
such
Aristotle calls bodily goods,
and
all
by nature, questioning, thinking, and knowing ani-
certain ways.
And
The
goods that
real
the goods that, taken together, constitute happiness
life
are,
95
go about
to that question.
enumeration of the
in his
prescription for obtaining
We
:
the question that remains to be answered.
Aristotle offers us first
how ought you
pursue happiness, but
to
Doer
the
as health, vitality',
and
vigor.
since our senses give us the experience of bodily pleasures pains, Aristotle also includes such pleasures
Few
goods.
of us,
observation that avoid,
if
we
I
think,
we ought
would challenge
his
among
the real
common-sense
to seek bodily pleasure
and ought
to
can, bodily pain.
are goods we share with other animals. They are goods for us because we are animals. It is only in the way that we seek them that we differ from other animals. For
These bodily goods
example, other animals instinctively always instinctively
try to
tv}'
to avoid bodily pain
and
enjoy bodily pleasure. By watching a
human
beings
sometimes give up bodily pleasure or endure bodily pain
for the
pet cat or dog,
sake of
you
will see that this
some other good
we may even
think
it
is
that they think
so.
is
But
more
desirable.
And
advisable for us to limit our enjoyment of
bodily pleasures in order to
make room
in
our
lives for other,
more important goods.
The
bodily goods that have been mentioned are
ultimate end of happiness or a good
life.
means
to the
But they are also them-
g6
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
selves ends for
which other goods
of our bodily health,
and
shelter, clothing,
Aristotle
which he Aristotle,
health,
lumps
these things together under one heading
goods or wealth. Wealth, according
good because
a real
vitality,
it is
and pleasure. Without
a
we cannot enjoy health, vitality, out these things we cannot live well. Individuals who are starving, who are individuals
or pleasure, and with-
of
life,
individuals
or
who
whose bodies
moment
cannot
who
live
well.
are forced to
work
of wealth
is
much an
as
are con-
moment, inthem the simple com-
lack the externals that give
They
are
as slaves,
are confined by prison walls.
amount
freezing or sweltering,
are deprived of sleep or
the effort to keep alive from
who
dividuals forts
who
to
means to bodily certain amount of
a necessary
wealth,
sumed by
drink,
sleep.
all
calls external is
serve as means. For the sake
and pleasure, we need food,
vitality,
to
badly
as
who
The
off
as
are in chains,
lack of a certain
obstacle to living well
achieving happiness as the deprivation of a certain
and
amount
of
freedom. In both cases
I
have
said, as Aristotle
amount." He does not say live well,
that unlimited
would
nor does he say that unlimited wealth
reason for the limitation
not unlimited, goods, good, of which
is
say, "a certain
freedom is
is
needed
needed.
to
The
not the same, but both are limited,
just as bodily pleasure
we can want
too
much
for
is
also a limited
our own ultimate
good.
To tioned
bodily goods and external goods, or wealth
adds a third. These goods he refer to
to the
men-
the two kinds of goods that have already been
—
them
calls
goods of the soul.
as psychological goods, as
goods of the body
—
Aristotle
We
might
we would probably
as physical goods.
refer
— Man
The most obvious
Among
skill.
We
thinking.
the
need
skills all
of us need
know-how
including
all sorts,
certainly the skill of
is
not only in order to produce well-made
it
and
things, but also in order to act well
live well.
Less obvious, perhaps, are the psychological goods that
need because we are
We
cannot
good is
we
—
sort
A is
life
of a slave or of a
human
love other
totally
loveless
life
a life deprived of a
—
a
among
chological
we
good
are as external to ourselves
a
good of the
not place
Aristotle does
He
the external goods.
—
natu-
much-needed good.
treats
it
rather as a psy-
Because
soul.
psychological need on our part, friendship
is
like
it
a
fulfills
knowledge and
rather than like the things that satisfy our bodily needs.
There body.
are pleasures of the
Among
them,
for
mind
example,
as well as pleasures of the is
the pleasure
we
making things and from our enjoyment of works of that are well feel
in chains
without friends of any
life
the various forms of wealth are,
friendship
skill
man
not a
is
beings and to be loved by
Even though other human beings as
solitary life
naturally desire to acquire knowledge, so
desire to
them.
A
complete solitude.
life.
Just as rally
we
animals as well as thinking animals.
social
live well in
any more than the
life,
good
a
97
:
of these psychological goods are goods of
the mind, such as knowledge of
and
Doer
the
made by
in acquiring
others.
There
is
get
art
from
—
things
also the satisfaction
knowledge, in having
we
of one sort or
skills
another, and in loving and being loved.
Human
beings desire to be loved.
spected for the
traits
good
life,
honored unless
we
is
also
wish to be
re-
they think admirable or lovable. Recogniz-
ing this, Aristotle includes, a
They
self-esteem
among
the goods that contribute to
and honor. But,
not a real good unless
really deserve the
it
honor we
is
in
his view,
being
for the right reason
receive.
Some
individuals
g8
Aristotle for
:
Everybody
seek fame instead of honor.
good reputation even
I
have
now
if
They
are satisfied with having a
they do not deserve
it.
almost completely enumerated the
real
goods that
make a good life as a whole. They are the component parts of that whole, and as such they are the means we must use to achieve that whole for ourselves. This is ArisAristotle thinks go to
totle's
answer
first
To
achieving happiness.
and possess well and
all
make
the extent that
these real goods, a
good
life for
second answer
Aristotle's
how to succeed in we manage to obtain
the question about
to
we succeed
in
our
effort to live
ourselves.
to the
same question involves
ferent kind of prescription for us to follow.
It
a dif-
directs us to act in
such a way that we develop a good moral character. Over and
above is
the real goods that have so far been mentioned, there
all
one more
cifically,
goods that we need
—good
habits;
more
spe-
good habits of choice.
Persons possess a
class of
who have developed good
well. Persons
one
habit,
who have
the
that enables
acquired the
of playing tennis well
skill
them
skill
regularly to play
of solving problems in
who
geometry or algebra have a good habit. So, too, have those regularly
and without
or drinking
much
more than
is
good
for
themselves from eating
them, or
fi-om indulging too
in the pleasures of sleep or play.
These
are
are different
all
good
is
a
habits, but the
from the others.
bodily habit, and ease
difficulty restrain
skill
good habits mentioned
Skill in
in solving
playing tennis
is
a
last
good
mathematical problems with
good habit of the mind. Good habits of
this
able us to perform certain actions with excellence,
kind ennot only
regularly but also without effort. Contrasted with these habits of
action are habits that enable us to larly,
make
certain choices regu-
with ease, and without having to go through the process of
Man making up our minds and deciding how
we do so. The person who
Doer
the
:
99
choose each time
to
that
has acquired the firm and settled disposition
to avoid eating or drinking too is
a
much
has a habit of this
good habit because the decision
tempted to overindulge in food and drink
Food and drink
are
real
amounts. There can be too of
all sorts.
We
often
goods,
much
more than we need. That
why
is
amount and
only
many
moderate
in
real goods, pleasures is
good
Aristotle tells us that
—
when
the right decision.
is
but
want more of them than
good habits of choice or decision the right
of
sort. It
to restrain oneself
in order to seek real
them
also in order to seek
for us,
we need goods in
in the right
order and in the right relation to one another.
The name word
that Aristotle gives to all
that can
best be
translated by
to us in
English by way of
more usual English word
Good
for
is
a
Greek
English word "ex-
word more frequently comes
cellence." However, that Greek
down
good habits the
its
Latin translation, and so the
good habits
is
the
word
habits of the kind exemplified by skills of
'Virtue."
one
sort or
another are virtues of the mind, or intellectual virtues.
Good
habits of the kind exemplified by a settled disposition to choose
or decide correctly constitute a person's character, totle calls
them moral
Both kinds of virtue are life.
But moral virtue plays
real
goods that
we need
a very special role in
happiness, so special that Aristotle that has
and
so Aris-
virtues.
tells
for a
good
our pursuit of
us that a good
life is
one
been lived by making morally virtuous choices or deci-
sions.
Why
Aristotle thinks that statement
explain in the next chapter.
sums
it
up
I
will try to
13
Good
Habits and
Good Luck
Some
of the real goods that are required for a good hfe are
means
are
shelter,
wealth to
we
means
live well
Similarly,
engage in If
External goods, such as food, clothing, and
to others.
to
health,
because
we need
health,
vitality,
did not have to do anything at vitality
and vigor
vigor.
We
need
health to live well.
activities that are necessary to
would not need
and
vitality,
we need
and vigor obtain
all in
still
order to
in
other goods.
order to live well,
we
in order to be active.
In the order of goods, the highest ranking belongs to those that
we
life.
Wealth,
desire for their for
own
example,
sake as well as for the sake of a good is
not desirable for
its
own
sake, but
only as a means to living well. But such real goods as friendship
and knowledge sake of a good
Some
real
are desirable for their
own
sake as well as for the
life.
goods are limited goods; others are unlimited
goods.
For example, wealth and bodily pleasure are limited
goods.
You can want more
of
them than you need, and more
Man than you need
is
not really good for you. Knowledge,
the pleasures of the
always better.
Doer
the
mind
They
are unlimited goods.
are goods of
More
skill,
of
loi
:
and
them
is
which you cannot have too
much. /f there were
than you need;
no limited goods of which you could want more goods were equally important, so that
if all real
none of them should be sought
for the sake of
wanting certain things that appear good
to
any other;
you did not come
into conflict with seeking other things that are really
you
no
—
could be lived
2/ life
difficulty
for
this
good
way, then there would be
about living a good
if
for
little
or
and there would be no need
life,
good habits of choice and decision
in order to
succeed in
one's pursuit of happiness.
But
that,
about your right. Just
Aristotle
own
life
knew, for a
is not the way it moment, you will
is.
If
you think
see that he
think about the regrets you have had.
Remember
was the
times you were sorry because you were too lazy to take the trou-
what was necessary
ble to do
remember when you allowed
something you needed. Or
to get
yourself the pleasure of oversleep-
ing or overeating and regretted
it
later.
Or
the time
when you
did not do something you ought to have done because you feared the pain If
you might
you had made the
suffer in
doing
right choice
it.
and decision every one of
those times, you would have no regrets. Choices and decisions that leave
you with no
regrets are choices
and decisions that
contribute to your pursuit of happiness by putting real goods in the right order, by limiting the ited,
amount when
and by putting aside things you want
if
it
should be lim-
they get in the
way
of obtaining things you need.
Moral choices.
virtue, Aristotle tells us,
Making one
is
the habit of making right
or two right choices
among many wrong
102
:
Aristotle for
Everybody
choices will not do. right choices,
tion is
you
If
wrong choices
the
will
greatly
—away from achieving happiness
instead of toward
why Aristotle stresses the notion of habit. You know how habits get formed. To form
on time
for
outnumber
appointments, you have to
That
it.
the habit of being
be punctual over
try to
and over again. Gradually, the habit of being punctual formed.
Once
tion to be
on time
where you promised
in getting
stronger the habit, the easier it is
it is
to act that
you have formed
take pleasure in doing
cause you do
it
and
a habit
what you
with ease
way and
to be.
The
the harder
an opposite fashion.
to break the habit or to act in
When
gets
formed, you have a firm and settled disposi-
is
it
the
be moving steadily in the wrong direc-
well developed,
it is
you
are in the habit of doing be-
—almost without
You
effort.
find act-
ing against your habits painful.
What
I
have
just said
is
true of both
good and bad
you have formed the habit of oversleeping,
is
it
easy and pleas-
ant to turn the alarm clock off and go on sleeping. painful to get
up on time. So,
too,
habits. If
It is
hard and
you have formed the habit
if
of allowing yourself to overindulge in certain pleasures or to
avoid taking certain pains,
Such
it
is
hard
to stop
doing
it.
habits are bad habits, in Aristotle's view, because they
interfere with
your doing what you ought
things you need.
The to
do
in order to get
opposite habits are good habits because
they enable you to obtain what
what only appears
to
is
really
be good for you
at
good
for
you instead of
may
turn
making the
right
the time and
out to be bad for you in the long run.
Good choices
habits, or
among
moral
virtues, are habits of
goods, real
and apparent. Bad
Aristotle calls "vices," are habits of
habits,
which
making the wrong choices.
Every time you make a right choice and act on
it,
you are doing
something that moves you toward your ultimate goal of
living a
Man good
the
Doer
103
:
Every time you make a wrong choice and act on
life.
you are moving
one who
in the opposite direction.
makes the
The
virtuous person
is
time and time
choices regularly,
right
it,
again, although not necessarily every single time.
That
why
is
role in the pursuit of happiness.
virtue as the principal
portant of
all
Moral
virtue
much
of
such
Aristotle thinks that virtue plays
means
to
That
why he
is
a special
regards moral
happiness and as the most im-
the things that are really good for us to have. is
also
You cannot have
an unlimited good.
too
Habits of making right choices and decisions can
it.
never be too firmly formed.
Aristotle calls sists
one aspect of moral virtue temperance.
con-
habitually resisting the temptation to overindulge in
in
pleasures of for us of
or the temptation to seek
all sorts
any limited good, such
bodily pleasures tempt us right away. to
It
is
that
more than
One
as wealth.
we can
Having temperance enables us Having temperance
us in the long run.
and not
for
its
own
sake as
—only
if it
reason
usually enjoy to resist
be good in the short run for the sake of what
wealth in the right amount
is
why them
what appears
really
is
good
good
for
also enables us to seek
means
as a
were an end
to other goods,
in itself
and an un-
limited good. Aristotle calls another aspect of
temperance
is
moral virtue courage. Just as
an habitual disposition to
resist
the lure of plea-
more important goods that overindulgence would prevent us from getting, so courage is an ha-
sures for the sake of in pleasure
bitual disposition to take whatever pains
may
be in\'olved in
doing what we ought to do for the sake of a good
life.
For example, we recognize that getting knowledge and developing certain have.
skills
are
intellectual
virtues that
But acquiring knowledge and
skills
we ought
may be
to
painful.
104
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
Studying
is
how
practicing that
is
The
how to play how to think
often hard to do; learning
strument well,
to write well, or
a musical in-
well involves
often irksome.
habit of avoiding
what
is
irksome because
difficult or
it is
painful can certainly interfere with your acquiring knowledge
and
skills
that are really
good
for
you
That bad habit
to have.
Aristotle calls the vice of cowardice.
The
person
who
habitually avoids taking pains and trouble for
the sake of obtaining real goods dier
who
who
is
as
much
a
coward
runs away in battle for fear of getting hurt.
risks his life
victory in a
as the sol-
The
soldier
or overcomes his fear of injury for the sake of
good cause has courage. So,
anyone who
too, has
habitually takes trouble, undergoes hardships, and suffers pain, in order to obtain things that are really
Temperance and courage
One
is
concerned with
good
for
him.
differ as aspects of
moral
virtue.
resisting the lure of bodily pleasures
with limiting our craving for limited goods.
The
other
is
and con-
cerned with suffering pains and hardships. But both are alike in
one very important
Both are habits of making the
respect.
right
choice between things that only appear to be good and things that are really good.
Both are habits of making the
between something that may be
good, but only in the
really
short run of today, tomorrow, or next week, is
really
good
for us in the long
Aristotle realized that
it
is
run or
for
on
and something
our
hard for those
years or experience to keep their eyes
right choice
life
who
are
immediately present pleasures and pains.
that that
difficult
reminded us that the
whole
is
for those
—
who
difficulty of looking
a difficulty all of us
moral virtue lasting
even
young
in
remote, future goods in
relation to is
that
as a whole.
He knew
are older. But he also
ahead
must overcome
to one's life as a
in trying to acquire
the habit of choosing rightly between goods of
importance and transient pleasures and pains.
Man
Doer
the
105
:
His pointing this out calls our attention to the fact that trying to live well
goal any less desirable to attain. obligation to
make
not easy for any of us. That does not
is
make
the effort.
Nor does
On
relieve us of the
it
the contrary, in Aristotle's
view the satisfaction that comes from having succeeded a
good
effort
or in trying to live one
life
not by
is
raw materials or
is
worth
all
in living
the trouble and
takes.
it
However, a willingness fort
the
itself
know-how
If
made, producing If
what
true of
it
is
individuals
her disposal and
if
he or she has the
skill
well
is
almost entirely within the individual's the fault
fail,
making
ef-
an individual has the appropriate
necessary for producing something that
power. is
enough.
at his or
and make the
to take the trouble
work of
a
art
is
is
Unfortunately,
theirs.
not true of living a good
life.
Success in that venture
can
without being
fail
is
not entirely within our power.
at fault.
We
can
fail
even
if
moral virtue that Aristotle thought was requisite
Good
we have
The
reason
why
the
for success.
habits of choice are requisite for success, but having
does not guarantee
We
them
it.
this
so
is
is
that all the real goods
we should
seek to possess in order to live well are not entirely within our
power
to obtain.
Some, such
acter (the intellectual
as
good habits of mind and char-
and the moral
virtues) are
much more
within our power to possess than others, such as wealth and health, or even freedom
edge and
skill
and friendship. Even acquiring knowl-
or forming
good habits of choice may depend on
having helpful parents and teachers, which
is
beyond our own
control.
We
are not able to control the conditions
born and brought up.
Much
that
happens
choice on our part.
We to us
under which we are
cannot make fortune smile upon
us.
happens by chance rather than by
io6
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
Effort
on our
does the care
we
part does not assure us that
we need
possession of the external goods
we
come
will
to live a
take of our bodies assure us that
good
we
into
Nor
life.
will retain
our health and vigor. Poverty and disabling disease and even the loss
of freedom and of friends can be our
on our
virtuous conduct
Moral
however important
virtue,
lot in spite
of the most
part.
it is
for living a
good
life,
is
ndt enough because chance as well as choice plays a role in the
Good luck goods we come
pursuit of happiness.
Some
of the real
fortune,
though making
a
makes mortal
as necessary as
good
habits.
to possess are largely the gift of
good use of them
depends on our having good still
is
after
we have them
habits. That, in Aristotle's view,
virtue the controlling factor in living a
good
life.
In addition, having good habits enables a person to bear up
under misfortunes. chance, we can fall
If
we cannot
at least take
Moral
for the things of
which we
virtue helps us in both
turns of fortune Aristotle
ing a good
—
sums life
other
is
ways
to deal
all this
up when he
One
make
right choices
that are not really
tune supplies us with to obtain
good
our success in
is
liv-
having the moral
from day
to day.
being blessed by good luck or good fortune. As
moral virtue prevents us from aiming
A
with the twists and
says that
depends on two things.
and choosing things power
try to
are deprived by misfortune.
good and bad.
virtue that enables us to
The
good fortune; and we can
into our lap as a result of
make up
control what happens to us by
advantage of the good things that
life, it
real
in the
good
wrong direction
for us, so
good
for-
goods that are not entirely within our
by choice. has been said,
is
one
in
which
a person has ev-
erything that he or she desires, provided that he or she desires
nothing amiss. In order to desire nothing amiss, one must have
Man
—
the goods bestowed
dition to the goods acquired by
Among
brought up, and
we
live
our
beyond the luck, in ad-
good habits of choice.
which we
society' in
never
lives. Aristotle
depend on the
in a
good society are
good climate and having good
ing in a
as
are born,
us forget that
lets
are social animals as well as physical organisms.
good family and living
loj
lie
these goods of fortune are things that
environment and on the
physical
:
on us by good
moral virtue. But one must also have goods that reach of choice
Doer
the
Having
important as
a
liv-
good water, and
air,
other physical resources available.
Up
to this point,
happiness as
if it
we have been
were a
considering the pursuit of
solitary affair
—
as if
it
were something
each of us could do by himself or herself alone, with no thought
That
of others.
do in order
to
is
hardly the
way
to live well
with others.
what others can and should do good
we cannot
to
We
must
also think of
help us in our effort to lead a
life.
The life it
things are. Since
complete solitude, we must think of what we have
live well in
pursuit of happiness
aims
anybody
at directly
else.
is
is
one's
selfish to the extent that the
own good
not the good
life,
good life
of
But when we realize that we cannot succeed in
the pursuit of happiness without considering the happiness of others,
our
self-interest
tirely selfish
That
is
virtue that
becomes enlightened.
cannot be en-
and succeed.
why, according
we have
to Aristotle, the
two aspects of moral
so far considered are not enough. In addition
temperance and courage, there
to
We
is
justice. Justice
is
concerned
with the good of others, not only of our friends or those
we
love, but of everyone else. Justice
good of the all-enveloping society
we
in
is
also
whom
concerned with the
which we
live
—the
society
call the state.
Living in a good society contributes greatly to the individual's
io8
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
pursuit of his
own
happiness because a good society
deals justly with the individuals
who
are
one
is
members.
that
It
also
requires the individual to deal justly with other individuals
and
to act for the
which
all
the
Persons selves
good of society
members of
who
as a whole.
its
That good
is
a
good
are not temperate
and courageous injure them-
by habitually making the wrong choices. Persons
habitually
make
wrong choices
the
jure others as well as the society in for this
is
that those
in
society participate.
who
firmly
will also
be unjust and in-
which they
aim
who
live.
at a really
The
good
reason life
for
themselves will regularly make choices that carry out that aim.
Choices so directed others
and
will also
aim
directly at a really
at the welfare of the society in
good
life for
which others share
as
well as themselves.
who wants more wealth than is really good for him; or the person who overindulges his appetite for bodily pleasures; or the person who craves someConsider, for example, the person
thing that
human
is
not really good for anyone
beings in order to dominate their
will certainly ruin their
own
lives.
It
that they will injure others as a result of rection.
But persons
who aim
their
own
tion cannot help benefitting others
they
live.
is
—power lives.
over other
Such persons
also highly probable
aiming
in the
wrong
di-
lives in the right direc-
and the
society in
which
14
What
Others Have
a
Right to Expect
from Us
Aristotle said
two things that seem
to
me uncommonly
wise
human being to another. Once undercommon sense. men were friends, justice would not be necthat justice is the bond of men in states.
about the relation of one stood, they are also
He
said that if all
essary.
He
also said
we are led to conclude that members of a state (which is the largest organized society to which we belong) are not all friends with one .another. If they were, they would not need to be bound together by justice to Putting the two remarks together,
the
form the society that we
Most of group.
We
us belong to are
dren or as both.
call a state.
more than one
members of
We may
society or organized
a family, either as parents or chil-
also
belong to other organized groups,
such as a school, a club, a business organization of one
who have combined pose.
with one another for
sort or
human beings some common pur-
another. All these are societies or associations of
110
Everybody
Aristotle for
;
The purpose
of the association distinguishes two of these
organized groups from
all
the
Associations such as schools,
rest.
universities, hospitals, business organizations,
some ample, aim at at serving
and clubs
all
aim
particular good. Educational institutions, for ex-
the dissemination and advancement of knowl-
edge; hospitals, at the care of health; business organizations, at
the production or distribution of things to be bought and sold;
and so on. In contrast, the family
of
ing
and improving
its
tages to be derived
human
a society that
is
members, and the
life
that
state
life.
from
is
aims
aims
at enrich-
no additional advan-
there were
If
at sustaining the
a society that
living in states, Aristotle thinks that
beings would have been content to continue living in
the smaller society of the family or in the slightly larger society
formed by a group of
What
tribe.
tribes into
led
men
something
families,
like
group families into
to
what we
tribes
call a
and group
larger societies was, in Aristotle's view, the ad-
still
vantages to be gained from the larger and
more
inclusive associ-
ations.
As we have seen, our aim merely alive,
tary
to stay alive
of course,
is
but to
as
human
live well
—
beings should be not
as well as possible. Staying
indispensable to living well.
but social animals,
human
Not being
soli-
beings must associate with one
another in order to sustain and preserve their
lives
and
to bring
into the world another generation that must be cared for and
protected during infancy.
The
family and the tribe, according to Aristotle, are the asso-
ciations or societies that originally
these purposes.
same
What first
They may
came
into being to serve
not do so any longer, or not to the
extent, but Aristotle asks us to think about their origin.
caused
place?
human
beings to form these associations in the
Man
One answer
that
may
suggest itself
the
Doer
"instinct."
is
iii
:
Instinct
causes bees to form beehives and ants to form ant colonies or ant
mounds. Perhaps, then, and
lies, tribes,
states. If so,
in contrast to
natural,
business organizations. stinct.
Men
it is
a
human
latter are
as schools,
clubs, or
hardly the products of in-
join together voluntarily to
for the particular
form fami-
would be completely
these societies
such associations
The
instinct to
form these associations
purposes they serve.
In Aristotle's view, families, tribes,
and
no more the
states are
products of instinct than are schools, clubs, and business organizations.
They
are not like beehives
and ant mounds, which
for
a given species of bee or ant are always organized in exactly the
same way, generation
after generation,
that particular species of bee or ant.
beings belong to the
species,
we
and organization
terns of association
and
same
in
and wherever you But though
human
all
find quite different pat-
human
families, tribes,
states.
That, according to Aristotle, were,
in
origin,
voluntarily
indicates
that these
involved thought schools, clubs,
up
for themselves.
tribes,
and
To
and thoughtfully
states are also
human
that
and
beings
they are like
this extent,
and business organizations
voluntarily, purposefully,
societies
and purposefully formed,
formed with some plan of organization that the
lies,
find
human
institute.
beings
But fami-
unlike schools, clubs, and busi-
ness organizations because they are natural as well as voluntary.
Does not tribes,
and
Aristotle contradict himself states are
both voluntary and natural?
contradicting himself states
by saying that families,
if
He would be
he thought that families,
tribes,
and
were natural in the same way that beehives and ant
mounds
are natural
Aristotle, there
is
—the product of
instinct. But,
according to
another way in which a society can be natu-
112
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
ral. It
can be natural in the sense that
some
natural need
—
it
must be formed
to serve
the need to stay alive or the need to live
well.
A
society can be natural in this sense
and thoughtfully formed
purposefully,
makes the
and
—
also be voluntarily,
to serve the
need that
society natural.
Families, according the Aristotle, originated from the need of
human
beings to stay alive and to protect and rear their young.
Groups of
families, or tribes, being a
little
and involving
larger
more human beings working together, came into being in order same need a little more effectively. The even-larger organization of the state, which originally grew out of combina-
to serve that
and
tions of families
more
effectively but also served the additional
abling
some
individuals,
secure, attention
and making
When he
is
it
and
more than There
ants, wolves that
men
But only
That animal.
is
is
man
is
life
by nature a political animal,
meant by the statement
in packs,
and
that
man
is
a
and
lions that live in families.
establish laws or
customs that
differ
from
society to another.
is
a
live well,
that
man
is
a political
custom-making and law-making animal. There
When
ture a political animal, he
selves,
improving
to
organize their societies voluntarily, purposefully,
another meaning.
not
purpose of en-
better.
one meaning of the statement
He
still
to live well. Life itself being
are other social animals, such as bees
hunt
and thoughtfully and one human
all,
could be turned
effort
and
richer
not
if
Aristotle says that
saying
social animal.
is
not only served that same need
tribes,
man is by nahuman beings can-
Aristotle declares that
is
also saying that
cannot achieve the best kind of
li\'es
by living together only in families and in
that, Aristotle thinks they
The Greek word
must
for
tribes.
them-
To do
live together in cities or states.
for a city or state
is
"polis,"
from which we
Man word "poHtical." The Latin word
get the English state
is
from which we
"civis,"
"civilized."
Being
let
The good
friends with
societies
—
justice
is
"civil"
and
in states to
civil or civilized life.
which
seldom
that
ever
if
them
necessary to bind in
this
would not be
justice
state are
and harmoniously
largest
of
all
the state.
moment, suppose
Let us, for the
are all friends with
ily
were friends,
one another,
together peacefully
human
men
If all
Since the members of a
necessary.
the
life is
113
:
for a city or
EngHsh words men must live
us retum to the two statements with
chapter began.
all
by nature,
political
live as well as possible.
Now
get the
Doer
the
one another
members
that the
—
of a fam-
friends in the highest sense
of that word.
When
two
human
beings are friends in this highest sense,
they love each other. Their love impels each of the good of the other
ever
may
—
to
Each, out of such friendship or love,
to injure the other
to
wish
for
wish to benefit the other, to do what-
be necessary to improve or enrich the
happiness or good
them
of the other.
life
will act to
promote the
of the other. Neither would do anything
life
by impeding or obstructing the other's pur-
suit of happiness.
That
is
why
justice
would be unnecessary
which the parents loved
their children, in
in a family
in
which the children
loved their parents, and in which husband and wife, brothers
and
sisters,
loved one another perfectly and at
all
times. But in
most families there are times when love or friendship falls
short of perfection.
say to another,
ask
is
'Tou
unjust," or
''I
Then one member
are not being fair to
have a right
fails
of the family
or
may
me," or "What you
to expect this or that
from
you."
At such moments, love ceases to be the thing that binds the
— 114
'
Everybody
Aristotle for
members
of the family together, and justice enters the picture
justice that tries to see that the individual obtains
has a right to expect, that the individual the others, and that he or she
is
is
being
what he or she fairly treated
by
harmed
or
protected from being
injured by them.
did not intervene
If justice
members of
perfection, the
when
love failed or
short of
fell
the family might not stay together,
or at least they would not live together peacefully and harmoniously, trying to share in the
them
What
all.
which the members ship or love.
men
enjoyment of goods
has just been said
Where
are, for the
love
is
most
is
common
even truer of
part,
absent, justice
states
not related by friend-
must
step in to bind
together in states, so that they can live peacefully and har-
moniously with one another, acting and working together
common Of
—
ship
for a
purpose.
Aristotle ship.
to
in
knew
these,
that there are several different kinds of friend-
he thought that only one was perfect friend-
the kind that exists between persons
who
love
one an-
other and wish only to benefit the other. Aristotle
frequently,
also
knew
we speak
that
such friendships are
rare.
More
of another person as being a friend because
we get some pleasure from him. Such friendships are selfish. The person we call a friend serves some interest of our own, and we regard him or her as a friend he
is
useful to us or because
only so long as that remains the case. In contrast, true friendship or love
is
unselfish.
It is
benevolent.
It
aims
at serving the
good of the other. Justice, like love,
is
concerned with the good of the other per-
between them. Anyone
son.
However, there
who
understands love knows that one individual should never
is
a clear difference
say to another, "I have a right to be loved.
me.
You ought
to love
Man
When we
the
we
them of
give to
:
115
someone, we do not give the person
truly love
loved what he or she has a right to claim from us. trary,
Doer
and
ourselves generously
without any regard to their
rights.
We
do
On
the con-
unselfishly,
them more than
for
they have any right to expect.
We
sometimes even love persons who do not love us
We
turn.
do not make
their returning
our loving them. But when we act
them what they have tent that
we want
our love a condition
justly
from them
for
toward others, giving
we
a right to expect,
justice
in re-
are selfish to the ex-
in return.
To
say that
we
should do unto others what we would have them do unto us
is
selfish in this sense.
What do
others have a right to expect
the promises
whenever
we make
telling a lie
from us? That we keep
them. That we
to
would hurt them
in
tell them the tenth some way. That we
we have borrowed and promised to return. That That we do not steal what belongs to them. That we do not injure their health, damage their bodies, or kill them. That we do not interfere with their freedom of action when their conduct in no way injures us. That we do not make false statements that would injure their reputation or give them a bad name. All these things, and more of the same sort, can be summed up by saying that others have a right to expect from us that we return anything
we pay our
debts to them.
do nothing that might impede or obstruct piness
— nothing
that
might
their pursuit of hap-
interfere with or prevent their ob-
taining or possessing the real goods they need to
need
for themselves.
It
them
them, and
a right to
obliged to respect
We
may
is
—
if
their
we
not always be
it
is
for these real
their right to
ourselves are just, at least
make good
lives
goods that gives
them
that
we
are
just.
not perfectly
just.
Some
ii6
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
persons are the very opposite of
just.
Instead of having the habit
of respecting the rights of others, they are habitually inclined in the opposite direction
even when
—
to get things they
want
for
themselves
do so they must run roughshod over the
to
rights of
others.
That
is
why
made
laws are
to prescribe
what the members of
should or should not do in order to deal
a state
another.
everyone had the habit of being
If
dealings with others, there would be for their
enforcement by the
perfectly just,
no need
with one
justly
in
just
for
all
his
such laws or
But since few individuals are
state.
and since some are habitually inclined
to
be un-
laws that prescribe just conduct must be enforced by the
just,
state to
prevent one individual from seriously injuring another
by violating his or her
Do them
rights.
others have a right to expect us to act positively to help in their pursuit of happiness?
Not
interfering with,
imped-
or obstructing their efforts to obtain or possess the real
ing,
one
goods they need
is
goods
Have they
is
another.
According
thing.
to Aristotle's
tween love and
justice, the
Helping them
to obtain
such
a right to claim our help?
understanding of the difference be-
answer
is
no.
It is
love, not the obligations of justice, that impels
the generosity of
one individual
to
help another to obtain or possess the real goods needed for a
good
life.
That
is
why
the laws that the state enforces do not
require individuals to help one another by taking positive action to
promote the pursuit of happiness by However, the
state
does
others.
make and enforce
laws that require
the individual to act positively for the welfare of the as a
whole.
The
happiness by the
common
its
welfare of the
members.
A
community good
good of the people
is
community
affects the pursuit of
society, a society in
which
served and advanced, con-
Man tributes to the
many words
good
life
that the
of
its
Doer
iij
:
individuals. Aristotle says in so
end that the good
happiness of the individuals
the
state
who compose
it.
should serve It
is
the
should promote
their pursuit of happiness.
to
When,
therefore, we, as individuals, obey laws that direct us
behave
for the welfare of the
indirectly helping to
fellow
human
beings.
of our love for them,
community
as a
What we do we do
directly for a few others out
indirectly for all the rest by obeying
laws that require us to act for the welfare of the
which
whole, we are
promote the pursuit of happiness by our
they, as well as we, live.
community
in
15
What We Have a
Right to
Expect from Others and
from the State
Love thy neighbor as
Do
unto others as you would have them do unto you!
Both of these familiar maxims pear to
thyself!
make
relate yourself to others.
Both ap-
yourself the pivot of your action toward others.
Love yourself and love your neighbor
in
the
same way and
even, perhaps, in the same measure as you love yourself. Think of
how you
wish others to behave toward you and behave in the
same way toward them.
We
seem
to
have reversed that order by considering
first,
in
the preceding chapter, what others have a right to expect from us and now, in this chapter,
from others.
It
what we have
would be more accurate
above an order that puts us Rights are rights.
If
first
any one
a right to expect
to say that
we have
risen
and others second.
human
being has them, based
Man upon needs
human
common
that he or she shares in
beings, then
the others have the
all
makes no difference whether you think or
own
and your action
choices,
under an obligation to obtain
and
other
rights
Justice, as
is
a
First
The
ul-
your practical thinking, your
all
good
for yourself.
life
to live as well as
is
it
humanly
You
are
possible to
possess, in the course of a lifetime, all the
things that are really
good
we have
positive action
first.
about what you should do.
in the order of thinking
for you.
seen, does not require
on your
you
to
promote, by
part, the
happiness of others, as you are
own by
the love you bear yourself. Jus-
required to pursue your tice
iig
rights, too. It
of your
which you do come
a sense in
is
timate goal that should control
—
all
:
of the rights of others.
first
However, there
do
with
same
first
Doer
the
only requires you not to impede or frustrate others in their
pursuit of happiness.
you do
pursuit,
Your
rights
you go beyond
If
so because
and the
that to help
you love them
as
them
you love
with which
rights of others,
in their
yourself. justice
is
concerned, are based on the things that are really good for any
human ture.
being because they
Thinking about what
really good,
fulfill is
that having a certain
ing a satisfactory degree of health,
as
really
amount
if
of wealth, hav-
and having freedom
not only as
a right to expect
what they have
means
to living
good
that
is
for
you
is
from others
a right to expect
same because everyone's
And
For example,
rights.
is
are really
but also as
to living well.
What you have same
na-
you, you would not be led to say that everyone has a
for
right to these things,
means
human
good, and especially about what
must precede thinking about
you did not think good
needs inherent in
rights are the
really
good
is,
from you. Rights are the
same and because what
for every other
so because all of us are
therefore, the
human,
all
human
is
being.
of us have the
120
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
k
same human nature, inherent damental needs calling
which
in
same fun-
the
are
for fulfillment.
Among those needs is the need to live in association with other human beings. We are not the kind of animal that can go alone. As we have seen, human societies families, tribes,
—
it
and
states
—have
vation of
which
life
arisen to
needs
to fulfill other
itself
Although society
life
fails to
of
it
good
if
way
the
organized or the way
is
in their efforts to acquire for
may
it
not
operates either
who
members
are
and possess things
that are really
them.
For example,
a family it
is
not a good family
if it
should. This does not
good because right to expect
it
It
that the family itself
means only
does not do for
from
if it
does not
does not help them to grow up as they
mean
young children cannot preserve
without families.
does not give
if it
the freedom they have a right to,
care for their health,
their
own
a
is
lives
bad thing,
and grow up
that a particular family its
is
not
children what they have a
it.
In his concern with
what
is
good and bad,
cerned with good and bad societies
human
to live in as-
beings, a particular society
help or positively hinders individuals
the children in
for
good because we need
human it
higher goods on
for
depends.
itself
is
sociation with other
be good
goods on which the preser-
for
depends and our need
good
living a
need. But they also help us
fulfill this
—our need
as well as
beings and with their good and bad
ready been said about society
itself
simple common-sense observation.
Aristotle
con-
with good and bad lives.
being good
We
is
What is,
for
has
al-
him, a
cannot get along
at all
without living in society.
Beginning there, Aristotle then goes on
makes
a particular society
other.
And
just as his
good or one
to
consider what
society better
ultimate question about
than an-
human
life
is
Man about the best
life
tion about society
can
that each of us
Doer
:
121
ultimate ques-
live, so his
about the best society in
is
the
which we can
live
and pursue happiness. Since Aristotle thinks that, of or political society,
good or
It
good
state
one that
that a
Human
and harmoniously
It
his answers to ques-
state
obvious as
it is
state
is
gov-
to say that a
cannot
exist
beings cannot live together peace-
if all
human
government.
beings were friends and
might not even be true
perfectly just, so that there
one that
is
For him, a
in the absence of
That might not be tme loved one another.
just
on
best state.
good as
is
lived well.
is
without govemment. fully
and the
him
to
well. That, for Aristotle, life is
societies, the state,
the one that most enables us to live the
is
seems obvious
emed
human
civilized life, let us concentrate
about the good
tions
all
was no need
humans were
if all
enforcement of
for the
laws to prevent one individual from injuring another. But
knew from common experience that bound together by love or friendship,
human
beings
most
human
Aristotle
all
are not
that
beings are not perfectly
just,
and
that
some
are quite unjust in
their selfishness.
That
ment
is
is
why
his
common-sense conclusion was
that govern-
necessary for the existence of a state or a political soci-
ety.
Being necessary, government self,
itself is
good, just as society
it-
is good. However, as we have seen, a parmay be bad or not as good as it should be. So, particular form of govemment may be bad or not as good
being necessary,
ticular society
too, a as
it
should be.
It
has been said, by
that
government
human were
is
—being
beings
—cannot
common
live
some who
lack Aristotle's
not necessary at
all.
as they are, not as
They
common fail
sense,
to see that
one might wish they
together peacefully and act together for a
purpose without living under a government having the
122
Aristotle for
:
power
Everybody
to enforce laws
and
to
make
decisions.
criminals must be restrained. In order that a uals
may
act together for a
some machinery
for
common
It is
not only that
number
of individ-
purpose, there must also be
making the decisions
that their concerted
actions require. It
has also been said that, although government
essary,
a necessary evil
it is
because
may be
it
and be-
cive force (the force used in the enforcement of laws)
cause
it
Those who Aristotle
say this
on the
According
understand very important points that
liberty of individuals in a society.
to Aristotle, the
—obeys
just
fears the
to
fail
the freedom of the individual.
makes about the enforcement of laws and about the
limitations
is
on
involves limitations
just laws
punishment
untarily, not
good
man
because he
it is
man who
virtuous, not because he
is
keeps the peace vol-
him government
is
not
is
not an
bad man.
the good
He
law
his breaking the
under the coercion of law enforcement. He
for the
government.
the virtuous
may follow from He obeys laws and
coerced by government, and so for
Nor does
—
that
or disturbing the peace.
evil as
nec-
involves the use of coer-
man
feel that his
freedom
is
limited by
does not want more freedom than he can use
without injuring others. Only the bad than that, and so only he
man
feels that his
pleases, without regard for others,
is
wants more freedom
freedom
to
do
as
he
limited by government.
The fact that government itself is necessary and good does not make all forms of government good, or as good as they should be.
For
Aristotle, the line that divides
government
is
good from bad forms of
determined by the answers to the following ques-
tions. First,
does the government serve the
who are governed, or who wield the power
common
does
those
of government?
it
good of the
serve the selfish interests of
people
Government
that
a
Man serves the self-interest of the rulers
ment
that
promotes the good
life
Second, does the government disposal of the rulers, or does in a
way
might or
whether
force,
disposed
is
than
rather
must have authority
Government
who
making of
on
man
or
more
benevolent or well-
is
To
tyrannical.
that those
that
ernment
is
is
be
government
good,
mled acknowledge and
are
fear
and submit
to
way
it is
the only form of
states or political societies.
to a third question.
It
applies to
government
neither tyrannical nor despotic, but constitutional
ruled by laws. constitution
—
—
laws, in
which even those who govern
About such government we have the fundamental law
a just constitution?
government
And
are
to ask: Is the
on which government are the laws
—
itself
made by
that
just laws?
Any government
that
is
not tyrannical
Among
nontyrannical govemments,
ment
better than a despotic one.
is
Aristotle called constitu-
government. By calling such gov-
to suggest that
proper for
government based on
based
in this
political
he meant
political,
This brings us
good
is
government or
government that
is
in the
that rests solely
be in the hands of one it
at the
have been made
fear.
tional
that
that
power or force that they
accept, not merely
from
it
even when
despotic,
good.
merely on the power
on laws
Government
a part?
is
12^
:
Only govern-
tyrannical.
which the ruled have agreed and
to
which they have had than one,
rest
rest
it
is
of the ruled
Doer
the
governments, the best
is
a
is
to that extent
good.
constitutional govern-
And, among constitutional
the one with a just constitution and
with just laws. In praising constitutional government, Aristotle speaks of
the government of free that
men and
equals.
He
also speaks of
it
as
it
as
form of government in which the citizens rule and are
ruled in turn.
Those who
are ruled by a despot are subjects, not citizens
— 124
•
Aristotle for
Everybody
with some voice in their
own government. Those who
by a tyrant are no better off than ruled as inferiors, not equals. are ruled by other citizens
are ruled
both cases, they are
slaves. In
Only those who, being
whom
citizens,
they have chosen to hold
public office for a time are ruled as equals, and as free
men
should be ruled.
At take.
this point in his thinking, Aristotle
Living
at a
made
a serious mis-
time and in a society in which some
human
beings were born into slavery and treated as slaves, as well as a
women
which
society in
were treated
He
he made the
many human beings had inferior nawho appeared to be inferior
mistake of thinking that tures.
as inferiors,
did not realize that those
appeared to be so as the result of the way in which they were treated, not as a result of inadequate native
Making groups.
the one hand, he placed those
ruled as citizens
—
as free
own government. On fit
human beings into two who were fit to be
he divided
mistake,
this
On
endowments.
and equal and with
a voice in their
the other hand, he placed those
who were
only to be ruled despotically, either as subjects or slaves
without a voice in their
own government and
so as neither free
nor equal.
We cused
live at a
for
time and in a society in which no one can be ex-
making
Aristotle's mistake.
Correcting his mistake,
human beings should be their own government and
are led to the conclusion that all
erned
as citizens
with a voice in
The
be ruled as free and equal. inclusive all are those
who
are
still
thus
only exceptions to that in their infancy or those
we
gov-
all-
who
are mentally disabled.
Reaching tutional
human
this
conclusion
government
is
just
just stated,
only
if
we
its
also see that consti-
constitution gives
all
beings the equal status of citizenship without regard to
Man doing
sex, race, creed, color, or wealth. In
so,
it
the
Doer
also gives
:
125
them
the freedom they have a right to, the freedom of being ruled as citizens,
not as slaves or subjects.
One human
being
is
another, even though one in
many
more nor
neither
may be
less
human
than
superior or inferior to another
other respects as a result of differences in native en-
dowments
or acquired
These
traits.
inequalities should certainly
human
be considered in the selection of some than others to hold public
beings rather
but they should be
office,
totally
disregarded in considering the qualifications for citizenship.
human
All
beings are equal as humans. Being equal as hu-
mans, they are equal in the in their
common human
rights that arise
nature.
A
does not treat equals equally.
Nor
nize the equal right of
freedom
all to
from needs inherent
constitution it
is
just if
—
to
it
is
not just
if it
does not recog-
human
be ruled as
beings should be ruled, as citizens, not as slaves or subjects.
We now have reached one answer to the question about what we have a right to expect from the state in which we live and the government under which we live. We have a right to be ruled as citizens under a government to which we have given our consent and which allows us to have a voice in that govern-
ment. Is
that all
we have
Even though he made some human beings had the
a right to expect?
the mistake of thinking that only
right to be ruled as citizens, Aristotle
beings had a right to expect lived. it
The
thought that those
more from the
best state, in his opinion,
state in
human
which they
was one that did everything
could do to promote the pursuit of happiness by
its
citizens.
That remains true whether only some human beings or
all
should be citizens.
What can
a state
do
to
promote the pursuit of happiness by
its
126
Aristotle for
:
citizens?
It
Everybody
can help them
and possess
to obtain
goods that they need and have a right
to.
To
the real
all
understand
this,
we must remember one point made in the preceding chapter. Of all the real goods we must have in order to live well, some are more and some are less within our individual power to acquire and possess. Some, like moral virtue and knowledge,
depend
largely
on the choices we ourselves make. Some,
like
wealth and health, depend to a considerable extent on our having good luck or
on our being blessed by good
The main ways can help
what
it
its
which
in
good
a
state
and
a
fortune.
good government
individuals in their pursuit of happiness
can to overcome deprivations they suffer
bad luck or misfortune, not
as a result of fault
on
that
The
do the most
The one thing how good it is, is
best state
and the
best
to
their part.
should do for them what they cannot, by choice and for themselves.
is
as a result
effort,
do of It
do
government are those
in this direction.
that to
no
make
state or its
or not they acquire moral virtue
the choices each of
government can do, no matter
Whether depends almost entirely upon
citizens morally virtuous.
them makes. The
government can,
therefore, only give
tions that enable
and encourage them
its
best state
and the
best
citizens external condi-
to try to live well.
not guarantee that, given these conditions, they will
all
It
can-
succeed.
Their success or failure ultimately depends on the use they
make
of the good conditions under which they live their
lives.
pjRj or
MAN THE KNOWER
»k
16
What Goes
into the
Mind and What Comes out of
It
Earlier chapters have dealt with thinking
and with knowing but
mind that thinks and knows. II, we considered productive thinking
not with the
—
In Part
thinking that
is
the kind of
involved in the making of things. There
we
also
—the kind
considered the kind of knowledge needed for making
we
called
In
or
skill
Part
knowledge
III,
know-how.
we examined
—thinking about
and knowledge of what
tion
or right
and wrong
Now,
in Part IV,
for us to
we
will
—with
itself
is
do
good and bad in the
And we
knowing, not
time we
thinks
will coiisider
and knows.
lives.
will
just for the sake
of
be concerned with knowledge
knowledge of the way things are
knowledge of what we ought or ought not first
for us to seek,
conduct of our
be concerned with theoretical think-
ing, thinking for the sake of
production or action.
thinking and practical means and ends of human ac-
practical
the
as well as with
to do.
Here
for the
what we know about the mind
that
i$o
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
Language plays a large part in human thinking and knowing. The words we use, according to Aristotle, express the ideas we think with. The declarative sentences we utter or the statements we make express opinions that we affirm or deny opinions that may be either true or false. When a statement we make happens to be true, it expresses knowledge. If it happens to be false, we have made an error.
—
We
cannot be
about
it
in error
about something and have knowledge
same time. Opinions may be
at the
either true or false,
correct or erroneous, but incorrect, erroneous, or false knowl-
edge
is
as impossible as a
Where do
seemed obvious our minds
—
ence. That turns
first
we somehow
to Aristotle that
that they are
is
round square.
the ideas with which
why
his
account of
to the senses
and
we
think
come
are not born with
fi-om?
It
them
in
the products of our experi-
human
thinking and knowing
to the experience that results
from
the functioning of our senses.
The
windows or doorways of the mind. Whatmind from the outside world comes into it through the senses. What comes into it may be words or sentences that other human beings utter. As everyone knows, we ever
senses are the
comes
into the
learn a great deal that way, certainly from the
moment
that our
schooling begins. But learning does not begin with schooling.
Nor does all our learning, even after schooling, involve statements made by others. Taking the human race as a whole, as well as
human
infants in every generation, learning begins with
sense experience before the learners use words to express what
they have learned. In Aristotle's day,
external senses
—
it
sight,
reason Aristotle called
was generally thought that we have hearing, touch, smell, and
them
external senses
is
taste.
five
The
that each involves
a
Man a sense organ
on the surface of our bodies, there
by the outside world: sight results things outside us, hearing from
touch from what outside
acts
on our nose, and
side acts
Knower
to
be acted on
:
131
from the action on our eyes of
what outside
on our
taste
the
acts
skin, smell
on our
ears,
from what out-
from what outside
acts
on our
tongue and mouth.
Modern than
and
five senses
sense organs; for example, the sense organs
by which we sense hunger and organs by which we
the sense
we have more
scientific research has discovered that
thirst
within our
the position of our bodies. But the exact
sense organs does not
own
bodies and
sense the motion of our limbs or
affect the
number
of senses and
account that Aristotle gives of
the contribution that the senses and sense experience
make
to
our thinking and knowing.
Each of the organ
The
is
senses produces sensations only
outside.
its
sense
acted on physically by something in the outside world.
senses are passive receivers that
ceiver.
when
Each of our sense organs
We
cannot
must be is
activated
a highly specialized re-
smell things with our eyes;
taste or
from the
hear or see them with our tongues and noses.
We
we cannot
are aware of
colors through our eyes, of sounds through our ears, of odors
through our nose, and so on.
we can be aware of and shape of bodies we can see
Certain aspects of the world around us
more than one way. The well as feel by touch.
from one place
motion
is
We
size
as
can see and hear the motion of bodies
to another,
slow or
in
and we can even
tell
whether that
fast.
Sensations of the various kinds just mentioned are the raw materials out of
which our sense experience
these raw materials
come
in separately
is
formed.
Though
from outside, through
the channels of different sense organs, they do not remain separate, or isolated
from one another,
in
our sense experience. The
132
;
Everybody
Aristotle for
world we experience through our senses
a
is
various sizes and shapes, in motion or at
world of bodies of
and
rest,
Our
another in space in a variety of ways.
related to
one
experience of this
—the
world of bodies also includes a wide variety of qualities colors bodies have, the sounds they
make, the roughness or the
smoothness of their surfaces, and so on. According
to Aristotle,
perception on our part.
our sense experience
The
sensations
we
is
the product of
receive passively
through our sense organs are merely the raw materials that we
somehow put
together to constitute the seamless fabric of our
sense experience. In that putting together,
we
are
more
active
than passive. Sensation that arises
is
input from the outside. But the sense experience
from our perception of that outside world involves
composed of many
memory and
imagination on our
elements,
having their origin in what our various senses take
all
part. It
is
but transformed by the way they are put together to make up
in,
the whole that
If
we
see at
is
the world
we
perceive.
describe any typical perceptual experience in words,
once that there
is
much more
to
it
we
than the raw materials
of sensation. For example, you perceive a big, black, barking
dog chasing a
tiger-striped,
cat runs in front of a blue halt. In that description
name ear
halt
the colors and the sounds.
a street, chasing, running, ^all
the street, and the
sudden
A dog and a cat, an automobile and suddenly slowing down to a more than
sen-
from outside.
you perceive an object
when you
to a
sensed by the eye and the
these things that you perceive involve
sations received
When
down
of a sense experience, only a few words
visible or audible qualities
— —
and
yellow cat
automobile that screeches
that
you
call a
dog or
a cat, or
perceive actions that you call chasing or running.
Man your
memory and your imagination
the dog you perceive miliar animal that
is
is
of the kind of animal that a cat
is,
You have some understanding cated by your
fast
things,
If
if
a fa-
from dogs.
different in kind
of what tigers are
like, as indi-
perception of the cat as tiger striped.
and slowing down.
is
understanding
You
stand the difference between walking and running,
going
133
before. In addition,
You have some
involved.
:
are involved, especially
a stranger to you, while the cat
you have seen around
your understanding
Knower
the
you did not understand
under-
between all
these
you could not have had the perceptual experience that
was described. According
to Aristotle, these various
have result from the of our senses.
activity
understandings that
we
of our mind, not from the activity
Our mind forms
ideas of cats
and dogs, of run-
ning and chasing. Ideas are based on the information that our senses receive from the outside world, but the ideas themselves
from the outside world. They
are not received Aristotle, the
product of the mind's activity in
stand the world Just as
we experience through our
we can
sensed, so
if
its
according to
effort to
under-
senses.
sense things because they are capable of being
we can understand
standable. If the barking dog visible
are,
things because they are under-
and the screeching car were not
and audible, we could not see and hear them. Similarly,
the dog and the cat were not understandable as different kinds
of things, tures.
In
we could not understand them Aristotle's view, we apprehend
as
having different na-
the natures of cats or
dogs by our idea or understanding of what a cat is,
just as
we apprehend
is
or
what
a
dog
the blackness of the dog or the blueness
of the automobile by the visual sensations received by our eyes.
When mind an
a carpenter sets out to
make
a chair, he
idea of the chair he wants to make.
must have
He must
in
not only
have an idea of chairs in general but also the more definite idea
134
•
Aristotle for
Everybody
of the particular chair he wishes to make. Working with these
and with pieces of wood
ideas
shapes those pieces of
wood and
become
them
puts
The
they take on the form of a chair.
productive worker has
raw material, the carpenter
as his
together so that
idea in the
mind of
the
the form of the material he works
on.
Living matter having a certain form
having a different form
When
a dog.
is
Living matter
a cat.
is
children learn to distin-
guish between cats and dogs and to recognize each see
when
they
and dogs involves some under-
their perception of cats
it,
standing of the special nature of each of these two kinds of
animals. That understanding consists in their having an idea of
what a
cat
is
and an idea of what
a
dog
is.
In Aristotle's view, having the idea of a cat in one's
mind
the form that
each cat the kind of animal as the
hand
is
to all cats
This leads him
mind
way of saying the same thing where the forms
is
having
and makes
which we use
the form of forms. Another
mind as the place become our ideas of them.
describes the
that are in things
The mind forms
to
to say that, just
the tool of tools (the instrument by
other instruments), so the
separating
common
is
it is.
amounts
ideas by taking the forms of things
them from the matter of
things.
and
Producing ideas
we
the very opposite of producing things. In producing things,
put the ideas that
forming matter ideas,
in
our minds into things by trans-
accordance with our
ideas.
In
producing
our minds take the forms out of things and turn them
into ideas
have
in
we have
is
whereby we understand the nature of the things
this or that
that
form.
Getting or producing ideas should also be contrasted with eating things.
When we
eat
matter into our bodies.
an apple, we take both
The form without
its
form and
the matter
its
would not
1
Man
the
Knower
:
135
The matter without the form would not be an apple. But when we get the idea of an apple, we take the form away from the matter of the apple. The action of our mind in nourish
us.
doing so turns the form of an apple into an idea of the kind of
an apple
fruit
The
is.
ideas or understandings so far
we
derstandings of objects that
mentioned are ideas or un-
They
perceive.
are the kind of
They are also we can remember when they are absent. They are even the kind of objects that we can imagine, as we might imagine a cat or dog that we have never perceived, or objects that are present in our sense experience.
the kind of objects
dream of one
that
is
strangely shaped or colored.
But when the mind sense experience,
it
producing ideas on the basis of
starts
does not stop with ideas that enable us to
understand objects we can perceive, remember, and imagine.
We
can understand
perceive, such as justice.
We
many
objects of thought that
good and bad,
right
we cannot
and wrong, freedom and
could not have discussed these objects in earlier
chapters of this book
if
we
did not understand
them
—
if
we had
not formed ideas of them.
Thinking begins with the formation of ideas on the
basis of
the information received by our senses. Sensations are the input
the the
mind receives from mind produces as a
Thinking goes
them other.
the outside world. Ideas are the output result
further.
It
of what
receives.
relates the ideas
together, separates them,
By these
it
and
sets
it
produces.
It
joins
one idea against an-
further activities of thinking, the
mind produces
knowledge, not only knowledge about objects we can perceive,
remember, or imagine, but not
fall
also
knowledge of objects that do
within our sense experience. Arithmetic, algebra, and
geometry are good examples of such knowledge.
1^6
Aristotle for
:
A
sensation
when you
Everybody
is
neither true nor
the sensation
when your
itself
is
when
in
it
is
The
error
is
in
is
not
you think
false;
that
but
we can
objects
it
on the
if,
would as
it
basis of
you may be
black,
it is
in
your thinking, not in your sensing.
and almost every adjective and verb
our language names an object of thought
we have formed an
think about because
dog, for ex-
not black. Your sensing
as gray,
common noun
Every
The
shadows. In bright sunlight,
shadows
in
that information alone, error.
as
it,
senses deceive you, as they often do,
neither true nor false.
may have been
have been seen by you black
simply have
sense the blackness of a dog or the blueness of an au-
tomobile. Even
ample,
You
false.
think about are objects
remember, or imagine. Dogs and
—an
object
idea of
we can
it.
Not
in
we can all
the
also perceive,
example, are objects
cats, for
we can perceive, but we can also think about them when no dogs and cats around for us to perceive through our senses. In addition, we can think about the very small particles that
there are
atom although our
of matter inside the
senses are unable to per-
ceive anything so small, even with the help of the most powerful
microscope. Like sensations, ideas are neither true nor
were talking or the single
to
one another, and
word
''cat,"
I
you would not be able
saying either yes or no. Let us assume for the
and
I
had the same understanding of these
meant
for
also
meant
for you,
same
ideas.
When
me, they
they expressed the
suppose that
when
I
said "cat,"
the direction of an animal in the that very
room
My
uttering the
to
you and
I
respond by
for
said "dog,"
when I
I
each of us
you and
I
said "cat."
nodded or pointed
in
that started to bark at
moment. You would immediately
a cat, that's a dog."
If
moment that you words. What they
because
I
thought about the same object. So, too,
Now
false.
spoke the single word "dog"
say,
"No,
that
is
not
word "cat" while nodding
Man or pointing to
the
Knower
:
137
an animal that both of us were perceiving could
have been spelled out in a sentence: "That animal over there a cat."
Your saying no could
ing, "If
you think
than
we can be
shadows assertion,
That
thinking of cats or dogs any
more
made
cannot be in error in error
as black rather
just
have been spelled out by sayin error.
that animal
statement you have just
We
also
a cat,
is is
you are
false."
when we is
dog standing
see the
than gray. Only
such as "That dog
black," does the question arise is
must enter
and along with
into our thinking,
When
"is"
and
"is
have passed from the level of
in the
when we make some
whether what we say or think
word, "not."
is
true or false.
That word it
goes another
not" enter into our thinking, just
"is"
we
having ideas to the level of
combining and separating them. Then we have reached the level
where we are forming opinions that can be either true or
false.
There are other words, such
as
"and," "if" and "then,"
"since" and "therefore," "either, or," "not both," that enter our
thinking at a
still
higher level of thought. This
which making one statement reject
another as
is
the level at
leads us to affirm another or to
false.
among these three levels of thought in his account of how the mind operates to produce knowledge. From the raw materials of sense experience, the mind forms ideas. Ideas in turn are the raw materials out of which the mind Aristotle distinguishes
forms judgments in which something
is
affirmed or denied. As
single ideas are expressed in speech by single
so judgments are expressed by sentences in
which the words
words or phrases,
—
declarative sentences
"is" or "is not" occur.
The third level Aristotle calls reasoning or inference. Only when one statement becomes the basis for asserting or denying
1^8
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
another statement does the mind
move up
to the third level of
thought. At this level, thinking involves giving reasons for what
we
At
think.
true or false,
He
it
may
what we think may not only be
also
be either logical or
wrote the
first
book on the
many
the standard textbook for
subject, a
his basic rules for
book that was
centuries and that
considerable influence. In the next chapter,
some of
either
illogical.
was a great logician. He founded the science of
Aristotle logic.
this level,
we
still
exerts
shall consider
conducting our thinking in a logical
manner. Although does
not
logical thinking
always
pointed out that
reach
it is
Hence cal or
for
logical
better than illogical thinking,
conclusions that are
possible for the
are true without reaching
possible
is
them
mind
result
Aristotle
to hold opinions that
in a logical
thinking to
true.
it
manner, even
in
as
it is
false conclusions.
we pay some attention to what makes thinking logiillogical, we shall have to consider what makes thinking after
true or false.
17
Wbrds
Logic's Little
As Newton's name Aristotle's stein's
is
name
is
associated with the law of gravitation, so
As Ein-
associated with the law of contradiction. is
to the theory of relativity, so Aristotle's
theory of the syllogism. contradiction:
''is"
and
Two
to the theory of the syllogism
incorrect reasoning.
words
not."
''is
They
—
are
lie at
Two
to the
the heart of the law of
pairs of
Aristotle's
is
words are central
account of correct and
"if and "then," "since" and
"therefore."
As a rule of thought, the law of contradiction marily what not to do. that
commands
our speech or
in
It
is
a
tells
us pri-
law against contradiction, a law
us to avoid contradicting ourselves, either in
our thought.
It tells
us that
we should not an-
swer a question by saying both yes and no. Stated in another
way,
it
tells
us that
proposition. If
I
we should not
affirm
say or think that Plato
was
and deny the same Aristotle's teacher,
I
should avoid saying or thinking that Plato was not Aristotle's
140
:
Aristotle for
To
teacher.
Everybody
say or think that
would be
to
deny something
that
I
have affirmed.
You may
ask
why
this
sound. Aristotle's answer
rule of thought
and
so basic
is
that the law of contradiction
is
so
not
is
only a rule of thought but also a statement about the world
—about the
self
The law
we
realities
is
immediately obvious to
ever
it
may be
It
think about.
try to
of contradiction, as a statement about reality, says
what time.
it-
—cannot both
either exists or
it
common exist
does not
sense.
and not
A
—what-
thing
exist at the
but not both
exist,
same
once.
at
A
thing cannot have a certain attribute and not have that attribute at the
same time. The apple
my hand
in
that
am
I
looking at
cannot, at this instant, be both red in color and not red in color.
This
is
so very obvious that Aristotle calls the law of contra-
diction self-evident. deniability.
It
and not red that a part
is
at the
is
Its
self-evidence, for him,
means
impossible to think that the apple
same time,
greater than the
just as
whole
it
is
un-
impossible to think
which
to
its
both red
is
it
belongs.
It
is
impossible to think that a tennis ball that you hit over the fence is
to be
found
in the grass that lies
time, to think that
it
beyond and,
at the
cannot be found there because
it
same
no longer
exists.
The law
of contradiction as a statement about reality
underlies the law of contradiction as a rule of thought.
itself
The law
of contradiction as a statement about reality describes the way things are. scribes the
The law of contradiction as way we should think about
thinking about
When true,
them
to
conform
to the
a rule of
thought pre-
things
we wish our
if
way things
are.
a pair of statements are contradictory, both
nor can both be
false.
One
cannot be
must be true, the other
false.
Man
the
Knower
.
141
Plato either was or was not Aristotle's teacher. All swans are
white or some are not. However,
if
instead of saying that
some
swans are not white, which contradicts the statement that
swans are white,
would not have
I
had
said
Aristotle's distinction
is
who
possible for both of these statements
cannot be
—
"No swans are white" true. Some swans may be
is.
it is
Aristotle
dictory, Is
false to say that all
calls
be
to
—
"All swans are
false,
though both
white and some black, in
swans are white or that none
a pair of statements
when both cannot be
not contra-
contrary,
both can be
true, but
there a pair of statements, both of
both of which cannot be
state-
this.
white" and
which case
a contradiction
are not acquainted with
between contradictory and contrary
ments may be surprised by It
no swans are white,
People
resulted.
all
false.
which can be
true, but
according to Aristotle, the
false? Yes,
statement that some swans are white and the statement that some swans are not white can both be true, but both cannot be false. Swans must be either white or not white, and so if only some are white, some must be not white. Aristotle calls this pair of statements subcontrary.
Suppose, however, that instead of saying that some swans are white and some swans are not white, are white"
statements have been subcontrary false?
I
White and black
true that
said
— impossible
No, because some swans might be
or blue.
had
"Some swans
and "Some swans are black." Would that
any
it
both
must be
will not
to
be
gray, or green, yellow,
are not exclusive alternatives.
visible object
This being the case,
for
pair of
It is
not
either white or black.
do
to pose as the contrary of
"All swans are white" the statement "All swans are black," for
neither
may be
true
and both can be
not "All swans are black."
To state the contrary "No swans are white,"
false.
of "All swans are white," one must say
I 142
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
Unlike "black" and ''white," some pairs of terms, which are contrary terms, do exhaust the alternatives. integers or
third possibility. natives,
and
not."
"is
When
one uses terms
odd number
The is
I
it
that are exclusive alter-
statement that any given whole
not odd, and
is
no
number is an number is
contradicted by the statement that that
an even number, because even,
all
is
possible to state a contradiction without using "is"
is
it
For example,
whole numbers are either odd or even. There
it
odd,
if it is
it
is
not even, and
must be one or the
cannot exaggerate the importance of
if it is
other.
Aristotle's rules
con-
cerning statements that are incompatible with one another in
one of these three ways
—through
being contradictory of one
another, through being contrary to one another, or subcontrary to
one another. The importance
that observing these rules not
is
only helps us to avoid making inconsistent statements but also helps us to detect inconsistencies in the statements others
and
When herself or
him and
to challenge
a person
we
what they
made by
say.
are conversing with contradicts himself or
makes contrary statements, we have every
right to stop
"You cannot make both of those statements. Both cannot be true. Which of the two do you really mean? Which say,
do you want It
is
ments
to claim as true?"
particularly
—statements
important to observe that general containing the word "all"
dicted by a single negative instance. ization that all swans are white, single sifies
swan
that
is
To
—can
state-
be contra-
contradict the general-
one needs only
to point to a
not white. That single negative instance
fal-
the generalization.
Scientific generalizations are put to the test in this way.
claim that they are true can be upheld only so long tive instances are
negative instances
found is
to falsify
as
The
no nega-
them. Since the search
an unending one,
a
scientific
for
general-
Man
the
Knower
14^
:
ization can never be regarded as finally or completely verified.
Human
beings are prone to generalize, especially in their
human
thinking about other
beings
in sex, race, or religion. If they are
selves to say
—unthinkingly,
such and such.
who
one hopes and
so. If
they will permit themselves to say that
one can point was
The
permit them-
that all
women
are
all
they are Protestants,
Catholics are this or
every one of these cases, one negative instance suffices
to invalidate the generalization;
ization
—
from themselves
will
they are white persons, they will permit them-
If
selves to say that all blacks are so
that. In
differ
men, they
the easier
to,
in the
first
and the more negative instances
it is
to
show how wild the
general-
place.
use of contrary terms, such as "black" and "white," or
"odd" and "even," brings into play another
set
control our thinking according to certain rules
—
of words that
"either-or"
and
when we toss a coin to decide somewhen it lands, it must be either heads or
"not both." For example, thing,
we know
that
tails,
not both. That
ever,
weak disjunctions,
or that,
the
is
a strong disjunction.
which something may be
in
and perhaps both, though not
same time. To
There
in the
same
are,
how-
either this
respect or at
say of tomatoes that they are either red or
green permits us to say that one and the same tomato can be
both red and green, but Disjunctions,
at different times.
especially
strong
disjunctions,
enable
us
to
make simple, direct inferences. If we know that a whole number is not odd, we can infer immediately that it must be even. Similarly, if we know that a whole number is not a prime number, we can infer immediately that it must be divisible by numbers other than
itself
coin has landed heads up, tails,
have
lost the toss.
and one.
we know
When we at
see that the tossed
once that we, who bet on
We do not have to turn the coin over to be
sure of that.
Inferences of this sort Aristotle calls immediate inferences
144
•
Everybody
Aristotle for
because one goes immediately from the truth or statement to the truth or ing are involved.
If
falsity
one knows
of another. that
it
and
one knows
in addition
that at least
of one
falsity
steps of reason-
true that all swans are
is
white, one also knows immediately that
No
some swans are white; some white objects are
swans.
One
can make mistakes
and mistakes
that all swans are white, jects are
in this
simple process of inference,
made. For example, from the
are frequently
some white ob-
correct to infer that
it is
swans, but quite incorrect to infer that
fact
all
white objects
are swans.
That incorrect inference
The
class of
Swans
are only
is
some of the white
also say that all white objects are
Two
pairs of
well as in the
and
which they
objects in the world.
say, "/fall
are white."
we
all
swans
words are operative
are white
is
to treat the
in
To
we can
two
classes
immediate inference
process of reasoning.
They
are
as
''if"
to express the
an immediate inference (the inference that
from the
fact that all
swans are white, then
say, "//" all
To make
swans are white,
and "since" and "therefore." In order
''then,"
conversion.
are not.
more complex
logical correctness of
some swans
illicit
larger than the class of swans.
the mistake of thinking that because
as coextensive,
an
Aristotle calls
white objects
it
swans are white), we that
some swans
illicit
conversion,
must follow
express the incorrectness of an
swans are white, then
it
does not follow that
all
white objects are swans." "If-then" statements of these two kinds are statements of logically correct
and
point to note here
logically incorrect inferences. is
The important
that the truth of these "if-then" statements
about logically correct and logically incorrect inferences does not in any way depend upon the truth of the statements con-
nected by "if" and "then."
Man
The and
it
statement that
would
still
may
swans are white
all
Knower
the
be
in fact
—but only —
are white, if
would
still
if
Even
all are.
if
the statement that
be logically incorrect to infer that
from the
So much
What
and "then"
for the use of "if"
must follow" or
"it
it
white objects
all
"it
—the
accom-
latter
does not follow"
—
to
of correct and incorrect inferences.
recognition
When we
and "therefore"?
about "since"
all
false,
swans are white.
fact that all
panied by the words express our
false,
be logically correct to infer that some swans
white objects are swans were in fact true instead of
are swans
14^
:
substitute
we are actually make when we said only
"since" and "therefore" for "if" and "then,"
making the inference "if"
we
that
did not
and "then."
To
stay
we have been
with the same example that
using,
I
have made no actual inferences about swans or white objects in all
the "if-then" statements
make an
have made about them.
I
actual inference until
therefore follows that
swans are white enables
Only when
I
I
say, ''Since all
some swans
make
me
are white."
to assert that
may be
falsity
false
no swans
I
if all arey
white
even though
are,
When .
making
.
say, "If all
not that .
,"
I
was
But when
.
I
.
I
would
.
The
,"
I
my
first
inference
actual infer-
statement, intruth
may be
conclude that
false to
am
so.
only saying
say "Since all swans are
saying that all are.
are white.
My
my
initial
are white.
of
falsity
was logically correct to do
all are.
am
it
it
connected by
second.
false in fact.
swans are white
that assertion,
some swans
it
is
and so
are white,
my
because
troduced by the word "since,"
some
my
logically correct, but the conclusion of
ence may be actually
that
of
swans are white,
kind,
"since" and "therefore," does the truth or
statement affect the truth or
do not
My assertion that all
some swans
assertions of this
I
Should
I
be right in
also be right in asserting that
— 146
:
Aristotle for
What
Everybody
has just been said about Aristotle's rules of immediate
inference helps
me
summarize
to
briefly the rules of reasoning
that constitute his theory of the syllogism.
Here
a
is
model
syllogism:
Major premise:
Minor
All animals are mortal.
premise:
men men
All
Conclusion:
All
are animals. are mortal.
Let us consider two more examples of reasoning syllogistically
from a major and
one is
in
false
a
minor premise
which the reasoning
is
to a conclusion. First, this
logically valid, but the conclusion
because the minor premise
is
false.
Major
premise:
Angels are neither male nor female.
Minor
premise:
Some men
are angels.
Some men
are neither
Conclusion:
And
this
one
in
which
male nor female.
a true conclusion follows logically
from
two true premises. Major
premise:
Mammals do
Minor
premise:
Human Human
Conclusion:
not lay eggs.
beings are
mammals.
beings do not lay eggs.
Considering these three different pieces of reasoning, we can observe at once that syllogistic reasoning
is
more complicated
than immediate inference. In immediate inference,
once from
a single statement to
we go from two
syllogistic reason-
statements, in which there are three dif-
ferent terms, to a conclusion in
occur.
at
another single statement, and
both statements will have the same terms. In ing,
we go
which two of these three terms
Man In the
first
example above, the three terms
the
Knower
in the
:
14J
major and
minor premise were ''animals," "men," and "mortal." And the in the conclusion
two terms
premise) and "mortal"
were "men"
term
(a
in the
term in the minor
(a
major premise). That
always the case in syllogistic reasoning, and
is
always the case
it is
that the third term, which occurs in both premises ("animals"),
has been dropped out of the conclusion.
term that
Aristotle calls the
common
is
minor premise the middle term. sion because
it
has serx^ed
That function other.
is
its
It is
to the
major and the
dropped out of the conclu-
function in the reasoning process.
connect the other two terms with each
to
is
why
as contrasted
with
The middle term mediates between them. That
Aristotle calls syllogistic reasoning
mediated
immediate inference. In immediate inference, there dle term because there I
The
yourself. First,
that
if
this
works in the three ex-
You can do
that for
only additional rules that you must note are these. the major or the
some form of
contains
how
reasoning just given.
syllogistic
is
no need of mediation.
bother to spell out
will not
amples of
is
no mid-
"is
minor premise
is
negative
(if
it
not" instead of "is," or "no" instead
of "all"), then the conclusion must also be negative.
not draw an affirmative conclusion
if
You
one of the premises
is
canneg-
ative.
The second nectively.
do
rule
Here
is
is
that the middle term
an example
in
must function con-
which the middle term
fails to
so.
Major
premise:
Minor
premise:
Conclusion:
Not only
is
No men are by nature beasts of burden. No mules are by nature men. No mules are by nature beasts of burden.
the conclusion false in
incorrect conclusion.
An
but
it is
also a logically
affirmative conclusion
must be drawn
fact,
I 148
:
Aristotle for
Everybody
from two affirmative premises, but no conclusion
at all
drawn from two negative premises. The reason
validly
the negative in the major premise excludes
minor premise excludes
men. Hence we cannot between the
relation
men
is
that
fi:om the
by nature beasts of burden; and the nega-
class of things that are tive in the
all
can be
all
mules from the
class of
correctly infer anything at all about the
mules and the
class of
class of things that
are by nature beasts of burden. It is
example
interesting to observe in the
major and minor premises are both
from them
that does not logically follow
both premises to be
sible for
given that the
just
conclusion
true, while the
false in fact
is
false. It
and
is
quite pos-
for a false
conclu-
sion to follow logically from them. For example:
Major
premise:
No
Minor
premise:
All married
No
Conclusion:
What consider)
out and
have daughters.
married
show us
is
have daughters.
many
others that
perhaps, worth repeating. Reasoning
we might
may
be logi-
whether the premises and the conclu-
sion are true or false in fact. is
are fathers.
something that has already been pointed
cally correct regardless of
true
men men
these examples (and
all
is,
fathers
Only
if
both premises are in
the conclusion that follows logically from
them
fact
also in
fact true. If
either premise
logically
which
it
logically
that
is
false,
then the conclusion that follows
from them may be either true or is.
On
the other hand,
from certain premises
is
if
false.
We
cannot
tell
the conclusion that follows
in fact false,
one or both of the premises from which
then we can infer it
is
drawn must
also be false.
This leads us to one more important rule of reasoning that
Man
Knower
the
immediate
Aristotle pointed out. In syllogistic reasoning, as in
inference, the validity of the inference
and
149
:
expressed by an
is
a "then." In the case of syllogistic reasoning,
we
''if"
are saying
that if the two premises are true, then the conclusion that logically follows
from them
also true.
is
the truth of the premises.
We
We
have not yet asserted
have asserted only the validity of
the inference from the premises to the conclusion.
we
Only when
assert the truth of the premises by substituting "since" for
"if,"
can we also substitute "therefore"
for
"then" and assert the
truth of the conclusion.
The
On
rule with
which we
the one hand,
of the conclusion other hand, the premises
it
if
if
are here
says that
it
we
we have
concemed has two
parts.
a right to assert the truth
assert the truth of the premises.
says that
we have
we deny
the truth of the conclusion.
On
the
a right to question the truth of
tion the truth of the premises" rather than
I
say "ques-
"deny the truth of the
when we deny the truth of the conclusion, we know only that either one of the premises is false or that both may be, but we do not know which is the case. The double-edged rule just stated is particularly applicable to premises" because
a kind of reasoning that Aristotle called hypothetical.
It
usually
involves four terms, not three.
Alexander Hamilton,
men
in
one of the Federalist papers,
were angels, no government would be necessary."
ing said that, Hamilton went on to deny that
no conclusion would
follow.
Denying the
men
said: "If If,
hav-
were angels,
ff statement (which
is
called the antecedent in hypothetical reasoning) does not entitle
you
to
deny the then statement (which
is
called
the con-
sequent).
However, Hamilton obviously thought that government unquestionably necessary for a society of
human
beings.
would, therefore, have had no hesitation in denying that
is
He men
1 ISO
:
Aristotle for
are angels.
Everybody
He would have been
doing so because deny-
right in
ing the consequent (or the then statement) in hypothetical rea-
soning does entitle you to deny the antecedent (or the
if state-
ment).
The
truth that
a single
complex statement
reasoning behind
cause
Hamilton
men
society."
it.
getting at can also be expressed in
that conceals rather than reveals the
That complex statement
are not angels,
The
is
government
is
is
as follows: ''Be-
necessary for
of statements about the difference between
men and
well as statements about the special characteristics of
make government compressed
human
reasoning that goes unexpressed involves a series
necessary for
argument
that
human
omits
or
society.
conceals
premises Aristotle called an enthymeme.
angels as
men
The
that
kind of
indispensable
18
Telling the Truth
Thinking
The word
and
It
"truth" has been used over and over again in the two
preceding chapters. Since those chapters are about the way the
mind works and about thinking and knowing, that reference to truth
When we know When we try to
and
falsity
it is
quite natural
should have been frequent.
something, what we know
is
the truth about
think correctly and soundly, our effort
is
it.
to get
at the truth. I
thought
it
possible to use the words "truth"
and
"falsity" (or
mean because everyone does understand what they mean. They are common notions, commonly used. The question "What is truth?" is not "true" and "false") without explaining what they
a difficult question to answer. After is,
the difficult question, as
whether
The
we
a particular statement
reason
why
I
is
you understand what
shall see,
is:
How
and
tell
true or false?
say that everyone, as a matter of
sense, understands truth
truth
can we
falsity is that
common
everyone knows
how
1S2
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
to tell a
Every one of us has told
lie.
lies
on one occasion or
another, and everyone understands the difference between ing a
and
lie
telling the truth.
Let us suppose that
On
Sunday. taurant
moment,
the
to you.
My
of what
I
when
To
think.
dinner that evening.
I
"is"
— It
is
think
think
is
it
think
"is
this
not"
"is
To
—
tell
in other words,
why
I
For lied
open
for
dinner
or to say "is not"
when you
is
when
the very op-
think "is," and
who
taught at Harvard University
century wittily remarked that a
liar is a
is
a person
who
thinks.
To
lie is
but the very opposite of
said a
have done
is
understands.
moment
To
tell
the truth,
it.
ago, everyone understands this. All
have done so
His answer consists in
is
I
what everyone
as preparation for Aristotle's simple,
and common-sense answer
makes our thinking
to
not to say in words what one thinks,
to spell out, as explicitly as possible, I
A
intentionally puts "is" in
to have what one says in words agree with or conform
what one
clear,
is
the truth
place of "is not," or "is not" in place of "is."
I
is.
not" are what he meant by ontological predicates.
liar,
As
that resit
willfully misplaces his ontological predicates. "Is"
"is
is
that
not."
philosopher
and
then,
you
on
closed
not open.
consists in saying "is"
when you
who
I
to tell a lie.
beginning of
person
tell
said that a certain restaurant
when you
An American at the
I
us not be concerned with the reason
same time
say "is"
not"
for
let
posite of this. "is
is
lying consisted in saying in words the very opposite
at the
you think
think a certain restaurant
I
Sunday morning, you ask me whether
a
open
is
tell-
to the question
about what
true or false.
that, just as telling the truth to
another person
an agreement between what one says and what one
thinks, so thinking truly consists in an
agreement between what
Man one thinks and what one
think truly
I
he was not an
if
Columbus was
a Spaniard or
think he was an Italian and falsely
I
for
an understanding of
explanation of what makes our thinking true or
is;
have truth
or that that
sity in
that
is
in
which
our mind)
which
if
not,
our mind) not,
is
we
if
not.
is
we
is
Truth
I
Ital-
think
We
Aristotle's
We
false.
think
think that that which
is,
is
is,
fal-
not; or that
in
someone
words
to
the agree-
else,
another person and
what we actually think. In the case of thinking the is
an
if
am
I
is.
between what we say
agreement
if
think falsely (or have
think that that which
In the case of telling the truth to
ment
153
:
Italian.
This one example suffices
truly (or
Knower
thinking about. For example,
is
asked whether Christopher ian,
the
between what we think and the
consists in a
truth, the
facts as
they are.
correspondence between the mind and
real-
ity.
We
express most of our thoughts in words, whether
we
are
speaking to ourselves or to someone else or writing our thoughts
down
some
in
fashion.
Not
all
the thoughts
we
express orally
are either true or false. Aristotle points out that questions are
neither true nor
nor the
false;
nor are the requests we make of others,
commands we
give.
some form
tences that contain
Only
declarative sentences
of the words
''is"
that can be rephrased to contain those words
—
and
facts
things are. fail
to
Only such statements can
do
so. If
lies in its
of the matter. Declarative statements
are the only statements that try to describe the facts
or
not," or
fact that Aris-
understanding of what makes a statement true
agreement with the
sen-
are true or false.
This should not seem surprising in view of the totle's
''is
—
—
the
way
either succeed in doing so
they succeed, they are true;
if
they
fail,
they
are false. It
would appear, then,
that statements that are prescriptive
154
Aristotle for
•
Everybody
rather than descriptive cannot be either true or false. tive
statement
How
to reading
truth
is
one
and
what you or
that prescribes
can a statement that says that books and
I
ought
I
A
prescrip-
ought
to do.
devote more time
to
playing games be true or false
less to
if
the statement of our thoughts consist in an
falsity in
agreement between what we
assert or
deny and the way things
are or are not?
Being able to answer that question there were to
aim
no answer
at in life,
to
it,
is
of great importance.
If
we ought employ in
statements about the goals
and about the means we ought
order to reach them, would be neither true nor
to
false.
Everything we learned from Aristotle about the pursuit of happiness (in Part
an expression of
of this book) might
III
Aristotle's
could not claim, and
I
opinions about such matters. But he
could not claim, truth
mendations about what we ought
good
human
life
that
we
be interesting as
still
are
to
do
recom-
for his
in order to achieve the
under a moral obligation
to try to
achieve.
Aristotle obviously life
and how
to
had an answer
thought that his teaching about the good
achieve
it
was
true. Therefore,
about the truth of statements that
to the question
contain the words ''ought" or ''ought not." just as a descriptive
forms to
reality,
he must have
statement
is
true
if
it
He
did.
He
said that,
agrees with or con-
so a prescriptive statement
is
true
if it
agrees
with or conforms to right desire.
What is right desire? It consists in desiring what one ought to desire. What ought one to desire? Whatever is really good for a human being. What is really good for a human being? Whatever satisfies a human need. The statement that a person ought to desire whatever is really good
for
himself or herself
is
a
self-evident truth.
It
is
self-
Man way
evident in the same
than the Just as
whole
finite
it
is
that the statement that a part
which
to
than any of
ought
edge
parts, so
its
to desire that
our
really
is
human
good
for
consists in desiring
we ought it
really
is
bad
really
is
needs
less
is
self-evidently true.
is
greater
is
less
is
human
good
for us, or that
we we
for us.
the need for knowledge. Knowl-
is
beings to have. Since right desire
what we ought
right desire,
to
155
:
impossible for us to think that
is
it
which
is
it
statement that
to desire, the
knowledge conforms
to desire
conforms
belongs
belongs, or of a whole that
it
which
to desire that
Among
it
impossible for us to think of a part that
than the whole to which
ought not
Knower
the
true,
Because
to right desire.
according to Aristotle's
theory of what makes a prescriptive statement true.
We
have
A
false. its
taken the easiest step toward answering the
just
question about
how we can
statement such as ''A
parts" reveals
its
truth
stand the terms that
and "greater than" true. is,
tell
It is
on
whether
finite
its
whole
a statement is
greater than
very face. As soon as
—
make up the statement we immediately see that
—
any of
we under-
''whole," ''part,"
the statement
impossible to understand what a whole
and the
true or
is
what
is,
relation oi greater than, without at the
understanding a whole to be greater than any of
its
a part
same time
parts.
There are not many statements we can make that are evidently true in this way.
good ought
to
be desired
is
The
statement that what
one of them. But
its
truth
manifest as the truth about wholes and parts because for us to
understand wholes and parts than
it
is
is
to
it
self-
is
really
is
not as
is
easier
understand
the distinction between real and apparent goods and the distinction
between what ought
to
be desired and what
is
in fact de-
sired.
We
sometimes
call
statements self-evident that are not
self-
156
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
evident.
When we
do
argument. That
is
so on.
—acceptable
men
all
These statements may have been accepted
What
I
have
and by
just said indicates
whether a statement its
wrote,
are created equal, that they are
may
truth
as true by the
to establish their truth.
another way in which we can
true or false. If
is
and
others, but a fairly extended
argument would have been necessary
true,
when he
their Creator with certain unalienable rights,"
signers of the Declaration
tell
without any further
Jefferson did
Independence, that "we hold these truths
be self-evident: that
endowed by
recommend them
usually wish to
what Thomas
in the Declaration of to
we
so,
acceptable truths
as generally
it is
not self-evidently
be established by argument or reasoning. Ac-
cording to Aristotle, the truth of some statements can be demonstrated in this way.
Two
conditions are required for the
onstration or proof of a statement's truth.
premises used in the reasoning.
The
One
other
is
is
dem-
the truth of the
the correctness or
validity of the reasoning itself
Let the statement be: 'The United States State of truth.
other
New
New
One
''A
one
is
Two
whole
"The United
is:
York
that the
York."
is:
United States
is
than the
larger
premises are needed to establish
is
States
larger than is
From
part."
is
any of
a whole, of
its
parts."
which the
these two statements,
larger than the State of
New
it
its
The
State of
follows
York.
The
premises being true, the conclusion that follows from them
is
also true. Just as very
few statements can be seen by us to be
self-
evidently true, so also very few can be seen by us to be true as a result of valid reasoning
from true premises. The truth of most
we think is not so easily dewe remain in doubt about whether a false. When we are able to resolve our
of the statements that express what
termined. In most cases,
statement doubts,
is
true or
we do
so by appealing to the evidence afforded us by the
experience of our senses.
Man For example,
we
if
way
look at the building and count
its
building's height
The
Knower
157
:
doubt whether a certain building
are in
twelve or fifteen stories tall, the
simple observation will
the
remove
to
A
stories.
that doubt
single,
is
is
to
relatively
us whether a statement about the
tell
true or false.
is
appeal to observation
way
the
is
determine the truth of
to
statements about things that are perceivable through our senses.
You may the
way
ask whether
check our
to
we can
own
trust
our senses. Not always, but
observation
to
is
have
it
confirmed or
corroborated by the observation of others.
For example,
as a result of
my own
observation,
I
may make
the statement that the automobile that crashed into the wall was
going very
Other witnesses of the same event may have
fast.
be appealed to in order to get
them
report the
A is
who
the truth of this matter. If
same observation,
automobile was going very nesses
at
fast
is
it
possessed by a statement that
ment its
its is
speed
is
we
We
truth.
we
wit-
it is.
it
was not.
When we
A
statement
say that a state-
are not estimating the degree of
own
assessing our
are
The more
regard as certainly true. Ei-
either true or false.
only probably true,
claiming truth for
of
only probably true has the same truth that
ther the auto was going very fast or
about
to
probably true that the
crashed.
more probable
agree on this point, the
statement that
is
it
when
all
degree of assurance in
it.
Degrees of probability are not measures of the truth of a
state-
ment, but only measures of the assurance with which we can determine
its
as the truth
truth that
we
truth.
A
truth that
about wholes and
we
affirm with certitude, such
parts, is
no more
true than a
regard as only probable, such as the truth about
the speed of the auto that crashed.
Some
witnesses are qualified to
make
us to determine the truth of statements;
ample,
as a result
of
my own
observations that help
some
observation,
I
are not.
may
For ex-
say that the
1^8
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
on your
ring
gold and
finger
gold.
may, of course, look
It
be only gold plated.
still
sible, to tell
is
which
It
is
difficult,
as if
if
looking at or handling the ring.
ways of determining the
made of
witness, can say
not impos-
The
jeweler
By putting your
gold.
whether
result of
my
it,
by
this just
knows there
real character of objects that
and by observing the
test
were
by unaided observation. Even an experi-
it is
enced jeweler would not give you an opinion about
they are
it
are
look as
if
ring to the appropriate
the jeweler, as an expert
original statement about the ring
is
true or false.
So jects
far
we have considered
—statements about
statements about particular ob-
the height of a certain building, about
the speed of a certain automobile, about the metal of a certain ring.
The
tion.
Sometimes,
truth of such statements can be checked by observa-
we can be
servation of others as well,
or the ob-
relatively sure
about the
under consideration; sometimes, we are
truth of the statement left
own
of observation, our
as a result
unsure.
Observation seldom gives us the certainty we have about the truth of statements that are self-evidently true or that can be es-
tablished as true by valid reasoning.
I
say "seldom" rather than
''never" because, according to Aristotle,
about observable objects are
some simple statements some general
as evidently true as
statements are self-evidently true. That there in
my
typewriter as
evident to me.
me am as
I
am
I
of the truth of
fact.
certain of
ment about wholes and
We
are
alizations
left
a piece of paper is
immediately
do not need the confirmation of other witnesses
to assure I
is
writing this sentence
its
my
statement about this observable
truth as
I
am
of the truth of the state-
parts.
with a large class of statements that
from experience, such statements
we
as "All
call
gener-
swans are
Man white" or "All Eskimos are short." Since
it
the
Knower
:
159
impossible for us
is
or anyone else to observe the color oi all swans, or the height of
Eskimos, observation by
all
itself
cannot establish the truth of
these generalizations.
A number
may persuade us that the The larger the number of
of observations
izations are probably true. tions, the
more we may be persuaded. Increasing
can only increase the probability.
It
can never
general-
observa-
number
their
result in certainty
that the generalizations are true.
However, we can be certain that even
if
we can never be
certain that
a generalization it
is
true.
I
is
false,
pointed out in
preceding chapter that the statement ''Some swans are
the
black" or even the statement 'This swan that
I
am
observing
is
black" contradicts the statement "All swans are white." Contradictory statements cannot both be true.
vation that this one swan
is
swans are white. In the
all
black
falsifies
light of that
with certitude that the generalization Aristotle's tell
whether
saying that
The
is
a statement
is
are able to
tion provides us with
obser-
the generalization that I
know
false.
how we
true or false can be
do so by appealing
the one hand, and to reason,
my
one observation,
answer to the question about
we
truth of
are able to
summarized by
to experience,
on
on the other hand. Sense percep-
one way of checking the truth or
falsity
of
recommends that we always consider the opinions of others before making up our own minds the opinions held by most men, or by the statements in question. In addition, Aristotle
—
few
who
are experts, or by the wise.
19 f'l
Beyond
a
Reasonable Doubt
In our courts two standards are set for the verdict to be rendered
by a
jury.
On
questions of fact that the court submits to the
jury, the jury
is
sometimes required
to give
an answer that
holds beyond a reasonable doubt; and sometimes if
the jury's answer
is
one that
it
thinks
is
it
is
it
sufficient
supported by a prepon-
derance of the evidence. Aristotle
made
a
somewhat
similar distinction between two
which we can answer questions of
ways
in
jury's
answer that
is
beyond
can answer a question by knowledge.
When
Aristotle calls
all
a reasonable doubt,
sorts.
Like the
we sometimes
a statement that has the status of
our answers do not consist of knowledge,
them opinions. Opinions approach knowledge
to
the extent that they have the weight of the evidence on their side.
At the very opposite end of the scale are those opinions
that are totally
unsupported by evidence.
Aristotle's distinction
between knowledge and opinion
is
a
Man one
very sharp
We
consists of necessary truths.
beyond
ample, we cannot doubt that a If
something
its
parts.
parts.
its
than any of
Such
161
is
whole
is
whole,
it
finite
a finite
impossible for
It is
affirm such truths with
reasonable doubt. For ex-
all
it
greater than any
must be
greater
not to be.
one example of what
self-evident truths constitute
means by knowledge. The other example
totle
:
sharp, perhaps, for us to accept without
certitude because they are
of
Knower
For him, when we have knowledge, what we
quahfication.
know
—too
the
Aris-
consists of con-
clusions that can be validly demonstrated by premises that are
When we
self-evidently true.
know
only
what they sert
is
that assert
true,
Here, too,
what they true.
is
we know we are in
Aristotle in his
is
Knowing
true, but
the
what they
that
we not we also know why reasons why what they as-
affirm such conclusions,
assert
assert
cannot be otherwise.
possession of necessary truths.
day thought that mathematics, especially ge-
ometry, exemplified knowledge of this high quality. that
is
The view
held of mathematics in our day does not agree with Aris-
totle's.
Nevertheless mathematics
comes nearer than any other
meant by knowledge. of geometry, we can understand one
science to exemplifying what Aristotle
Considering the truths
other distinction that Aristotle
made between knowledge and
opinion. There are two ways, he says, in which one can affirm the conclusion of a geometrical demonstration.
who
The
teacher
understands the demonstration affirms the conclusion in
the light of the premises that prove In contrast, the student stration
but
teacher said truth itself
someone
is
else
who it
is
who
affirms
it.
He
does not understand the
the
conclusion
to
only
true does not have knowledge.
a necessary truth, to affirm is
or she has knowledge.
hold
knowledge. For most of
it
as a matter of
it
demon-
because
Even
if
the
the
on the authority of
opinion rather than
us, the scientific truths
with which
as
we
i62
Aristotle for
:
Everybody
are acquainted are opinions tists,
we
not knowledge that
We may
find this
we hold on
the authority of scien-
ourselves possess.
way of distinguishing between knowledge
and opinion more useful
as well as
more
Only
acceptable.
a
very few statements are necessary truths for us because they are
and
self-evidently true,
their opposites are impossible. All other
may
statements express opinions that
Though
would
Aristotle
call
may
or
true.
statements of this sort state-
all
ments of opinion rather than of knowledge,
we can
not be
let
divide opinions into two groups, one of
us see whether
which has some
resemblance to what Aristotle meant by knowledge.
The
we hold may either be supported by reasons and by observations, or they may be held by us without such opinions
support. For example,
one
me
else told
it
reason for thinking
my it
part.
The
any the
cerned,
I
thinking
it
was it
if
hold an opinion only because some-
true,
and
I
myself do not have any other
be true, then that
to
statement
less a
I
may
Each of us we hold to be
a
mere opinion on
be true. That does not make
in fact
mere opinion. So
far as affirming
me
have no grounds that provide to
is
it
con-
is
with reasons for
be true apart from the authority of someone
else.
—
number of personal prejudices things we want to believe them. We grounds for believing them. Instead, we are
also has a
true simply because
have no rational
emotionally attached to them. For example, persons often believe that their
may is
may
or
country
not be true.
is
It
the best country in the world. That
may even
true by citing evidence of
one
sort or
reasons for thinking so. But persons
not
cite
The
be possible to argue that
who
evidence or give reasons. They
statements to which one
is
it
another or by giving
believe this usually
just
wish
to believe
do it.
emotionally attached by such
wishful thinking are mere opinions. Other persons
may
be emo-
Man
the
tionally attached to opinions that are opposite.
one opinion nor the other, which may be
Knower
Since neither
very opposite,
its
supported by reasons or evidence, one opinion of this sort
good
16^
:
is
is
as
as another.
In the case of or her
tached.
none
own
mere opinions, everyone
—those
entitled to prefer his
which the individual
to
emotionally
is
About such opinions there can be no argument,
that
is
rational.
Opinions of this
personal taste in food or drink.
than pineapple juice, and
You
orange juice.
There
is
is
no point
I
at least
sort are like expressions of
You may like orange juice better may prefer pineapple juice to and
are entitled to your likes,
in
at-
our arguing about which
is
I
to
mine.
better.
become arguable only when the opinions about which we differ are not mere opinions in the sense just indicated only when they are not simply personal prejudices, expressions of taste, or things that we wish to believe. Differences of opinion
—
For example,
I
may have good
reasons for thinking that har-
nessing the energy of the sun will provide us with sufficient
when we run out may have good reasons
energy
solve the problem. statistics
of
fossil fuels
such
as coal
for thinking that solar
Each of
us, in addition,
and
oil.
You
energy will not
may be
able to cite
provided by careful studies of energy sources. Neither
may be able to persuade the other. Nevertheless, opinions we hold and about which we differ and argue are of us
mere opinions on our
the
not
part.
Let us suppose that neither of us has studied the energy prob-
lem
ourselves.
others
on the
We
have simply read what has been said by
The
we hold
are based
others. Let us further suppose that
you have
subject.
on the authority of
most of the authorities
opposite opinions
in this field
authorities that can be appealed to,
your
side.
on your
side; or that
of the
you have the most expert on
Aristode would say that you have the stronger case.
—
164
:
Aristotle for
Everybody
In his view, the opinion that
most of those who are the experts,
We
held either by most men, or by
is
experts, or by the best-quahfied
among
hkely to turn out to be the better opinion to hold.
is
approach nearer to what Aristotle meant by knowledge,
and we move further away from mere opinion, when the opinions held are based
on
Those opinions
ing.
scientific
evidence and scientific reason-
that are supported by a
preponderance of
the evidence and by the soundest reasoning are regarded by entists in It
is
sci-
our day as knowledge.
not knowledge in Aristotle's sense of the term because
what we claim
to
know may
opinions when,
opposite
more evidence
is
turn out not to be the better of two
by further
scientific
found on the opposite
side; or
investigation,
when, by
fur-
ther scientific thought, better reasons are found for holding the
opposite opinion.
No
scientific
finally or ultimately true
—
^true
conclusion
beyond the
tion or rejection by further investigation
known by
is
possibility
us to be
of correc-
and further thought
about the matter.
The
opposite of any opinion that
we hold
as
scientific
a
conclusion always remains possible because no scientific conclusion
of
is
itself a
scientific
necessary truth. Nevertheless, a large
derance of the evidence and by unchallenged reasons centuries.
number
conclusions have been supported by a prepon-
The
fact that
new
discoveries
may
shift
for
many
the scales
against these conclusions or the fact that the reasons in favor of
them may be
seriously challenged by
new
thinking about the
subject does not prevent us from regarding such conclusions as well-established knowledge
Are
for the time being.
scientific conclusions,
supported by a preponderance of
the evidence and by the best reasoning that time, the only opinions
we
is
available at the
are entitled to regard as knowledge?
No. Philosophical conclusions may
also be opinions that
we
are
Man entitled to regard as
the
Knower
How
them
165
knowledge because they are supported by
sound reasoning and by the weight of the evidence that favor of
:
is
in
rather than their opposites.
do the conclusions of philosophical thought
the conclusions of scientific research?
The answer
differ
from
in the
lies
two words "thought" and "research." Scientific conclusions are based on the investigations undertaken by laboratories or not.
The
conclusions never by
scientists,
whether
in
thinking that scientists do to reach these
itself suffices.
It
is
always thinking about
the observations or findings of carefully planned and carefully
executed research or investigation. In contrast, philosophical thought reaches conclusions based
common
on
experience, the kind of experience that
have every day of our
lives
without doing any research
carefully carrying out carefully
phers do no research.
of us
all
—without
planned investigations. Philoso-
They do not
devise experiments or carry
out investigations. Philosophical thought about the
common-sense opinions
common
that
experience begins with
most persons hold.
It
improves
upon such common-sense opinions by being more reflective and analytical than most persons are. In my own view of the matter, I
it
reaches
have called
its
best
Aristotle's
and most-refined conclusions
uncommon common
in
what
sense.
Scientific or philosophical conclusions are usually general-
izations
from experience
—
either the special experience that re-
sults
from research or investigation or the
that
all
common
experience
of us have without investigation or research. As
noted in an earlier chapter, any generalization can be
by a single negative observation. This sophical as
it
is
is
it
as true of a philo-
of a scientific generalization.
eralization goes without being falsified, the to regard
as established
we
falsified
The
more
longer a gen-
entitled
we
are
knowledge even though we can never
1
66
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
regard
it
as finally or ultimately true
—beyond the
possibility
of
correction or rejection.
Because philosophical conclusions are based on rather than
by the
on
results
common
special experience, because they are not affected
of investigation or research, conclusions of the
kind that Aristotle reached more than two thousand years ago
can
still
claim the status of philosophical knowledge in our day.
our
common
Most of the
scientific
Nothing
in
experience since his time has
falsified
them. conclusions that were currently ac-
cepted in Aristotle's day have been rejected or corrected since then.
They have
either
research, or they have
been
falsified
by the discoveries of
been corrected and improved by
later
better
thinking as well as by better observations and more thorough investigations.
Not
all
opinions that can be regarded as established knowl-
edge take the form of
scientific or philosophical generalizations
from experience. Historical investigation or research reaches
—the
conclusions about particular matters of fact
date
when
some event took place, the steps by which some individual became a ruler, the circumstances that led to the outbreak of a war, and so forth.
Here, as in the case of science, research amasses evidence
about which historians think and,
in the light of their thinking,
advance conclusions that they regard
as
supported by a prepon-
derance of the evidence and by good reasons.
When
they are
reached in this way, historical conclusions can be regarded as established knowledge even though further research
may change
our view of the matter.
We now
see that there are at least five different kinds of
knowledge, only one of which
is
knowledge
in the strict sense
Man that Aristotle attaches to that word.
we have when we understand other four kinds are ical
thought
(i)
(2)
is
Knower
:
i6j
the knowledge
truths that are self-evident.
The
the well-founded opinions of mathemat-
—the conclusions
demonstrate;
That one
the
that
mathematicians are able
to
the well-established generalizations of scientific
research or investigation; (3) the philosophical opinions that are
based on
mon
common
experience and on the refinement of com-
sense by philosophical reflection; and (4) the opinions
about particular
facts that historians are able to
support by his-
torical research.
All four are opinions in the sense that they are never so firmly
established by reasons
and evidence
or corrected by further thought or are also
knowledge
that they
new
in the sense that at a given
the weight of the evidence in their favor
supports
cannot be
observations. Yet
them remains unchallenged.
falsified all
four
time they have
and the reasoning that
PART T DIFFICULT
PHILOSOPHICAL
QUESTIONS
20
Infinity
Difficult philosophical questions are questions that
ble to answer in the light of
of
common
sense.
common
it is
impossi-
experience and by the use
To answer them requires sustained reflection
and reasoning.
How
do such questions
from the refinements of
arise?
For Aristotle they arose in part
common
sophical thought developed.
sense that his
own
philo-
In part, they were questions he
asked in response to the views of others that were current in his day.
Among Greek
the students of nature
physicists,
who
preceded him were two
Leucippus and Democritus, who
first
proposed
the theory of atoms. According to their theory, everything in the
world of nature ter,
is
composed of
— space
separated by a void
tiny, invisible particles of totally
mat-
devoid of matter. They
called these particles atoms to indicate that these units of matter
were not merely very small, but absolutely small.
Nothing
172
Everybody
Aristotle for
;
atom
smaller, in their view, can exist, for each
unit of matter.
It
cannot be cut up into smaller
Atoms, according only in
And
size,
They
differ
units.
from one another
are constantly in motion.
they are infinite in number.
Confronted with In the
it.
Democritus,
to
shape, and weight.
an indivisible
is
an atom
If
void or empty space inside
is
in
which case
empty space, the matter
it
is
a solid unit of matter with
then, he argued,
it,
cuttable or indivisible. Either an it,
to
place, he challenged the central notion in the
first
theory of atomism.
inside
two objections
this theory, Aristotle raised
is
it
no
cannot be un-
atom has some empty space
not a unit of matter; or, lacking
continuous, in which case
it is
divis-
ible.
The
reasoning here can be illustrated by taking something
larger than I
break
of
it
wood
an atom.
am
I
holding in
into two smaller pieces of
is
now
my hand
No
a separate unit of matter.
piece of wood, they can
of the two pieces of
no longer be broken
wood can be
one matchstick.
wood. Each of these pieces longer being one
into two. But each
further divided,
and so on
without end.
Whatever
is
Anything that uous.
If
it
or more.
one
were not,
By
— it
is
infinitely divisible.
a single unit of matter
—must be contin-
would not be one unit of matter, but two Aristotle thought he showed that
this reasoning,
there could be ter,
continuous, Aristode held, is
no atoms. There may be very small
but however small these particles
divided into smaller particles,
if
each
is
may
be,
units of mat-
they can be
a unit of matter
—one
and continuous. In the second place, Aristotle objected to the view that there are
an
be very
infinite
number
of atoms in the world.
large, so large that
a counter
might use
to
it
do
The number may
cannot be counted in any time that so.
But
it
cannot be an
infinite
Difficult Philosophical Questions
number because,
These two objections of his day
may
an
Aristotle maintained,
number
infinite
moment
things cannot actually coexist at any
173
:
of
of time.
that Aristotle raised against the atomists
appear
at first
to
be inconsistent.
On
the one
hand, Aristotle appears to be saying that any continuous unit of
On
matter must be infinitely divisible.
the other hand, he ap-
number
pears to be saying that there cannot be an infinite units in existence at
any one time.
existence of an infinity
The apparent
and
contradiction
is
an
We
earlier chapter of this
the distinction between the potential
what can be (but
is
not)
and what
Aristotle thinks that there tial,
One
neither actual.
is
it?
resolved by a distinction that
characteristic of Aristotle's thought.
distinction in
he not both affirming the
Is
denying
also
of
have come upon
book
(see chapter 7).
and the actual
is
this It is
—betweep
is.
can be two
infinities
—both poten-
the potential infinite of addition.
The other is the potential infinite of division. The potential infinite of addition is exemplified in the infinity of whole numbers. There is no whole number that is the last number in the series of whole numbers from one, two, three, four, and so on. Given any number in that series, however large it may be, there is a next one that is larger. It is possible to go on adding number after number without end. But it is only possible,
to
you cannot actually carry out
do so would take an Aristotle, as
we
infinity of time.
world
—
that
it
infinite
time
this process of addition, for
—time without end.
shall see in the next chapter, did not
On
deny the
the contrary, he affirmed the eternity of the
has no beginning or end. But an infinite time
does not exist at any one
whole numbers,
it is
moment. Like
the infinite series of
only a potential, not an actual, infinite.
So, too, the infinity of division
is
a potential, not
an actual.
— 174
•
Everybody
Aristotle for
infinite.
Just as
you can go on adding number
number
after
without end, so you can go on dividing anything that
contin-
is
uous without end. The number of fractions between the whole
numbers two and three is numbers is infinite. Both actual.
At
They do not
this
be
if
moment
Aristotle
number of atoms
of time.
maintained, there
infinity of coexisting things, as there
the atomists were correct in their view.
be remembered, that
totle
moment,
number of whole
however, are potential, not
actually exist at any
or any oth^r
cannot be an actual
infinite, just as the infinities,
at this very
coexist.
It
is
They
moment an
that
held,
would it
must
actually infinite
and that alone which
Aris-
denied.
His reasoning on this score ran as follows. Either the of actually coexisting things indefinite.
is
definite or indefinite. If
number it is
But nothing can be both actual and
infi-
indefi-
nite,
it is
nite.
Therefore, there cannot be an actual infinity of any sort
an actually
infinite
infinite world,
an actually
ally existing units
The
number of
coexisting atoms,
infinite space that
is
an actually
filled
with actu-
of matter.
only infinities that there can be, according to Aristotle,
are the potential infinities that are involved in the endless processes of addition or division. Since
one moment of time suc-
ceeds another or precedes another, and since two
time do not actually coexist, time can be
infinite.
moments of
21
Eternity
Time can be
infinite, Aristotle
of a series of
moments
thought, because
it
is
made up
or instants that precede or succeed
another and do not actually coexist. ceases to exist as the next
moment
One moment
one
of time
of time comes into existence.
Since that process can go on endlessly, there can be an infinite
number of moments or instants of time. Time can be infinite, but is it? If it is, then the world that now exists has no end. Even if it had a beginning, it can go on without end, for there
is
no end
to time.
There can always be
another moment. Aristotle less,
went
further.
He
not only thought that time
is
end-
but he also thought that the world had no beginning as
well as
no end.
If
the world had neither beginning nor end,
no moment of
then time
is
infinite in
time that
is
not preceded by an earlier moment. There
moment
of time that
is
both directions. There
is
not succeeded by a later
moment.
is
no
— ij6
:
Aristotle for
Why
Everybody
did Aristotle think the world
word "eternal"
express
to
his
He
eternal?
is
used the
understanding that the world
has neither beginning nor end. Sometimes the word "eternal"
used to signify timelessness, nal. Aristotle
when
is
it
God
said that
is
eter-
used the word "eternal" in that sense, too. But, in
his view, the eternity of the
of
as
is
God quite another. To understand this
world
distinction
one thing, and the
is
between the two
eternity
eternities
the eternity of timelessness and the eternity of time without
beginning or end of time
—we
must consider
understanding
Aristotle's
itself.
Time, he said, is the measure of motion or change. Another way of expressing this thought is to say that time is the dimension in which motion or change occurs, just as space is the which material things
dimension
in
cupy or
space.
fill
ball that rolls
Changing things endure
from one
is
in time.
The
billiard
side of the table to the other does so in a
period of time. That motion takes time.
motion
Existing things oc-
exist.
The
duration of the
measured by the number of moments of time
that
it
took for the billiard ball to get from here to there. It
follows, Aristotle thought, that time has neither beginning
nor end
why
if
motion or change has neither beginning nor end. But
did he think that motion or change cannot begin and can-
not end? That
The
answer,
is
if
a very difficult question, indeed.
there
is
an answer,
lies in
Aristode's notion of
cause and effect and in his notion of God. Anything that happens, Aristotle said,
thing must cause
must self.
itself It
it
must have to
a cause. If a
cue that struck
it.
to move move itTo set the
had
to
move. But
move. That which causes
move. For example, the
was moved by the
billiard
billiard ball in
motion, the
something
had
else
to
body moves, some-
move
billiard it.
a
body
billiard ball did not
And
cue
itself
so on.
Difficult Philosophical Questions
What mover
amounts
this
in the series of
to
a denial
is
existence
—of
come
first
did not first
tion of the
world.
that, the neces-
mover
moving and moved. The the of motion
—
efficient cause
first
we
moving.
on God, we
shall return to Aristotle's
concep-
I
need only point out
God, unlike the God of the
Bible, did not create
first
that Aristotle's
Aristotle, as
in his view, the first
in a series of things
that started things
In chapter 23
—more than
mover. But,
first
mover was not the
mover
the
a
ij-j
Aristotle's part of a first
mo\ers and things moved.
shall see, did affirm the existence sar\'
on
:
mover. For the present,
Aristotle
would ha\e denied the statement with
which the Bible opens: "In the beginning God created the
He would
heavens and the earth."
saw no reason whatsoever
have denied
for thinking that the
because he
it
world ever had a
beginning. If
there
is
no reason
for thinking that the
ever had a beginning, there that the world in
ual things of
motion
is
equally
will ever
which the world
is
come
world in motion
no reason to
composed come
and pass away. There cannot be an
for thinking
an end. The individ-
infinite
into existence
number
of individ-
any one time. But there can be an inficoming into being and passing away in an
ual things coexisting at nite
number
of things
infinite time, or
Coming into we have seen, one t\'pe of change. movement from one place to another, it
time without beginning or end.
being and passing away Like local motion, or
never started and
The
it
is,
as
never ends.
t\pe of motion that Aristotle had most in
talked about the eternity of
bodies on earth nor any other terrestrial change. at
the heavens
and
at the
the planets, and the
movement
stars.
mind when he
motion was not the movement of
He
there of the sun
looked up
and moon,
These motions, he thought, most
clearly exemplified the eternity of
motion and, with
it,
the eter-
ij8
:
Aristotle for
Everybody
nity of the world.
God
is
As we
shall see in chapter 23, the eternity of
used by Aristotle to explain the eternity of the world.
These two
eternities are as different as timelessness
from everlasting time.
is
different
22
The
Immateriality of
The
Mind
three philosophical questions with
which we
in this chapter are not all equally difficult.
question
difficult
is
question whether the existence of the
an element of immateriality into Finally,
first
and
least
whether the material things of the physical
world are also immaterial in some respect.
rial.
The
are concerned
and most
difficult
More
world that
a
of
all,
difficult
human mind is
is
is
the
introduces
otherwise mate-
the question whether
the universe includes a being or beings wholly immaterial.
The
reader
who remembers what was
have some clue question.
We
to the
answer that Aristotle gave
saw there that
all
rials that
human
art.
to the first
the changing things of physical
nature are composed of matter and form.
terms of works of
said in chapter 8 will
The
artist
We
understood
this in
or craftsman takes mate-
can be formed in one way or another and produces a
—
work of
art
them
form they did not originally have. The wood that be-
a
by transforming the materials he works on
giving
i8o
Aristotle for
:
comes form
Everybody
a chair as a
—the
form of chaimess
maker transformed It is
human
of
result
—
that
it
The
did not have before the
chairs that
men
we understood that form is many different
produce have
shapes, but whatever shape they have, they are
the form,
a
it.
important to remember that
not shape.
on
productivity takes
not the shape,
makes
that
all chairs.
It
is
chairs of different
all
shapes the same kind of thing. That form was an idea in the
mind of the maker before it became the form by which he transformed the wood into a chair. Having that idea, the maker understood the kind of material thing he wished to make. As the idea in the
mind
of the maker
is
an understanding of the kind of
thing to be made, so the form in the materials transformed by the maker
what makes
is
Whether they than
artificial things, all
not material.
it
the kind of thing that
are products of
Form
is
human
made.
is
art or natural rather
material things have an aspect that
not matter; matter
is
is
not form. Things
composed of form and matter have an immaterial
as well as a
material aspect.
As we have seen, we may be able
—
without form, but pure matter not
The forms
exist.
Lacking
ities.
all
and what has no Is it
to think
that matter can take actualize
form, matter by
about matter
unformed matter
itself
—can-
its
potential-
can have no
actuality;
actuality does not exist.
equally true to say that the forms that matter takes do not
exist apart
tuality
totally
—
from the matter
to
which they
give
some kind of acThe
the actuality of a chair or the actuality of a tree?
forms that are the immaterial aspect of material things are material
forms
—forms
that have their existence in matter.
the only existence they have?
Can
But
is
that
they also exist apart from the
matter of things that are composed of matter and form? Aristotle's
answer
to that question
is
affirmative.
Once more
— Difficult Philosophical Questions
necessary
is
it
remember something
to
chapter. In chapter 16, totle,
in
an
earlier
understands the kind of thing that a
by having an idea of
is
in
pointed out that, according to Aris-
I
human mind
the
chair or a tree
said
181
:
Having an idea
it.
consists
having in the mind the form of the thing without having the
matter of
The
also.
it
made
point just
activity as
its
relates to the difference
knower and mind
As producer, the mind has
in
its
between mind
a productive idea that
transform raw materials into chairs and tables.
and
into those raw materials table.
As
of the physical world. rial
things
gets
It
It
tree or a horse
By doing
so,
uses to ideas
its
them
the form of a chair or a
from the natural things
them by
taking the forms of mate-
away from the matter of those composite
trees or horses.
it
puts
gets ideas
gives
knower, the mind
a
in
activity as producer.
it
objects
understands the kind of thmg a
is.
remember from chapter 16 is the difference between knowing and eating. When we eat (take food into our system and digest it), we take both the matter and the form of Another point
to
the composite thing that gives us nourishment
—an apple
or a
potato.
As
Aristotle
eat gives us
saw
its
why the apple or potato that we that when we digest and assimilate
the reason
nourishment
we transform
it,
it,
is
matter.
Nourishment involves the assimilation of the food we similation occurs
when
a potato loses that foFjn
bone, and blood. That
eat.
As-
matter that had the form of an apple or
and
is
takes
on the form of human
why we must
take into our
own
flesh,
bodies
both the matter and the form of the material things from which
we
seek nourishment. If
to
knowing were exactly
like eating,
we would never be
understand the kind of thing an apple or a potato
is.
To
able
un-
i82
Everybody
Aristotle for
:
we must
take
away from the matter
that
derstand the kind of thing an apple or a potato the forms of those composite things
is,
they form.
we must
In assimilating edible things,
separate the matter
from the form and replace the form the matter had by the form of our
own
bodies.
we must
In understanding knowable things,
separate the form
from the matter and keep the form separate from matter. Only as separate
from matter does the form become an idea
in
our
minds, an idea by which we understand the kind of thing an apple or a potato
Why?
This
is
is.
the difficult question that remains to be an-
swered. Aristotle's answer turns on a distinction between the
kind of thing a potato or an apple
is
in general,
and particular
potatoes or apples, each a unique thing. This particular apple that
I
my hand
have in
form, which makes ter that
makes
it
it
is
the unique thing
an apple,
this apple,
is
The
is
because the
not that one over there on the table.
That one over there has the same form matter.
it
united with this unit of mat-
in a different unit of
different units of matter that enter into the
position of two individual apples
is
what makes them
com-
different
individuals. The form that each of them has is what makes them both apples the same kind of fruit. When we have the idea that enables us to understand the
—
kind of thing an apple eral,
is,
we
are understanding apples in gen-
not this or that individual apple. In Aristotle's view,
can perceive through our senses the individuality of apple, but
understand
we cannot, through its
individuality.
the ideas
Only kinds
we have
in
we
this or that
our minds,
in general are
under-
standable, not individuals.
That eral, ter
is
why
the mind, in
its
understanding of kinds in gen-
must separate the forms of material things from
and keep those forms separate
as the ideas
their
by which
mat-
we un-
Difficult Philosophical Questions
derstand.
forms
—
That
also
is
why
mind
Aristotle called the
183
:
the form of
the place where the forms of material things can exist
apart from their matter.
We
now
have
reached Aristotle's answer to the second ques-
beginning of
tion stated at the
mind introduce an element of immateriality otherwise material? Yes, Aristotle said, If
it
into a world that
beings,
would not
it
in the
makeup
the
mind
separate from their matter,
is
as distinct
To keep
And
did not keep or hold the forms of material things
which we understand kinds tato
of
give us the ability to understand
material things by separating their forms from their matter. if
is
does.
mind were not an immaterial element
the
human
Does the human
this chapter.
we would in general
not have the ideas by
—
the kind of thing a po-
from the kind of thing an apple
is.
or hold forms separate from matter, the
mind
itself
must be immaterial.
If
or held in matter,
and then they would no longer be ideas
it
were material, the forms would be kept
by which we understand kinds in general.
There
is
another way of saying the same thing that
us to understand Aristotle's
perceiving are one
mode
argument
a
little
better.
When we
of knowing.
material elements in our
Understanding
is
we know
derstanding, vidual thing
is.
Sensing and
knowing
in-
which
are
brains,
makeup.
a different
and perceiving, we know
and our
help
sense and per-
ceive individual things (this or that apple), such volves the action of our sense organs
may
mode
of knowing. By sensing
this or that individual thing.
By un-
the kind of thing in general that this indi-
Unlike sensing and perceiving, such knowing
does not involve the action of any material organ, not even the brain.
Seeing
is
our brain.
an act of the eve, but understanding It is
an act of our mind
is
not an act of
—an immaterial element
in
184
:
Aristotle for
Everybody
our makeup that
may
be related
to,
but
is
distinct from, the
brain as a material organ.
To sum up what we have totle,
learned so
far:
According
to Aris-
the forms of material things in the physical world are im-
material aspects of them.
which we
In addition, the material world, of
are a part, includes
we have minds
an immaterial element because
as well as brains,
minds
that are distinct
from
brains.
These ficult
are Aristotle's answers to the
first
philosophical questions with which
and most
difficult
—
material being
question
will
—about the
two of the three
we began. The
dif-
third
existence of a totally im-
be answered in the following chapter.
23
God
Aristotle's
view of the universe as eternal
dergoing change
He
change.
—
leads
him
—
to question the
attributes all the
as everlastingly
changes constantly occurring on
earth to the motion of the heavenly bodies.
them It
everlastingly in
If
cause of
its
it
effect to
cause
—
else in
A
it,
too,
is
itself in
would need
motion or changing
a cause of
its
in
motion, a
changing. Given infinite time, one might go back
from
a
were,
But what keeps
motion?
cannot be something that
any way.
un-
cause of everlasting
cause in an infinite series and never reach a
mover
in
motion that
is
not
itself
first
moved by something
motion.
prime mover that moves everything that
out moving and without being
is
in
motion with-
moved must cause motion by The bat that hits the ball and propels it is the efficient or active cause of the ball's motion. The candy in the window that entices me into the store to
being attractive rather than propulsive.
1
86
:
buy and self
Everybody
Aristotle for
eat
cause of
causes
it
moving,
my
it
my
motion
me.
attracts
It
entering the store
way. Without
in a different
it-
not the efficient but the final
is
—
why
the reason
I
move
in that
direction.
To move tion, the
everything else without
prime mover,
itself
Aristotle argues,
the gravitational attraction that the earth exerts that
fall
moon
to
upon the
come
tides.
them and adopt them
he says that a heavy body that
he
to rest there,
That motion tracted
is
only
in this
on
intelligences
motives for action.
as
wishes to
to earth
falls
speaking metaphorically, not
is
like
literally.
the motion of the person that
by the candy in the window to enter the
Thinking
mind
upon the bodies
In his view, attractive or final causes operate that can respond to
When
in
at-
surface, or the gravitational attraction that the
its
exerts
an
as
he did not have
tractive or final cause. In thinking this,
mo-
being moved or in
must function
way, Aristotle found
it
at-
is
store.
necessary to
endow mo-
the heavenly bodies with intelligences that function as their tors.
As the engine of an automobile
telligence
is
is
motor, so an
its
in-
the motor that keeps a star in motion. But unlike
the automobile engine, which must celestial intelligences function as
itself
be
set in
motion, the
motors through being attracted
by the prime mover of the universe.
To
be an
unmoved and
eternal
ingly in motion, the prime
mover of
a universe everlast-
mover must be immutable. But must
be immutable, in
Aristotle's view,
Anything that
material has potentialities:
is
change or motion. actually
We
all
that
it
have seen,
It
is
some
to
also be immaterial.
also imperfect, for at
it
subject to
is
any time
it
is
not
can be. in earlier chapters, that that
completely potential cannot tual in
it
exist.
respects, while
Nothing
which
is
exists that
being potential
purely or is
not ac-
in other respects.
Difficult Philosophical Questions
The
reverse,
however,
is
:
i8y
not true. Pure actuahty (form without
though pure potentiahty (matter without form)
matter) can exist,
cannot.
It is
by such reasoning that Aristotle came to the conclusion
that the prime
mover
is
pure actuality
—
a being totally devoid of
matter or potentiality. In addition, this immaterial being perfect being, a being lacking
This perfect being, which
to attain.
universe, Aristotle called
God,
no perfection
for Aristotle,
The
universe.
is
is
is
a
that remains for
it
the prime
mover of the
God. not the only immaterial being in the
intelligences that keep the stars in their eternal
rounds through being attracted by the perfection of
God
are also
immaterial. But though they, too, are immaterial in Aristotle's
them
theory, he did not regard
Only God It is
as perfect or
not impossible to explain the potentiality that
attributed to the stellar intelligences
actualities.
pure actualities.
that.
difficult if
must be
ality
is
Something
does not
fit
To modern
that
is
ears, Aristotle's
they are not pure
both immaterial and has potenti-
easily into Aristotle's
verse everlastingly in
if
scheme of
things.
account of what keeps the uni-
motion sounds mythical. Yet
ing to follow the reasoning that led
him
it is
interest-
to affirm the existence
of the immaterial and perfect being that he called God. That
reasoning provided a model for later thinkers in their efforts to
—
God not Aristotle's God, but the God of Genesis, the God who created the world out of nothing. The conception of God as Prime Mover and the conception of God as Creator are alike in three respects: the immateriality,
prove the existence of
the immutability, Aristotle's
and the perfection of the Divine Being. But
Prime Mover only serves
the universe
and
its
to
account
everlasting motion.
It
for the eternity of
was the need
to ex-
i88
:
Everybody
Aristotle for
which
plain that
led Aristotle to develop his theory of the
of the heavenly bodies and his concept of the Prime
motion
Mover
as
the final cause of their movements. Aristotle did not think
it
necessary to explain the existence of
the universe. Being eternal, so, in his view,
—
into being
it
never
it
came
into existence,
and
did not need an efficient cause that brought
it
human maker who human being However, the human creator
a cause that operated like a
We
produces a work of art.
who makes something
ordinarily speak of the
as creative.
He
always has the materials of nature to work on.
does not
make something out of nothing. He is, therefore, not creative way that God is thought to be creative. The conception of God as Creator arose from the need
in
the
explain the existence of the universe, as the conception of as
Prime Mover arose
in
Aristotle's
explain the eternity of the universe and is
would have
West had which
It
totle
the need to
everlasting motion.
arisen in the
minds of
God
reads, "In the beginning is
God
created the heavens and the
—Judaism,
West
Christianity,
would be both natural and reasonable
would have accepted or
rejected
to ask
what
is
and Islam.
whether Aris-
asserted by that
sentence. Since he thought the universe to be eternal,
not have denied that the universe had a
who
would he not
created
If to
Cre-
later thinkers in the
regarded as divinely revealed truth by the three
religions of the
ing that,
as
It
not been for the opening sentence of Genesis,
it
earth." This
major
its
determine whether the conception of
difficult to
ator
mind from
to
God
also
would he
beginning? And, deny-
have rejected the notion of a
God
it?
create
is
to
cause something that does not exist to
into existence (comparable to
producing a work of
art),
what the
human
artist
come
does in
then a world that has no beginning
Difficult Philosophical Questions
:
i8g
does not need a creator. But even a world that has no beginning
may need
a cause for
continued existence
its
Something
not necessary. Aristotle's view,
world does not
is
that does
if its
not necessarily
something that may or may not
exist necessarily,
may
then, keeps a world that
it
existence
may
cease to
is
exist,
in
If
the
exist.
exist.
What,
cease to exist everlastingly in exis-
tence? Aristotle did not himself raise or face that question. If
he had,
he might have reasoned his way to the conclusion that a cause
was needed
to
keep the universe everlastingly in existence,
as he did reason his
needed shift in
to
way
to the
conclusion that a
keep the universe everlastingly in motion. By a
the meaning of the word
''creator," the
reached might have led to the conception of
just
cause was slight
conclusion so
God
as Creator,
not just as Prime Mover. In
one sense of the word,
does not exist to
word
(a
more
to
cause something that
into existence. In another sense of the
which may or may not
into existence.
It
is
to cause the ex-
without regard to
exist,
in the latter,
is
more
its
subtle sense of
God
both as
Aristotelian theories described in this chapter
and the
the word
that Aristotle
Prime Mover and
The
is
subtle sense, perhaps), to create
istence of that
coming
come
to create
theory that
I
might have conceived
as Greator.
have suggested he might have developed within the
framework of
his philosophy are not
not even refinements of
common
common
sense,
sense.
They
are
though they may be
based on such refinements. In this very important respect, the theories dealt with in this
chapter differ from the philosophical views in earlier chapters of this book.
The
we have considered
theories dealt with in this
chapter might be regarded as Aristotle's theology, not his philos-
igo
Aristotle for
:
ophy.
If
his
Everybody
theology
is
thought, as his philosophy religious beliefs
—
it
is
at least related to
common
have prevailed in West-
more than two thousand
years.
This
fact
is
reason for thinking that Aristotle's conception of God, and
the reasoning that led this
is,
religious beliefs that
ern civilization for
my
not related to our common-sense
book.
him
to
develop
it,
should be included in
EPILOGUE For Those or
Who Have Read
Who Wish to Read Aristotle
In
my
Introduction to this book,
wished to learn
how
last
Aristotle's
thing
I
anyone who
I
did not
recommend
that
was
anyone
would
tell
anyone
is
to do.
much too difficult for beginners. Even in much of what is said remains obscure. The
books are
the best translations, translators use
do not use
to
by reading the books that Aristotle wrote. That
start
the very
recommended
to think philosophically that Aristotle
the teacher to begin with.
should
I
many words
words that we
that are unfamiliar,
in our everyday speech.
Though some
of the Greek
words that Aristode himself used were words that
his fellow
Greeks used, he gave them special meanings. Nevertheless,
some
readers of this
book may wish
those parts of Aristotle's works from which
I
spiration for this exposition of his thoughts.
that
among
It is
the readers of this book there will be
read the works of Aristotle before
—
if
to read
have drawn the
in-
even possible
some who have
not in their entirety,
at
192
Epilogue
:
least certain of his
major
They may wish
treatises.
exposition against the texts on which
I
have reHed
to check
my
main
for the
tenets of Aristotle's thought.
To fied
for
both groups of readers,
wherever possible. unusual ones.
I
I
must confess
I
that
I
have simpli-
have substituted commonplace words
have kept to the main thrust of
Aristotle's
thought on major points of his doctrine and have never allowed myself to be drawn off the main path by the qualifications, the complications,
and the
that
subtleties
Aristotle
himself in-
troduces, often to the perplexity rather than the enlightenment
of his readers.
To
provide those
who have
read or
who
wish to read Aristotle
with a guide to the texts that have served as
my
drawn up
book, which paral-
lels
a
second table of contents
for this
the table of contents that appears at
second table of contents,
I
have changed
its
all
sources,
I
have
beginning. In this the
titles,
substitut-
ing for the originals (which were appropriate to the style and
substance of that
more
pounded
my
rendition of Aristotle's thought) a set of
titles
precisely describes the Aristotelian doctrines being exin the five parts of this
book and each of
its
twenty-
three chapters.
To make
this clear,
precisely descriptive
contents at
I
have placed
titles,
the twenty-three chapters,
ments,
in
pounded
the
the beginning of
Aristotelian
titles
this I
in brackets, after the
that appear in the table of
book. Under the
will
language,
more
title
of each of
sometimes place brief
state-
of the doctrines being ex-
in that chapter. In every case,
I
will
append
a
references to appropriate portions of Aristotle's works, in
list
of
some
cases indicating the special relevance of a particular portion
being cited.
Epilogue
Part
1.
the Philosophical Animal]
Aristotle s Fourfold Classification of Sensible, Material Substances: In-
organic Bodies, Plants, Animals,
In this chapter
we
Men
Games]
[Philosophical
which
are concerned with the criteria by
tinguished between living and nonliving things; within the ing things, between plants and animals; and within the
between brute animals and rational animals,
life,
Metaphysics, Bk.
I,
Ch.
On
I,
Chs.
the Soul, Bk.
1,
5;
Generation of Animals, Bk. Parts of Animals, Bk.
is
this
I,
Bk.
liv-
domain of animal
human
beings.
I,
II,
Chs. 1-3,
Bk.
5, 9;
Ill,
Chs.
3,
12.
1.
Chs. 1-9; Book IV, Chs. 4-6.
Chs. 4-5.
was aware of
also pointed out that Aristotle
scheme of
i.e.,
Aristotle dis-
domain of
1.
History of Animals, Bk. X, Ch.
It
and His
Aristotle s Universe of Discourse: His Categories
I.
Taxonomy [Man
193
:
classification.
The
difficulties in
difficulties arise
applying
because of the
exis-
tence of borderline cases that straddle the lines that divide the living from the nonliving, and plants from animals.
History of Animals, Bk. VIII, Ch.
The
distinction
between
1.
essential
and accidental
differences
is
in-
troduced.
Categories,
Ch.
5.
Metaphysics, Bk. V, Chs. 4,
2.
11;
Bk. IX, Ch. 8.
The Range of Beings: The Ten Categories [The Creat Divide]
In this chapter exist in the ical objects,
way
we
are
concerned with the being of objects that do not
that sensible, material substances exist (e.g.,
fictions,
mathemat-
minds, ideas, immaterial substances, such as the
disembodied intelligences that are the
celestial
motors, and God).
194
•
Epilogue
Metaphysics, Bk.
On
Chs. 5-6; Bk. XII, Ch.
Ill,
the Heavens, Bk.
On. the
The
Soul, Bk.
II,
Chs.
8;
Chs. 4-6.
Ill,
between substance and accident,
distinction
Bk. XIII, Chs. 1-5.
12.
1,
i.e.,
between bodies and
their attributes.
Categories, Chs. 5-7. Physics, Bk.
I,
Ch.
2.
Metaphysics, Bk. VII, Chs. 4-6.
The
foregoing distinction
related to the point that material substances
is
and
are the subjects of change,
their accidents are the respects in
which
they change.
Physics, Bk.
I,
Chs. 6-7; Bk.
Essence or specific nature
II,
On The
11; Bk. VII,
form.
Ch. 16^ VIII, Ch.
6;
Bk. IX,
8.
the Soul, Bk.
II,
Ch.
4.
hierarchy of specific natures or essences.
Metaphysics, Bk. VIII, Ch.
On
3.
in relation to substantial
Metaphysics, Bk. V, Chs. 4,
Ch.
Ch.
the Soul, Bk.
II,
Aristotle's inventory
Ch.
of the various categories under which the accidental
attributes of substance
Categories,
Among
Ch.
3.
3.
fall.
4.
the accidents of substance,
some
are
permanent
or unchanging;
these are the properties that are inseparable from the essential nature of
each kind of material substance.
Topics, Bk. V, Chs. 1-3.
Epilogue
Aristotle's policy with regard to the
On
Ch.
II,
Productive,
3.
Ch.
Interpretation,
Topics, Bk.
195
:
ambiguity of words.
1.
4.
Practical,
and
Theoretic Reason or
Mind
[Man's Three
Dimensions]
summarizes
This chapter
briefly
tual
or thought into thought for the sake of
activity
thought
for the sake of
Aristotle's threefold division of intellec-
moral and
political action,
sake of acquiring knowledge as an end in
making
things,
and thought
for the
itself.
Ethics, Bk. VI, Chs. 2, 4.
On
Part
11
the Soul, Bk.
Ill,
Ch.
7.
Aristotle s Philosophy of
.
Nature and of Art [Man the
Maker] 4.
Nature as an Artist and the
totle's
The
difference between
Physics, Bk. Poetics,
The
Human
Artist as Imitator of
Nature
[Aris-
Crusoe]
I,
what happens by nature and what happ)ens by
Chs. 7-8; Bk.
II,
art.
Chs. 1-3, 8-9.
Chs. 1-4.
difference
between what happens by
art
and what happens by
chance.
Physics, Bk. Politics,
The
Bk.
II, I,
Chs. 4-6.
Ch.
11.
difference between the changes brought about by nature
changes brought about by
art.
and the
196
;
Epilogue
Metaphysics, Bk. VII, Chs. 7-9.
The
difference between man's production of corporeal things
and the
generation or procreation of Hving things in nature.
Generation of Animals Metaphysics, Bk. VII, Ch.
7.
The Three Main Modes of Accidental Change: Change of Place, Change
5.
of Quality, Change of Quantity [Change and Permanence]
The
between substantial change and accidental change, and
distinction
the differentiation of three distinct
Categories,
Ch.
Physics, Bk.
Ch.
modes of
accidental change.
14.
Ill,
Ch.
1;
Bk. V, Chs.
1-2,
5;
Bk. VII, Ch.
4;
Bk. VIII,
7.
Corporeal substances as the permanent or enduring subjects that
throughout
Physics, Bk.
all
I,
persist
accidental changes.
Chs. 6-7; Bk.
II,
Chs. 1-3.
Metaphysics, Bks. VIII-IX; Bk. XII, Chs. 1-5.
Aristotle's refutation
of the Parmenidean denial of change and of the
Heraclitean denial of permanence.
Physics, Bk.
The
I,
Chs. 2-4, 8-9; Bk. VI, Ch.
Aristotelian distinction
Physics, Bk. IV, Chs.
On
the Heavens, Bk.
The tion:
1, I,
8;
between natural and violent motion.
Bk. V, Ch.
Chs. 2-3,
6;
Bk. VIII, Ch. 4.
^8.
special character of the subject of
prime matter
9.
as the subject of
change
change
in
generation and corrup-
in substantial
change.
Epilogue
Physics, Bk.
I,
Ch.
7;
Bk.
197
:
Chs. 1-3.
II,
Metaphysics, Bk. VII, Chs. 7-9; Bk. XI, Ch. 11; Bk. XII, Chs. 2-3.
Aristotle's
6.
Doctrine of the Four Causes: Efficient, Material, Formal,
and Final [The Four Causes]
The
doctrine stated.
Physics, Bk.
Chs. 3-9.
II,
Metaphysics, Bk. VII, Ch.
The
Chs. 3-10; Bk. V, Ch.
Bk. VI, Chs.
3;
Ch.
17; Bk. VIII, Chs. 2-4; Bk. IX,
consideration of final causes in nature and
Physics, Bk.
On
I,
8;
2-3; Bk.
Bk. XII, Chs. 4-5.
art.
Chs. 8-9.
II,
the Soul, Bk.
Chs. 12-13.
II,
Parts of Animals, Bks. II-IV.
Generation of Animals, Bk.
The
role of potentiality
I,
Chs. 4-13.
and actuality
in
both substantial and accidental
change.
Physics, Bk.
Ill,
Chs. 1-3.
Metaphysics, Bk.
I,
Chs.
^7;
Bk. VII, Chs.
7-17; Bk. VIII, Chs. 4-6;
3,
Bk. XII, Chs. 2-5.
The
role of substance as the material
cause and of accidental form
as the
formal cause in accidental change; and of prime matter as the material cause and substantial form as the formal cause in substantial change.
Physics, Bk.
I,
Chs. 4-9; Bk.
Metaphysics, Bk.
I,
II,
Ch.
7;
Bk.
Chs. 6-7; Bk. V, Ch.
II,
8;
Ch.
3.
Bk. VII, Chs.
3,
7-17; Bk.
VIII, Chs. 4-6; Bk. IX, Chs. 6-9; Bk. XII, Chs. 2-5.
7.
Further Developments in the Theory of Potentiality and Actuality, and
of Matter and Form, Especially with Respect
to
Substantial Change, or
Generation and Corruption [To Be and Not to Be]
Epilogue
198
Physics, Bk.
Ill,
Chs. 1-3.
Metaphysics, Bk. VII, Chs. 6-9; Bk. IX, Chs. Bk. XII, Chs. 2-3,
Generation and Corruptions, Bk.
Aristotle's Analysis
8.
1,
3-9; Bk. XI, Chs. 9, 11;
5. I.
Chs. 1,3-5; Bk.
of the Intellectual Factors
7, 9.
Production
and
Know-How]
Ch.
4.
artist as imitator.
Poetics,
The
1,
intellectual virtue of art.
Ethics, Bk. VI,
The
Chs.
in Artistic
His Classification of the Arts [Productive Ideas and
The
II,
Chs. 1-5.
special character of the three cooperative arts of farming, healing,
and teaching. j
1
Physics, Bk.
II,
Chs. 1-2,
The beauty of products Poetics,
Ch.
8.
that are well
made.
7.
Part HI. Aristotle
s
Moral and
Political Philosophy
[Man
the
Doer]
9.
'
The End as
Means tion
j
the First Principle in Practical Thinking
as the Beginning of Action:
and Last
in
the
The End
Order of Execution
as First in the
as the desirable
Ethics, Bk.
I,
Chs. 1-2.
and the desirable
the
Use of
Order of Inten-
[Thinking about Ends and
Means]
The good
and
as the good.
Epilogue
The
:
igg
for their
own
ultimate end in practical thinking compared with axioms or
self-
between ends and means
distinction
as
goods desirable
sake and goods desirable for the sake of something else.
Ethics, Bk.
The
Chs.
I,
7, 9.
5,
evident truths in theoretical thinking.
Posterior Analytics, Bk.
10.
I,
Ch.
2.
Happiness Conceived as That Whidi Leaves Nothing
End
and, as so Conceived, the Final or Ultimate
to
to
Be Desired
Be Sought
Li\ing
and Living Well
The
distinction
between
Bk.
Chs. 1-2,
Politics,
I.
The conception
living
and
living well.
9.
of happiness as a whole good
Ethics, Bk.
I,
Aristotle's Distinction
11.
^10;
Chs. 4-5,
Goods That Ought
to
together with various
life,
\iews held by indi\iduals concerning what a good
life
consists in.
Bk. X, Chs. 2, 6-8.
Between Real and Apparent Goods, or Between
Be
L>esired
and Goods That Are
in
Fact Desired,
Together with His Distinction Between Satural and Acquired Desires
[Good, Better, Best]
Ethics, Bk.
On
II,
Rhetoric, Bk.
12.
Ch.
the Soul, Bk. I,
6;
II,
Bk.
Ill,
Chs. 4-5; Bk. X, Ch.
Chs. 2-3; Bk.
Ill,
Chs.
Chs. 6-7.
The Real Goods That Are the Components of
Constitute Happiness,
How
of Happiness
Ethics,
Bk.
I,
5.
3, 7.
to
and Moral Virtue
the
Whole of Goods That
as Indispensable to the Pursuit
Pursue Happiness]
Chs. 4-5, 7-10; Bk. VII, Chs. 11-14; Bk. IX, Chs. 4,
8-11; Bk. X, Chs. 1-8.
200
:
13.
Epilogue
Moral Virtue and Good Fortune as
the
Two
Indispensable Operative
Factors in the Pursuit of Happiness [Good Habits and
Moral
virtue
general and the three
in
temperance, courage, and
main
aspects
Good Luck] of moral
virtue:
justice.
Ethics, Bks. II-V.
Good
fortune as indispensable to happiness: the distinction between the
virtuous and the blessed
Ethics, Bk.
Ch.
I,
10; Bk. VII,
Politics, Bk. VII, Chs.
The
man.
1,
Ch.
13; Bk.
X, Ch.
8.
13.
between limited and unlimited goods: moral virtue
distinction
as
resulting in moderation with respect to limited goods.
Ethics, Bk. VII, Politics, Bk.
14.
I,
Ch.
14.
Chs. 8-10; Bk. VII, Ch.
1.
The Obligations of the Individual With Regard
Others and With Regard
[What Others Have
Man
as a social
Politics, Bk.
The
I,
and
to
the Welfare of the
a Right to
political
to
the Happiness of
Organized Community
Expect from Us]
animal.
Chs. 1-2.
family, the tribe, and the state, or political society, as organized
communities.
Politics, Bk.
Justice as
I,
Chs. 1-2.
moral virtue directed toward the good of others.
Ethics, Bk. V, Chs. 1-2.
Epilogue
The
distinction
on the
between
on the one hand, and friendship or
201
love,
other.
Ethics, Bk. VIII, Chs.
The
justice,
:
1, 9.
kinds of friendship.
Ethics, Bk. VIII, Chs. 2-6.
1 5.
The Role of
suit of
the State in Abetting or Facilitating the Individual's Pur-
Happiness [What
from the
Aristotle's
Have
conception of the good
of happiness by
Politics,
We
a Right to
Expect from Others and
State]
Bk.
I,
its
state as
one
promotes the pursuit
that
citizens.
Ch.
2;
Bk.
II,
Ch.
6;
Bk.
Ill,
Chs. (^10; Bk. VII, Chs.
1-3, 13-14.
Aristotle's theory of the
forms of government, and of the
criteria for judg-
ing the goodness and badness of diverse forms of government.
Politics,
Bk.
Chs. 2-3,
I,
Chs.
Aristotle's distinction
Politics, Bk.
1,
8, 12; Bk.
I,
5,
12-13; Bk.
VI, Ch.
4;
between natural and
Chs. 4^7,
Aristotle's
Ch.
I,
Ch.
legal or
conventional slavery.
from
legal or conventional justice.
7.
view of the role of
Politics, Bk.
Chs. 6-7, 11, 15-16; Bk. V,
13.
Aristotle's theory of natural as distinct
Ethics, Bk. V,
Ill,
Bk. VII, Chs. 2, 14.
13.
women
in the family
and the
state.
202
Epilogue
:
Part IV. Aristotle
[Man
The Senses and
16.
and Theory of Knowledge
Psychology, Logic,
s
the Knower] the Intellect: Perception,
Memory, Imagination, and
Conceptual Thought [What Goes into the Mind and What Comes out of
It]
Language
in relation to thought.
Ch.
Categories,
On
1.
Interpretation, Chs. 1-2.
Aristotle's
account of the external senses and of their distinction from the
common
interior senses: the
On
the Soul, Bk.
memory, and imagination.
sense,
Chs. 5-12; Bk.
II,
Chs. 1-3.
Ill,
Sense and the Sensible History of Animals, Bk. IV, Ch.
The
distinction
8.
between mere sensations and perceptual experience.
Metaphysics, Bk.
I,
Ch.
1.
Aristotle's doctrine that sensations
isolation, are neither true
Categories,
On On
Ch.
nor
ideas, taken
by themselves or in
4.
Interpretation, the Soul, Bk.
Ch. II,
1.
Ch.
5;
Aristotle's theory of ideas as
the Soul, Bk.
Ill,
Bk.
6;
Metaphysics, Bk. IV, Ch.
On
and
false.
Chs.
Ill,
Bk. V,
Chs.
Ch.
3, 6.
29.
forms that the intellect abstracts from experi-
4, 7-8.
Metaphysics, Bk. XIII, Chs. 2-3.
17.
Immediate Inference and
Syllogistic
Reasoning [Logic's
Little
Words]
Epilogue
The law
:
203
of contradiction as an ontological principle and as a rule of
thought.
On
Interpretation,
Ch.
Prior Analytics, Bk.
6.
Ch.
II,
Posterior Analytics, Bk.
I,
17.
Ch.
11.
Metaphysics, Bk. IV, Chs. 3-8; Bk. IX, Chs. 5-6.
The
On
square of opposition: contradictories, contraries, and subcontraries.
Interpretation, Chs. 6, 10.
Categories,
Ch.
10.
Prior Analytics, Bk.
Ch.
I,
2.
Immediate inference based on the square of opposition.
On
Interpretation, Chs. 7-10.
Prior Analytics, Bk.
The
I,
Chs. 2-3; Bk.
I.
Posterior Analytics, Bk.
Aristotle's distinction
Prior Analytics, Bk.
The enthymeme
Theoretical
II,
Ch.
II,
II,
12.
logical validity
and
factual truth.
Chs. 2-4. I,
Ch.
in rhetorical
Prior Analytics, Bk.
Rhetoric, Bk.
I,
between
Posterior Analytics, Bk.
The
Chs. 8-10, 22.
rules of the syllogism.
Prior Analytics, Bk.
18.
II,
Ch.
12.
argument.
27.
Chs. 20, 22.
and
Practical Truth [Telling the Truth
definition of truth.
and Thinking
It]
204
•
Epilogue
Metaphysics, Bk. IV, Ch. Categories,
The
Ch.
7.
5.
truth of axioms or
principles: self-evident truths.
first
Posterior Analytics, Bk.
I,
Chs.
Sentences that are neither true nor
On
Ch.
Interpretation,
Aristotle's theory
The
false.
2.
of the difference between the truth of factual and of nor-
mative statements:
Ethics, Bk. VI,
10, 12.
5,
3,
"is- statements"
Ch.
and "ought- statements."
2.
certitude or probability with
which propositions
are affirmed or de-
nied.
On
Ch.
Interpretation,
Prior Analytics, Bk.
9.
Ch.
I,
Posterior Analytics, Bk.
13; Bk. II,
Chs.
I,
Ch.
2, 6, 8,
25.
30, 33.
Metaphysics, Bk. IV, Chs. 4-6; Bk. VI, Ch.
19.
Aristotle's
Ch.
I,
Ch.
Posterior Analytics, Bk. I,
Rhetoric, Bk.
Ch. II,
I,
On
Doubt]
Ch.
Chs.
the Soul, Bk.
13.
Chs.
2,
4-8, 30, 33.
2.
25.
Metaphysics, Bk. IV, Ch. 10; Bk. XI,
a Reasonable
5.
Prior Analytics, Bk.
Topics, Bk.
Bk. IX, Chs. 6-7.
Theory of Knowledge and His Distinction Between Knowledge
and Right Opinion [Beyond Categories,
1;
4;
6, 8.
Ill,
Ch.
3.
Bk. VI,
Ch.
2;
Bk. VII, Ch. 15; Bk. IX, Ch.
Epilogue
Fart V. Aristotle
Cosmology and Theology
s
[Difficult
:
20$
Philo-
sophical Questions] The Actual and
20.
the Potential Infinite [Infinity]
Aristotle's criticism
Physics, Bk.
On
I,
Ch.
of the theory of the atomists.
2.
the Heavens, Bk.
Ch.
Ill,
4; Bk.
IV, Ch.
2.
Aristotle's doctrine with regard to the infinite divisibility of
continuous
magnitudes and of matter.
Physics, Bk.
Ill,
Chs.
1,
6-7; Bk. V, Ch.
Ch.
3;
Bk. VI, Chs. 1-2.
V, Ch. 13.
Metaphysics, Bk.
Ill,
Aristotle's denial
of actually infinite multitudes or magnitudes, together
4; Bk.
with his affirmation of the potential infinites of addition or division.
Physics, Bk.
Ill,
Chs. 4-8.
Metaphysics, Bk. XI, Ch. 10.
21.
The Eternity of the World and of Motion
Aristotle's
conception of time
as the
or
Change
[Eternity]
measure of motion.
Physics, Bk. IV, Chs. 1(^14.
Aristotle's
arguments
for the endlessness of
time and
for the everlast-
ingness of motion or change.
Physics, Bk. VII, Chs. 1-2; Bk. VIII, Chs. 1-6, 8.
Aristotle's theory of the influence of the restrial
On
motion of the heavens upon
motions and changes.
the Heavens, Bk.
I,
Chs.
2,
Generation and Corruption, Bk.
9-12; Bk. II,
II,
Ch.
Chs. 10-11.
3.
ter-
2o6
:
Epilogue
Aristotle's
conception of the immutability or eternity of God: the time-
lessness of the eternal or
immutable.
Metaphysics, Bk. XII, Chs. 6-7,
The Immateriality of
22.
9.
Human
the
volving the Abstraction of
Intellect:
Conceptual Thought as In-
Forms From Matter [The Immateriality of
Mind]
Posterior Analytics, Bk.
On
the Soul, Bk.
Ill,
I,
Ch.
3.
Chs. 4-5, ^8.
Metaphysics, Bk. XIII, Chs. 2-3.
23.
The Prime Mover: The Divine Being
as Pure Actuality [God]
Aristotle's theory of intelligences as celestial motors.
On
the Heavens, Bk.
II,
Chs.
Metaphysics, Bk. XII, Ch.
Aristotle's
arguments
1,
12.
8.
for the existence of a
motion of the heavens
in the
manner of
Physics, Bk. VIII, Chs. 1-6.
Metaphysics, Bk. XII, Chs. 6-9.
prime mover that causes the
a final, not
an
efficient, cause.
MAN
THE PHILOSOPHICAL ANIMAL Philosophical Games The Great Divide Man's Three Dimensions
NO
IDEA IN THIS BOOK IS LESS THAN 2,400 YEARS OLD. MAN
THE MAKER
Aristotle's
Crusoe
Change and Permanence The Four Causes To Be and Not to Be Productive Ideas and Know-How
MAN
THE DOER
Thinking about Ends and Means Living and Living Well
Good,
How
Better, Best to Pursue Happiness
Habits and Good Luck a Right to Expect from Us a Right to Expect from Others and from the State
Good
What Others Have What
We
Have
MAN What Goes
THE
KNOWER
Mind and What Comes out Logic's Little Words
into the
Telling the Truth
Beyond
and Thinking
a Reasonable
of
It
It
Doubt
ALL THE IDEAS IN THIS
BOOK ARE
RELEVANT TO CONTEMPORARY
LIFE
AND THOUGHT DIFFICULT PHILOSOPHICAL QUESTIONS Infinity
Eternity
The Immateriality
of
Mind
God
MACMILLAN PUBLISHING CO., New York, N.Y.
866 Third Avenue,
INC. 10022 PRINTED IN
USA.